ArticlePDF AvailableLiterature Review

The Meaning Maintenance Model: On the Coherence of Social Motivations

Authors:

Abstract

The meaning maintenance model (MMM) proposes that people have a need for meaning; that is, a need to perceive events through a prism of mental representations of expected relations that organizes their perceptions of the world. When people's sense of meaning is threatened, they reaffirm alternative representations as a way to regain meaning-a process termed fluid compensation. According to the model, people can reaffirm meaning in domains that are different from the domain in which the threat occurred. Evidence for fluid compensation can be observed following a variety of psychological threats, including most especially threats to the self, such as self-esteem threats, feelings of uncertainty, interpersonal rejection, and mortality salience. People respond to these diverse threats in highly similar ways, which suggests that a range of psychological motivations are expressions of a singular impulse to generate and maintain a sense of meaning.
The Meaning Maintenance Model:
On the Coherence of Social Motivations
Steven J. Heine
Travis Proulx
Department of Psychology
University of British Columbia
Kathleen D. Vohs
Department of Marketing and Logistics Management
University of Minnesota
The meaning maintenance model (MMM) proposes that people have a need for mean
-
ing; that is, a need to perceive events through a prism of mental representations of ex
-
pected relations that organizes their perceptions of the world. When people’s sense of
meaning is threatened, they reaffirm alternative representations as a way to regain
meaning—a process termed fluid compensation. According to the model, people can
reaffirm meaning in domains that are different from the domain in which the threat oc
-
curred. Evidence for fluid compensation can be observed following a variety of psy
-
chological threats, including most especially threats to the self, such as self-esteem
threats, feelings of uncertainty, interpersonal rejection, and mortality salience. Peo-
ple respond to these diverse threats in highly similar ways, which suggests that a
range of psychological motivations are expressions of a singular impulse to generate
and maintain a sense of meaning.
Nostalgia for unity, that appetite for the absolute
illustrates the essential impulse of the human
drama.
Albert Camus, An Absurd Reasoning
In 1949, Jerome Bruner and Leo Postman published
a study in the Journal of Personality entitled, “On the
perception of incongruity: A paradigm.” According to
Bruner and Postman, people maintain mental represen
-
tations of expected relations, paradigms, that in turn
regulate their perceptions of the world. Consider the
paradigm for playing cards: 52 cards, 4 suits, 2 colors,
and a wide array of associated features that are demar
-
cated into distinct categories. What would happen to
this paradigm if people encountered a card that did not
fit into any of their recognized categories? For exam
-
ple, what would happen if they were confronted with a
black queen of hearts? How would they perceive this
card, and how would this card affect their existing
playing card paradigm?
Bruner and Postman (1949) designed an experiment
to test this very question. In their experiment, most par
-
ticipants began by ignoring the novel relationships
among features, or more precisely, they failed to see
them. Instead, they automatically revised their percep
-
tions of the anomalous cards such that the suits and col
-
ors matched their mental representations of expected
relations (black hearts were seen as red). After re
-
peated presentations, however, most participants grad
-
ually became aware of the anomalous features, and un
-
prompted, began to revise their playing card paradigms
to account for these newly related features. Curiously,
about 10% of participants found themselves trapped in
a kind of paradigm purgatory, whereby they recog
-
nized that the cards with which they were presented
had unexpected features, but they could not articulate
the odd relationships. Consequently, they could not re
-
vise their existing paradigm to accommodate the
changes. Even more curious, these same participants
often experienced acute personal distress, with one
participant exclaiming “I can’t make the suit out what
-
ever it is. It didn’t even look like a card that time. I
don’t know what color it is now or whether it’s a spade
Personality and Social Psychology Review
2006, Vol. 10, No. 2, 88–110
Copyright © 2006 by
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
88
This research was funded by grants from NIMH (R01
MH060155–01A2) and SSHRC (410–2001–0097, 410–2004–0795)
to Steven J. Heine and by support from SSHRC and the Canada Re
-
search Chair Council to Kathleen D. Vohs.
We are especially grateful to Edith Chen, Ian Hansen, Ara
Norenzayan, Mark Schaller, Brandon Schmeichel, Azim Shariff, and
members of the Culture and Self Lab for comments on an earlier
draft.
Correspondence should be sent to Steven J. Heine, Department
of Psychology, 2136 West Mall, University of British Columbia,
Vancouver, BC V6T 1Z4 Canada. E-mail: heine@psych.ubc.ca.
or a heart. I’m not even sure what a spade looks like.
My God!” (p. 213).
If we were to grant that some of Bruner and Post
-
man’s (1949) study participants experienced actual
distress in this situation, one wonders why anyone
should be troubled when presented with a black queen
of hearts. Why care about playing cards? We propose
that the unease experienced by participants in Bruner
and Postman’s study reveals a much broader concern
that underlies a diverse array of human motivations.
This unease reflects a need for meaning.
Western Existentialism
We begin our investigation of a need for meaning by
considering the literature that has most directly ex
-
plored this concept. A number of philosophers, whom
we term the Western existentialists, have argued that a
key element of the human condition is a never-ending
pursuit of meaning. The meaning that is the goal of this
search is a fundamentally relational mode of being.
Kierkegaard (1843/1997, 1848/1997), for example,
wrote extensively on the manner in which the self is ex-
perienced in relation to that which lies outside the self.
He suggested that the self is experienced as “a relation
that relates itself to itself, and in relating itself to itself,
relates itself to another” (p. 351). Heidegger (1953/
1996) expanded on these notions to such an extent that
he would no longer use the word self in any manner,
preferring the expression Da-sein (being there) to ex-
press a being so connected to its environment that any
perceived discrimination was mere illusion. Camus
(1955) would later survey the relational themes of the
existential literature and extract as its central obsession
a universal inclination toward what he termed “the nos
-
talgia for unity:” a belief that all reality comprises a
single, interconnected whole.
Regardless of whether the world is a relational
whole, Camus (1955) suggested that the desire to per
-
ceive reality in such a manner, to both discover and
construct relations represented “the essential impulse
of the human drama” (p. 13). Camus reiterated a line of
existential thought by claiming that all cultural endeav
-
ors—philosophy, science, art, and religion—are mani
-
festations of the universal human need to relate all ele
-
ments of perceived reality into a single, unified,
cohesive framework of expected relationships.
It was Camus’ (1955) contention that, for the West
-
ern existentialists
1
, meaning is relation. Human beings
are meaning-makers, driven to make connections, find
signals in noise, identify patterns, and establish associ
-
ations in places where they may not inherently exist.
People are meaning-makers insofar as they seem com
-
pelled to establish mental representations of expected
relations that tie together elements of their external
world, elements of the self, and most importantly, bind
the self to the external world. When elements of per
-
ceived reality are encountered that do not seem to be
part of people’s existing relational structures, or that
resist relational integration, these inconsistent ele
-
ments provoke a “feeling of the absurd, a disconcert
-
ing sense of fundamental incongruity that motivates
people to re-establish a sense of normalcy and coher
-
ence in their lives.
The Meaning Maintenance Model
At first glance, matters of meaning may seem suffi
-
ciently esoteric and tenuous as to lie outside the pur
-
view of experimental psychology. However, such con
-
cerns are being put to rest by the chorus of voices
across multiple subdisciplines who have taken to
studying meaning-related phenomena. Echoes of
Camus’s nostalgia can be heard in research on sche-
mata (e.g., Markus, 1977), worldviews (Thompson &
Janigan, 1988), assumptive worlds (Janoff-Bulman,
1992), domains of the known (Peterson, 1999), a sense
of coherence (Antonovsky, 1979), unity principles
(Epstein, 1981), and above all, terror management the-
ory (e.g., Pyszczynski, Greenberg, & Solomon, 2004;
Solomon, Greenberg, & Pyszczynski, 1991) and the
new science of experimental existential psychology
(e.g., Greenberg, Koole, & Pyszczynski, 2004). The
commonality among these diverse lines of research is
an attempt to articulate how humans strive to create
and maintain order, certainty, and value in light of chal
-
lenges and abruptions in their endeavours to do so.
We propose an overarching model that parsimoni
-
ously integrates the diverse literatures on mean
-
ing-making, as well as the literatures on self-esteem
maintenance, uncertainty reduction, affiliative mo
-
tives, and terror management theory. We term this
model the meaning maintenance model (MMM), and
use it to make three central claims that are addressed
and developed over the course of this article.
The first of these claims is an expansion of a claim
that has been made by psychologists for decades and
philosophers for centuries (Aristotle, 1987;
Baumeister, 1991; Freud, 1930/1991; Heidegger,
1953/1996; James, 1911/1997; Kierkegaard 1848/
1997): meaning is relation. This is to say, meaning is
what links people, places, objects, and ideas to one an
-
other in expected and predictable ways. Because we
take meaning, relation, and association to be synony
-
mous in this context, we will use these words inter
-
89
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
1
Although we have highlighted here the arguments of the West
-
ern existentialists, we are not proposing that a desire to perceive real
-
ity as a relational whole is peculiar to Western thought. Rather, simi
-
lar arguments are evident in the literatures on Buddhism, Taoism,
and Hinduism, and we submit that a nostalgia for unity is character
-
istic of religious sentiments more generally.
changeably, such that meaning is the expected relation
-
ships or associations that human beings construct and
impose on their worlds. We further propose that there
exists a series of basic realms in which people seek to
discover or apply meaning. People seek coherent rela
-
tions within the external world, within themselves, and
between themselves and the external world. Generally
speaking, the most important relations people seek are
those between the self and the external world, and per
-
ceived breakdowns in their mental representations of
those relationships provoke the strongest efforts to re
-
construct meaningful associations.
The second claim involves humans as meaning
makers. We propose that humans possess an innate ca
-
pacity to identify and construct mental representations
of expected relationships between people, places, ob
-
jects, and ideas. As self-conscious entities, humans
also possess a unique capacity to reflect on these repre
-
sentations and can consequently detect structural
breakdowns and inconsistencies. Humans find it prob
-
lematic to be correspondingly robbed of meaning, or
otherwise confronted with meaninglessness, and there
-
fore seek to reconstruct a sense of meaning whenever
their meaning frameworks are disrupted. The greater
the disruption in their mental representations of ex-
pected relations, the more urgent is the need to regain
meaning.
The third and final claim is the most central to the
MMM, and it is the one on which we focus our review
of the empirical literature: Disruptions to meaning
frameworks lead people to reaffirm alternative frame-
works. Notably, these efforts need not be directed at the
specific domain of meaning that has been jeopardized.
The MMM thus proposes a fluid compensation model
(cf., McGregor, Zanna, Holmes, & Spencer, 2001;
Steele, 1988) whereby people whose meaning frame
-
works have been disrupted react by bolstering or reaf
-
firming other meaning frameworks that remain intact.
Meaning is sought in domains that are most easily re
-
cruited, rather than solely in the domain under threat.
We submit that the foundation of many motivational
phenomena investigated by psychologists is the ability
to construct and assert alternate relational matrices in
the presence of threats to another source of meaning.
Meaning is Relation
More than any other branch of human understand
-
ing, the Western existentialist philosophers of the 19th
and 20th centuries attempted to grasp the structure, ori
-
gin, and importance of people’s relational structures,
focusing on how these structures govern expectations
and shape perceptions of the world, the self, and peo
-
ple’s place within the world. Although these theorists
often used terms like relation or association, the term
most often used was meaning.
In simple terms, meaning is what connects things to
other things in expected ways—anything and any way
that things can be connected. Meaning is what connects
the people, places, and things around oneself: hammers
to nails, cold to snow, mothers to daughters, or dawn to
the rising sun. Meaning connects elements of the self:
thoughts, behaviours, desires, attributes, abilities, roles,
and autobiographical memories. Meaning is what con
-
nects people to that which lies beyond the self: the peo
-
ple, places, and things that surround them. Meaning can
come in as many forms as there are ways to relate these
elements of perception and understanding.
The MMM highlights the considerable array of do
-
mains in which people create meaning frameworks and
engage in fluid compensation in response to threats to
those frameworks. Building on ideas by prominent ex
-
istential theorists (Heidegger, 1953/1996; Kierke
-
gaard, 1843/1997; and Camus, 1955, in particular), as
well as existing models in the psychological literature,
(Janoff-Bulman, 1992; Park & Folkman, 1997;
Thompson-Janigan, 1988) the MMM proposes three
general domains wherein humans seek to achieve sta
-
ble, unified relations. These realms are broadly con-
strued of as the external world, the self, and the self in
relation to the external world. We next explore these
domains in turn.
Elements in the external world consist of the ex-
pected relationships between the people, places, ob-
jects, and events that constitute one’s external environ-
ment, where “expected” is meant to signal an imagined
or assumed reality, as opposed to how the world exists
in actuality. This realm consists of the sum total of be-
liefs about the world. For example, people expect
clocks to go forward, dogs to not speak, snow to be
cold, and the queen of hearts to be red. People strive to
make these propositional frameworks unified and in
-
ternally consistent, which results in efforts to avoid and
reduce contradictions (Heidegger, 1953/1996; Heider,
1958).
The self comprises all beliefs related to oneself,
which is to say the expected relations that unite oneself
both across time (diachronically) and across roles and
contexts (synchronically). People seek to establish that
the person they were 10 years ago is related to the per
-
son they are now, that they are somehow the same per
-
son despite enacting different roles in life, that their at
-
titudes are not in conflict with their freely chosen
behaviours, and that their actions, beliefs, and percep
-
tions about themselves make sense (Chandler,
Lalonde, Sokol, & Hallett, 2003; Festinger, 1957;
Goffman, 1973; Harmon-Jones & Mills, 1999; Ross,
1989). As with elements of the outside world, people
want their self-governing mental representations of ex
-
pected relations to be internally consistent, free of con
-
tradiction, and devoid of dissonance.
The self in relation to the outside world is the con
-
struct most commonly addressed in existential philoso
-
90
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
phy and literature. Put simply, this realm involves a
feeling of personal relation with the people, places, ob
-
jects, and events that constitute elements of the exter
-
nal world. Put even more simply, this construct repre
-
sents a desire to avoid feeling alienated from the
outside world. People seek close and lasting relations
with others, to belong to a community, for others to
view them in ways similar to how they view them
-
selves, and for their actions to have expected and val
-
ued consequences. This realm captures people’s de
-
sires to feel a part of a coherent cultural worldview
(Baumeister & Leary, 1995; Leary, Tambor, Terdal, &
Downs, 1995; Solomon et al., 1991; Swann,
Stein-Seroussi, & Giesler, 1992).
We do not anticipate that the urgency to repair
threats to meaning would be the same for all realms of
meaning. We propose instead that the intensity of the
motivation to compensate for a loss of meaning would
vary as a function of the realm of meaning under at
-
tack. Specifically, we predict that meaning mainte
-
nance efforts are of greater necessity for realms that are
more personally salient. For example, the nonrelation
implied by the eventual ending of one’s own existence
would provoke a more urgent meaning rebuilding re-
sponse (e.g., Pyszczynski et al., 2004) than the
nonrelation implied by the unexpected features of a
deck of altered playing cards, although the response to
the latter may not be trivial (e.g., Bruner & Postman,
1949). There are many elaborate and important rela-
tions between facets of the self, or between the self and
valued elements of the external world. When these
connections are no longer reliable, the individual is in
desperate need of asserting a viable network of ex-
pected relations.
Humans are Meaning Makers
At the core of the MMM is the proposition that hu
-
mans are inexhaustible meaning makers. From birth
onwards, people innately and automatically seek out,
construct, and apply mental representations of ex
-
pected relations to incoming information. Once these
relational structures are in place, events in the world
may be evaluated, either to see what gave rise to them,
or to identify how the events may be relevant to the self
(Asch, 1946; Cantnor & Mischel, 1979; Markus,
1977). The establishment of relational frameworks al
-
lows for many human desires to be met, especially the
drive to predict and control events.
Although determining relational regularities may
serve these and other functions, our innate relational
impulse cannot be reduced to any one of these func
-
tions, anymore than our capacity for vision can be re
-
duced to the need to see potential threats. As it is with
our capacity for vision, our meaning-making capacity
is always “on, and researchers are just beginning to
discover the extent to which even the youngest infants
implicitly determine, and subsequently come to expect
relational regularities of astonishing complexity. Audi
-
tory (Creel, Newport, & Aslin, 2004), and visual rela
-
tions (Fiser & Aslin, 2001) are implicitly determined
and applied, allowing for eventual linguistic associa
-
tions (Saffran, 2001) and causal attributions (Nazzi &
Gopnik, 2002).
Humans are surely not unique in possessing a ca
-
pacity to create and apply mental representations of ex
-
pected relationships. Nonetheless, humans’ status as
the only truly cultural species is accompanied by a reli
-
ance on relational structures that vastly surpasses that
of other species (Tomasello, 1999). Being a cultural
animal means seeing the world and its people as part of
a system that extends far beyond each individual. The
potential arrays of relations that humans have are or
-
ders of magnitude beyond those of their closest evolu
-
tionary relatives (Dunbar, 1993; Tomasello, Kruger, &
Ratner, 1993). Succeeding as a cultural species re
-
quires that people not only attend to and internalize di
-
rect relations among objects in the environment and of
themselves to those objects, but also to relations
among others, relations between others and external
events, and relations between the perceptions that oth-
ers have about those relations, and so on. Humans,
thus, do not just live in physical environments; they
also live in socially constructed environments. In such
environments actions can take on significance at vary-
ing levels far beyond the immediate physical conse-
quences of the actions. For example, the decision by an
individual to attempt to hunt some large game can po-
tentially come to reflect (a) the reciprocation of an ear-
lier received favor; (b) a calculated political move in
which one attempts to show bravery and enhance one’s
relative status; (c) an opportunity to forge and deepen
alliances with one’s fellow tribe members; (d) a chance
to beat out a rival competitor and make them look weak
in the eyes of others; (e) an attempt to demonstrate
one’s prowess to impress a sought after mate; (f) a
chance to obtain a valued good that would afford the
beginning of a trading relation with members of a
nearby tribe; (g) an occasion to obtain a new fashion
accessory or winter coat; (h) an opportunity to boost
the toughness of one’s reputation, and thereby protect
one’s family from future threats; (i) an occasion to
make a gesture of one’s generosity and good will; (j) a
chance to have an exciting story to tell around the
campfire; (k) an opportunity to test whether one’s new
spear is effective; or (l) a way to get a tasty meal; or all
of these. In sum, as a member of a cultural species,
people’s actions come to be draped in many layers of
potential sources of meaning (Bruner, 1990). Actions
are understood in terms of the relational structures
within which they occur.
Fitness as a cultural species is crucially tied to the
capacity to attend to relations among individuals in
one’s groups, particularly when social interactions are
91
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
governed by nepotism and reciprocity, as was likely the
case throughout humans’ ancestral history (Boyd &
Richerson, 1995). The acquisition of cultural skills,
which were clearly crucial to humans’ survival, hinged
on the ability to be aware of the intentions of compatri
-
ots (Dunbar, 1993; Tomasello, 1999). Understanding
the increasing orders of intentionality implicated in
primate’s complex social worlds appears to have been
a strong selective mechanism for primate, and espe
-
cially human, intelligence (Dunbar, 1992; Humphrey,
1976). Hence, it was adaptive for humans to recognize
and comprehend complex orders of relations within
their worlds.
We propose that this associative impulse is an
evolutionarily adaptive trait that occupies a primary
position in humans’ motivational ontology. Support for
this notion has emerged from the discipline of cultural
psychology. Cultural psychology maintains that hu
-
mans are meaning makers whose experiences are fun
-
damentally grounded in, and consequently supported
by, cultural meaning frameworks (for discussions on
this matter see Bruner, 1990; Shweder, 1990). The im
-
pulse to seek out relations we assume to be a psycho
-
logical universal (an accessibility universal;
Norenzayan & Heine, 2005), however, the specific
kinds of mental representations that people will con-
struct may vary considerably across cultures.
Fluid Compensation
as Meaning Maintenance
Although people depend heavily on relational ma-
trices, reality bombards them with events, behaviours,
ideas, and experiences that cannot easily be integrated
into existing paradigms. Moreover, an awareness of
conflicting events implies that existing relational struc
-
tures are inaccurate, inadequate, or nonexistent (Kuhn,
1962/1996; Piaget, 1960). That people rely so heavily
on relational structures to understand events in their
lives indicates that breakdowns of these structures are
highly problematic. Humans’ needs for stable rela
-
tional frameworks requires that they respond to actual
or potential tears in a meaning framework with at
-
tempts to rebuild other frameworks or to assert new
frameworks altogether.
In his influential book, The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions, Thomas Kuhn (1962/1996) proposed two
general responses to the awareness of an anomaly, de
-
fined as something unrelated or unrelatable to an exist
-
ing paradigm. The first of these responses is to revise
one’s system of relations such that it can accommodate
the anomaly. The second, and generally assumed to be
more common response, is to reinterpret the anomaly
in such a way that it ceases to be an anomaly, and in
-
stead now relates to one’s existing relational structures.
Other models of meaning maintenance have described
how people respond to ruptures in their mental repre
-
sentations of expected relations. For the most part,
these models propose strategies that are variants of the
revise and reinterpret strategies proposed by Kuhn
(1962/1996). For example, Piaget (1960) proposed that
children learn their schemata through interactions with
the world, which requires either assimilating new in
-
formation into an existing schema, or accommodating
their schemata to incorporate new information.
Janoff-Bulman (1992) construed meaning as “assump
-
tive worlds, which are “stable, unified conceptual sys
-
tem(s),” “a network of diverse theories and representa
-
tions,” and “strongly held set of assumptions about the
world and the self” (p. 5). When these assumptive
worlds are presented with an anomaly, the person is
forced to either revise the assumptive world or, more
commonly, reinterpret the anomalous event such that it
conforms to the existing assumptive world. In another
model, Park and Folkman (1997) describe “global
meaning” as “people’s basic and fundamental assump
-
tions, beliefs and expectations about the world…, be
-
liefs about the world, beliefs about the self, beliefs
about the self in the world” (p. 116). In addition, Park
and Folkman proposed the existence of “situational
meaning, which is the determination of how similar
one’s existing meaning frameworks are to those rela-
tions they perceive in reality. If there is a perceived dis-
crepancy between global and situational meaning, the
person is forced to either revise global meaning to ac-
count for the situational meaning, or reinterpret situa-
tional meaning to eliminate the discrepancy. In yet an-
other model, Thompson and Janigan (1988) described
a process of assimilating anomalies whereby “found
meaning, which represents one’s existing meaning
frameworks, can be revised to account for discrepan
-
cies between it and “implicit meaning, which repre
-
sents one’s appraisal of the real world.
We do not question that some variant of the two
Kuhnian processes of revising or reinterpreting often
take place in reaction to challenges to people’s mean
-
ing frameworks. However, the foundational premise of
the MMM is that there exists a third, complementary
route by which people can restore meaning following
disruption. This has not been articulated by other theo
-
ries. That is, following threats to meaning people will
reaffirm an alternative network of relations. If people
perceive an element of self or of their worlds that does
not find a place in their existing frameworks, they may
react by adhering more strongly to other relational
structures, even if these structures are unrelated to the
expected relationships that are under attack. In other
words, instead of responding to a relational anomaly
by reinterpreting it or revising their existing relations,
people may respond by reaffirming other relational
structures so as to compensate for damage done to the
framework undermined by the anomaly. This reaffir
-
mation we term fluid compensation (cf., McGregor et
al., 2001; Steele, 1988). The process is fluid insofar as
92
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
it does not require that a particular relational frame
-
work be asserted, but rather that any alternative frame
-
work of associations that is intact, coherent, compel
-
ling, and readily available can be affirmed to
compensate for a loss of meaning.
We further hypothesize that compensatory re
-
sponses can occur both within and across the three
realms of meaning; if the system of expected relations
that govern perceptions of the outside world is compro
-
mised, one may respond by bolstering other relational
systems governing the outside world, or by bolstering
the relations that pertain to the self, or the relations of
the external world to the self. For example, encounter
-
ing information that signifies one’s own mortality pro
-
vides a threat to the relations between the self and the
external world. In response to such a threat, people
may see patterns within noise (and thereby identify
new relations among events in the external world;
Dechesne & Wigboldus, 2001), enhance the value of
their ingroup (thereby creating relations between one
-
self and a desirable group; Greenberg, Porteus, Simon,
Pyszczynski, & Solomon, 1995), or desire high status
products (thereby creating desirable associations be
-
tween oneself and the external world; Mandel &
Heine, 1999). We argue that any of these responses
serve to compensate for the meaning disruptions by as-
serting an alternative meaning framework. Note, that in
reality none of these compensatory efforts actually di-
minish the threat posed by the initial disruption (in our
example, the threat of one’s own morality). Rather they
allow the individual to focus attention on another
framework that does not suffer from a perceived
anomaly.
Satiability, Substitutability and
Evidence for Similar Function
One hallmark of motivations is that they are obvi
-
ated or attenuated when sated (e.g., Baumeister &
Leary, 1995). For example, the need for meaning
would no longer drive behaviour when a person tempo
-
rarily perceives that his or her actions are supported by
an expected pattern of relations. In this way, the moti
-
vation is primarily evident when its goal (a viable
meaning framework, in this case) is potentially out of
reach, in the same way that people are mainly aware of
hunger motivations when their stomachs are empty.
The less reliable the present meaning framework, the
stronger and more urgent is the motivation to assert an
-
other more reliable matrix. In this way, people’s reli
-
ance on relational frameworks can be considered to be
a need.
A related proposition from the satiation feature of
motivations is substitutability (Baumeister & Leary,
1995). The same underlying drive can be satisfied by a
variety of alternatives to the extent that the alternatives
share a common function. Lewin (1935) and his stu
-
dent Ovsiankina (1928) proposed that if one action can
be substituted for another we can conclude that these
actions serve a common purpose, or have equifinality
(also see Shah, Kruglanski, & Friedman, 2003; Tesser,
Crepaz, Beach, Cornell, & Collins, 2000). For exam
-
ple, an individual’s hunger can be sated either by con
-
suming bread or fish. This substitutability suggests that
humans do not have specific motivations to consume
bread or fish per se; rather they have motivations to
consume food more generally. That bread can be sub
-
stituted for fish highlights the need to turn from a more
specific category (i.e., bread) to a more inclusive cate
-
gory (i.e., food) to understand the goal of hunger moti
-
vations. Substitutability between domains suggests a
common function. We submit that the satiability and
substitutability of various psychological motivations
indicates a common function: a need to maintain a co
-
herent framework of meaning.
Evidence for Fluid Compensation
of Meaning Maintenance
At the heart of the MMM is the proposition that
when people experience a disruption to meaning
frameworks they attempt to reconstruct meaning
through other relational structures that are available
and intact. Because this compensation is proposed to
be fluid, evidence for meaning construction efforts is
anticipated not only in the same domain as the original
threat, but also in domains far removed from the source
of the threat (although we submit that the first line of
defense to a meaning threat would be to try to respond
to the threat directly, and only affirm alternative mean-
ing frameworks if the present one is damaged beyond
repair; e.g., Stone, Wiegand, Cooper, & Aronson,
1997). We first discuss the evidence for fluid compen
-
sation within domains and then review evidence for
fluid compensation between domains.
Evidence for Fluid Compensation
Within Domains
We now consider research programs that have in
-
vestigated compensatory responses within domains.
We summarize evidence from four domains that are
most relevant to people’s drive to maintain meaning;
needs for self-esteem, certainty, belongingness, and
symbolic immortality. The MMM proposes new ways
of understanding the findings within these four
domains.
Self-esteem needs. Self-esteem is the construct
perhaps most closely tied to people’s perceptions of
meaning in their lives. Self-esteem has been viewed as
an indicator of people’s success at relating to their ex
-
ternal worlds (Crocker & Park, 2004; Leary et al.,
1995; Mischel & Morf, 2003), and, accordingly, how
93
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
much meaning they can derive from their lives. The
MMM proposes that people pursue self-esteem be
-
cause it facilitates the maintenance of a viable frame
-
work of meaning, particularly within individualistic
societies where the relative independence of people
renders other relational frameworks less potent (Heine,
2005; Heine, Lehman, Markus, & Kitayama, 1999).
Much empirical research in this area has investi
-
gated people’s responses to threats to their self-esteem
and their attendant efforts to restore it (e.g., Baumeister
& Jones, 1978; Cialdini et al., 1976; Leary et al., 1995).
Efforts to build self-esteem appear to be most evident
when an individual’s self-esteem is vulnerable or has
been threatened. At some point, however, people stop
trying to increase or restore their self-esteem, a pattern
akin to that seen for other basic motivations, and a pat
-
tern that suggests that a need for self-esteem can be
sated. People’s pursuits of self-esteem are largely
halted when they encounter an opportunity to reflect
on positive aspects of their lives (Cialdini et al., 1976;
Steele, Spencer, & Lynch, 1993). In contrast, the pur
-
suit of self-esteem is stimulated when people encoun
-
ter a threat to a positive view of self. In general, then,
we can conclude that people do not endeavour to maxi-
mize their self-esteem. Instead they strive to ensure
that their self-esteem reaches or exceeds some thresh-
old, and consequently self-esteem maintenance efforts
are engaged when people perceive that their personal
evaluations fall short of that threshold. The satiability
of self-esteem motivations supports the claim that they
represent a valid need (Baumeister & Leary, 1995).
Efforts to maintain self-esteem are not limited to a
specific process such as favorable social comparisons
or self-serving attributional biases; rather, there is
much evidence for fluid compensation to counter
self-esteem threats across multiple strategies. For ex
-
ample, Baumeister and Jones (1978) found that after
participants received negative feedback about certain
aspects of their personality they came to view other un
-
related aspects of their personality more positively rel
-
ative to participants who had not received negative
feedback. Cialdini and colleagues (1976) illustrated
that after college students failed a trivia test they were
more motivated to affiliate themselves with their
school’s football team after team victories but dis
-
tanced themselves after team losses. Hence, these lines
of research demonstrate that compensatory boosts to
self-esteem can be achieved when people take advan
-
tage of circumstances unrelated to the initial threat.
Thus, different self-esteem maintenance strategies ap
-
pear to be interchangeable.
The most explicit formulation of fluid compensa
-
tion in the self-esteem domain has been developed by
Tesser and colleagues in their self-evaluation mainte
-
nance model (Tesser, 2000, 2001; Tesser & Cornell,
1991; Tesser, Crepas, Beach, Cornell, & Collins,
2000). Building on the domain-general mechanism
identified by Steele and colleagues in their work on
self-affirmation (Steele, 1988; Steele & Liu, 1983;
Steele et al., 1993), Tesser and colleagues have pro
-
vided evidence for at least three substitutable processes
serving self-esteem maintenance efforts. Specifically,
Tesser and colleagues showed that a threat to the self
by way of negative social comparisons or cognitive
dissonance could be offset by self-affirmations of
one’s values, dissonance reduction, or positive social
comparisons. That is, the dissonance experienced
when one has made a “close-call” decision can be
eliminated by affirming one’s values (such as by wear
-
ing a coveted lab coat; Steele & Liu, 1983), receiving
favorable personality feedback (e.g., Heine & Lehman,
1997), or focusing on a positive social comparison sit
-
uation (Tesser & Cornell, 1991). Tesser and colleagues
also showed that social comparison processes can be
reversed when people affirm their values (Tesser &
Cornell, 1991) or are exacerbated when they write a
counter-attitudinal essay that elicits dissonance (Tesser
et al., 2000). Likewise, it has been shown that people
affirm their values more after they have been induced
to make negative social comparisons or have written a
counter-attitudinal essay (Tesser et al., 2000).
These highly divergent phenomena are substitut-
able because the engagement in one decreases the en-
gagement in the other (Tesser, 2000). The hydraulic
nature of these phenomena suggests that the different
processes are in service of the same underlying goal.
The processes previously reviewed are not enacted as
ends in themselves (i.e., the goal is not to make a down-
ward social comparison per se), but are means to a
higher end. Tesser (2000) proposed that this higher end
is the maintenance of self-esteem. The goal of main
-
taining high self-esteem transcends the more proximal
goals of engaging in downward social comparison or in
affirming one’s values because the myriad strategies
for maintaining self-esteem are substitutable
themselves.
Of course, describing people’s behaviors in the pre
-
viously discussed experiments as servicing a need for
self-esteem invites the question of why such a need ex
-
ists. This question has led to some rather diverse ac
-
counts of the functionality of the self-esteem motive.
For example, Barkow (1989) proposed that self-esteem
was selected to serve as a gauge of subtle changes of
the individual’s status within dominance hierarchies.
Leary and colleagues (Leary & Baumeister, 2000;
Leary et al., 1995) argued that self-esteem is an adapta
-
tion that functions as an indicator to detect when peo
-
ple’s social relationships and stability within valued
groups were vulnerable. Terror management theory
(e.g., Pyszczynski et al., 2004) has maintained that
self-esteem emerged as an adaptation to stave off the
debilitating existential anxieties that come from peo
-
ple’s fears of their own mortality. Heine and colleagues
(Heine, 2003; Heine et al., 1999) have argued that
94
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
self-esteem is derived from desires to actualize individ
-
ualistic cultural goals of being unique, self-sufficient,
in control of one’s personal fate, and distinct from oth
-
ers. These are diverse explanations and taking each on
its own, it is difficult to adequately account for data
collected in the competing paradigms.
The MMM provides another perspective by which
to understand the debate regarding the self-esteem mo
-
tive. The MMM does not dispute that people are often
motivated to secure self-esteem, but rather proposes
that self-esteem maintenance is itself in service of the
overarching goal of meaning maintenance. That is,
self-esteem is a means to the end of maintaining a via
-
ble relational framework, rather than being an end in it
-
self. Looking across the different depictions of the
function of self-esteem, it emerges that threats to
self-esteem signal that people are failing to function
-
ally relate to their external worlds. The MMM can also
address why the self-esteem motive appears stronger in
individualistic than in collectivistic cultures (Heine et
al., 1999). Within individualistic cultures, much mean
-
ing may be derived by viewing oneself as competent
and in control, given that these cultures encourage peo
-
ple to view themselves as the primary source of agency
(in contrast with some other cultures, in which agency
and control are often achieved more by adjusting one-
self to the desires of the collective; Markus &
Kitayama, 1991; Morling, Kitayama, & Miyamoto,
2002; Triandis, 1989). In sum, at least within individu-
alistic cultures, high self-esteem is an important means
to maintain a coherent relational structure.
Certainty needs. Many research paradigms in
social psychology have explored people’s motivations
to feel certain about their understanding of the world.
That is, it has been proposed that people have a funda
-
mental motivation to believe that their perceptions, at
-
titudes, and behaviors are correct (e.g., Festinger,
1957; Fromm, 1947). Related motivations have been
described as a need to know (Rokeach, 1960), a need
for cognition (Cacioppo & Petty, 1982), a need for
structure (Neuberg & Newsom, 1993), and a need for
cognitive closure (Kruglanski & Webster, 1996). The
commonality among these programs is the proposition
that people have a fundamental need to feel accurate in
their understanding of how the world operates.
Similar to other human needs, the desire for cer
-
tainty can be sated. People are most likely to pursue
certainty when they are made to feel uncertain
(Festinger, 1957). In contrast, when people are led to
feel reasonably certain, they are less likely to engage in
efforts to increase cognitive certainty (e.g., I.
McGregor et al., 2001). In this way, people do not usu
-
ally aspire to maximize certainty, except in specific sit
-
uations with highly important outcomes (Petty,
Cacioppo, & Goldman, 1981).
Moreover, research indicates that people’s needs for
certainty are substitutable. That is, a lack of certainty in
one domain can be compensated by increased certainty
in another. Research by I. McGregor and colleagues on
compensatory conviction underscores the hydraulic na
-
ture of certainty motivations. I. McGregor and col
-
leagues (2001) found that when participants were made
aware of an inconsistency in their lives they responded
by becoming more rigid in their beliefs about unrelated
topics. Thus, people compensated for a lack of certainty
in one domain by creating a sense of certainty in another
(also see I. McGregor & Marigold, 2003).
Empirical evidence surrounding a cognitive need
for closure also underscores the domain-general nature
of a motivation for certainty. People who are chroni
-
cally high in the need for nonspecific closure, or people
for whom a high need for closure has been induced, en
-
gage in a variety of tactics to re-establish a sense of cer
-
tainty (for reviews see Kruglanski & Webster, 1996;
Webster & Kruglanski, 1998). For example,
Kruglanski and Webster (1991) found that experimen
-
tally elevating a need for nonspecific closure (by creat
-
ing a sense of time-pressure and introducing ambient
noise) resulted in participants rejecting someone who
possessed an opinion different from the participants’
group (also see Kruglanski & Freund, 1983). Likewise,
research by Doherty (1998) found that people reacted
to a woman who deviated from cultural norms more
negatively if they had been encouraged to reach cogni-
tive closure.
Motivations for certainty also underlie a tendency to
rely on stereotypes. Because stereotypes allow people
to perceive the world in a more orderly manner, it fol-
lows that they should be relied upon more heavily by
those who feel a more urgent need to achieve closure.
In support of this notion, Dijksterhuis, van
Knippenberg, Kruglanski, and Schaper (1996) found
that people who were chronically high in need for clo
-
sure as well as people for whom a need for closure was
induced exhibited more stereotypically-biased memo
-
ries of social events.
Similar to the substitutability that has been identi
-
fied among the self-esteem maintenance strategies,
people are able to bolster a sense of certainty through a
broad array of tactics, some of which are far removed
from the initial source of uncertainty. It is thus inaccu
-
rate to claim that people only have needs to feel certain
about particular beliefs, such as a belief that one’s solu
-
tion to Task A is correct; rather, they appear to have
more general needs to feel certain about something. In
parallel to the fluidity of self-esteem maintenance
strategies, we can also conclude that feelings of cer
-
tainty in one domain can diminish efforts to achieve
certainty in another domain. Thus, certainty strategies
are interchangeable.
Certainty is one’s sense that the mental representa
-
tions of expected relationships that one has generated
95
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
are internally consistent, fit with their perceptions, and
meet many of the other needs that allow one to satisfy,
most notably, the desire for predictability and control
in their lives. The social world can be enormously
complex, and people wish to impose a sense of order to
this world: They seek to predict and control their envi
-
ronments based on mental representations of expected
associations that account for cause and effect relations,
as well as teleological relations that are formed when
they perceive their actions as directed towards a
higher-level purpose (Vallacher & Wegner, 1987).
Feelings of subjective certainty with regards to these
meaning frameworks provides people with confidence
regarding how they should behave, and an understand
-
ing of what they should expect from their environments
when they do (or do not) behave accordingly. In accor
-
dance with the MMM, certainty is the sense that one
has generated a reliable framework of relations be
-
tween themselves and their worlds (Bartlett, 1932;
Hogg, 2001). Through meaning, people believe that
they understand the operations of their world and their
place with in it, and are subsequently able to derive a
sense of certainty from these relations.
Affiliative needs. Humans are fundamentally a
social species, and our sociality has surely played a
role in the kinds of traits and attributes that were se-
lected for in the ancestral environment (Dunbar, 1992;
Tomasello et al., 1993). As a social species, human fit-
ness is enhanced with the maintenance of successful
relationships with others. When deprived of smoothly
functioning relationships, people suffer from a variety
of negative consequences, including an increased risk
for mental illness (e.g., Bloom, White, & Asher, 1979),
more deleterious responses to stressful life events (e.g.,
Delongis, Folkman, & Lazarus, 1988), and, overall, an
abbreviated lifespan (e.g., Goodwin, Hunt, Key, &
Sarnet, 1987; House, Landis, & Umberson, 1988).
Maintaining successful relations with others is a core
human need (Baumeister & Leary, 1995).
The need to belong is evident not only in people’s
desires to form relationships with others. This need
also manifests itself in people’s desires to belong to a
cohesive social unit that can be contrasted against
groups to which they do not belong. In a series of ele
-
gant studies Tajfel (Tajfel, 1970; Tajfel, Billig, Bundy,
& Flament, 1971) discovered a remarkable finding.
People appeared motivated to carve up an array of
strangers into “us” and “them,” even when the basis of
this categorization was unapparent, or when the indi
-
viduals stood to gain nothing personally. Tajfel’s in
-
triguing studies suggest that people possess a tribal im
-
pulse, which drives them into imagined enclaves of
similar others. People are not content to think about
themselves and others merely as individuals; in con
-
trast, people actively wish to assign themselves and
others to social clusters.
Similar to needs for self-esteem and certainty, there
appears to be both a satiability and a substitutability in
-
herent in our need for belongingness (Baumeister &
Leary, 1995). People do not strive to maximize their
sense of belongingness with others. Rather, people’s
motivation to pursue new relationships drops when
they have a number of close relationships relative to
times in which they are less connected (e.g., Reis,
1990). The drive for affiliation is spurred by depriva
-
tion and is weakened by achieving connection with
others. Moreover, there appears to be a limit regarding
the number of social relationships that an individual
can maintain, and once the limit is reached, the need to
develop further relationships is rendered weaker
(Audy, 1980; Dunbar, 1997). In general, people are
more motivated to establish and deepen their relation
-
ships when their affiliative needs are not sated.
Although each relationship is in some ways unique,
relationships also appear to serve a shared function.
People can achieve some of their belongingness needs
by replacing one relationship with another. For exam
-
ple, Milardo, Johnson, and Huston (1983) demon
-
strated that as people develop new intimate relation
-
ships they concomitantly spend less time with existing
relationships. Apparently, the needs that are satisfied
from the new intimate relationships reduces the utility
derived from interacting with pre-established relation-
ships. Similarly, Vaughan (1986) noted that as bad
marriages begin to dissolve, people preemptively seek
out new relationship partners. Furthermore, this same
research found that people who are unhappy in their
marriages often choose to have children, presumably
in an attempt to compensate for their weakened feel-
ings of belongingness. When one’s belongingness
needs are no longer adequately satisfied in one rela
-
tionship, the urgency to find new relationships in
-
creases. Likewise, Bowlby (1969) observed that chil
-
dren’s distress about being separated from their
mothers was reduced significantly if a familiar person
was nearby. Stated otherwise, children do not have a
need only to stay close to their mother, they also have a
need to stay close to someone whom they already
know. In sum, human needs to affiliate with others and
to achieve belongingness are not directed solely at spe
-
cific relationships. To a certain extent, belongingness
needs to belong are substitutable, such that people can
satisfy their broader belongingness needs by maintain
-
ing successful relationships with someone.
The MMM agrees that people have pronounced
belongingness needs that serve a variety of important
functions. The current model goes beyond existing ex
-
planations of belongingness functions by proposing
that one crucial purpose of having interpersonal rela
-
tionships is that they provide people with a general
sense of interrelation—a sense of meaning. Meaning
frameworks derived through close relationships pro
-
vide people with the sense that their opinions are
96
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
shared and are thus more likely to be correct (Hogg,
2003), suggest that people’s experiences are normal
(Pinel, Long, Landau, & Pyszczynski, 2004), provide
people with feelings of self-worth (e.g., Cialdini et al.,
1976), help to make sense of and cope with traumatic
experiences (Lehman, Ellard, & Wortman, 1986), and
provide relevant standards by which people can assess
their performance (Festinger, 1954). Meaning as inter
-
personal relationships allow people to gauge how well
they are functioning and provide them with a sense that
they can predict and control their worlds. Disruption of
interpersonal relationships and social categories is dis
-
ruption of human’s sense of meaning. We propose that
such disruptions motivate people to reaffirm alterna
-
tive relational structures.
Symbolic immortality needs. Borrowing from
a number of existential theorists including Becker
(1973), Freud (1930/1991), Lifton (1976), and Rank
(1941), terror management theory (TMT; Pyszczynski,
Greenberg, & Solomon, 1997; Pyszczynski et al.,
2004; Solomon et al., 1991) proposes that many human
motivations hinge on the existential anxiety associated
with people’s thoughts about their inevitable demise.
The theory stems from the observation that a primary
goal for all species is self-preservation, yet humans,
having the cognitive capabilities to comprehend that
their death is imminent, are inescapably aware that
they will fail at this central goal. A consideration of the
ultimate futility of one’s efforts to preserve his or her
existence is proposed to engender a great sense of exis-
tential anxiety or “terror. TMT proposes that people
aspire for symbolic immortality to protect them from
this anxiety that arises from the awareness that they do
not have literal immortality. Symbolic immortality is
posited to be achieved via a dual anxiety buffer, which
consists of a structure (i.e., the individual’s cultural
worldview), and the individual’s association with that
structure (i.e., his or her ability to live up to the stan
-
dards determined by his or her cultural worldview;
Pyszczynski, Greenberg, & Solomon, 1999). The cul
-
tural worldview is a constructed conception of reality
that provides the individual with a sense of order, sta
-
bility, and predictability. Within this worldview is a
consensually shared set of standards that mandate what
kinds of actions or thoughts are of value. By living up
to the standards that are inherent in the cultural
worldview, people are able to derive a sense of value
from their cultures.
TMT maintains that when people are confronted
with thoughts of their mortality, they combat the anxi
-
ety by bolstering either of the dual components of the
cultural anxiety buffer. One strategy is to reaffirm the
connections of one’s cultural worldview, thereby in
-
creasing faith in its validity and potential endurance.
For example, one can become critical towards people
who act in ways that are inconsistent with their cultural
worldview (e.g., Rosenblatt, Greenberg, Solomon,
Pyszczynski, & Lyon, 1989). Following from this
strategy, another strategy is to reaffirm one’s connec
-
tion to their cultural worldview by reflecting or em
-
bodying cultural values. In so doing, people may
achieve symbolic immortality insofar as they are con
-
nected to that which will endure after they are dead.
For example, one can desire possessions that convey
that one has the trappings of success in their culture
(e.g., Mandel & Heine, 1999).
Although TMT has its detractors (e.g., Leary, 2004;
Muraven & Baumeister, 1997; Paulhus & Trapnell,
1997), over the past decade and a half a number of re
-
searchers have conducted at least 175 experiments that
have provided striking support for a number of diverse
predictions from the model (for a review see
Pyszczynski et al., 2004). Studies that have been con
-
ducted to test TMT typically share the same straight
-
forward methodology: Participants in a control condi
-
tion are contrasted with those who have been reminded
of their mortality, which is operationalised through a
variety of different mortality salience primes. Subse
-
quently, various measures of worldview defense or
self-enhancement are contrasted across conditions fol-
lowing a brief delay. For example, threats to one’s
meaning frameworks via mortality salience have been
shown to lead to such compensatory responses as prej-
udice against outgroups (e.g., I. McGregor et al.,
2001), maintenance of cultural norms (Rosenblatt et
al., 1989), protection of cultural icons (Greenberg et
al., 1995), supernatural beliefs (Norenzayan &
Hansen, 2005), and a preference for George W. Bush
over John Kerry (Landau, Miller, et al., 2004), to name
a few. TMT currently stands as one of the most fecund
theories in psychology, and there are few motivational
phenomena that have not yet been linked with it in
some way. Furthermore, at least some of the findings
have been found to generalize well across divergent
cultural groups (e.g., Halloran & Kashima, 2004;
Heine, Harihara, & Niiya, 2002). Importantly for this
article, TMT findings lucidly demonstrate how broadly
fluid compensation processes can operate. Threats to
one’s meaning framework via mortality salience can be
compensated by aspiring for symbolic immortality via
a highly diverse array of responses, all of which in
-
volve reaffirming the connections within our cultural
worldviews, and reaffirming our connection to these
worldviews.
The desire for symbolic immortality also displays
the hallmarks of a satiable and substitutable motiva
-
tion. People do not strive to maximize their feelings of
immortality, that is, they do not continually reinforce
their dual anxiety buffer once their thoughts of their
mortality are no longer available (Pyszczynski et al.,
1999). Likewise, concerns with literal mortality can be
compensated by beliefs in symbolic immortality, via
the activation of either component of the dual anxiety
97
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
buffer, a finding that underscores the substitutability of
these motivations.
The MMM predicts similar findings that TMT stud
-
ies have reported but for different reasons. Rather than
viewing these effects as being reducible to the desire to
avoid the terror associated with the awareness of our
own mortality, the MMM proposes that humans seek to
preserve a viable framework of expected relations,
which may in turn be applied to the task of providing
symbolic immortality. Any disruption to one’s frame
-
work, particularly with respect to one’s relations with
the external world, creates a sense of urgency to repair
that fissure ortoconstruct another relational framework.
The MMM views an awareness of one’s imminent death
as one of many such disruptions of people’s associative
webs. The MMM hypothesizes that this attempt to af
-
firm an alternative meaning framework follows the
same course (including the same critical temporal de
-
lays; Pyszczynski et al., 1999) as that identified in ma
-
nipulations of mortality salience in TMT studies.
How might death be disruptive to one’s sense of
meaning? In his book entitled Meanings of Life (1991),
Baumeister devotes one chapter to the integral role of
meaning loss in death. In it, he maintains that death
threatens meaning (which he also defines as relation)
in four particular ways: (a) death undermines the pre-
dictability and controllability of one’s existence, (b)
death eliminates all potential that one has for earning
meaning in the future, (c) death reminds people that
their existence and the meaning framework that they
have constructed will likely be forgotten, and (d) death
nullifies the value of one’s life’s achievements. The
Western existentialists, Kierkegaard (1848/1997),
Camus (1955), Heidegger (1953/1996), and Sartre
(1957), stressed the relative psychological primacy of
humans’ fear of death. Yet, similar to the MMM, these
theorists were also careful to point out that the desire to
avoid an awareness of one’s own mortality partially, if
not completely, reduces to the desire to avoid mortal
-
ity’s assault on meaning frameworks. Following from
this line of thought, the MMM asserts that people do
not construct meaning frameworks mainly to assuage
their anxieties about death. Rather, people primarily
have anxieties about death because death renders life
meaningless by severing individuals from their exter
-
nal environment, and in a sense, from themselves. In
-
sofar as people are impelled to construct meaning in
the face of death, it is only to cover up the “gaps and
fissures” (Heidegger, 1953/1996) that the awareness of
death tears into the connective fabric of their meaning,
where death is not the only event that can produce such
tears. Nonetheless, in the current model, we submit
that death and meaning loss are inextricably interwo
-
ven (also see Dechesne & Kruglanski, 2004; Lifton,
1976).
In sum, according to the MMM, death is but one of
many events that stands to threaten people’s meaning
frameworks. It is perhaps the strongest or most potent
of the meaning threats that humans encounter, but re
-
sponses to it can be predicted using the same MMM
framework as can be used to predict fluid compensa
-
tion efforts following self-esteem threats, feelings of
uncertainty, and interpersonal rejection. We will return
to explore how the MMM and TMT can be contrasted
in a later section.
Evidence for Fluid Compensation
Across Domains
The research reviewed underscores the
substitutability of some motivations. Threats to
self-esteem in one self-domain can be compensated by
boosts in another; feelings of uncertainty in one area
can lead to attempts to feel certain in another; a dis
-
rupted relationship with one individual can lead people
to strive to deepen their relations with a different
group; and reminders of one’s mortality can be com
-
pensated by various attempts to achieve symbolic im
-
mortality. The MMM proposes that all of these in
-
stances represent special cases of responses to threats
to meaning. Notably, however, most of this research
has investigated the substitutability of these motiva-
tions within these specific domains. Although such
findings are completely consistent with the MMM,
there exists theories within each of these domains to
predict each of the respective domain-specific findings
(but not the findings within the other domains). In con-
trast, what is not consistent with existing theories (with
the exception of TMT regarding studies of symbolic
immortality) is the MMM’s prediction that evidence of
substitutability should be observed across the four do
-
mains. Such evidence would suggest that these sepa
-
rate domains serve a common function, which we sub
-
mit is the impulse to maintain a coherent relational
framework.
Fluid compensation among self-esteem, cer
-
tainty, and affiliative needs. One line of research
that cuts across the different research domains dis
-
cussed previously has been conducted under the con
-
ceptual aegis of social identity theory. Originally de
-
veloped by Tajfel and Turner (e.g., Tajfel, 1972; Tajfel
& Turner, 1979; Turner, 1975), and further elaborated
by Hogg and others (Abrams & Hogg, 1988; Ellemers,
Spears, & Doosje, 1999; Hogg, 2003; Hogg &
Sunderland, 1991), social identity theory has focused
on how people are motivated to have a sense of
belongingness with others and how they derive a sense
of identity from the various groups to which they be
-
long. One foundational premise of social identity the
-
ory is that the mere act of being categorized as a group
member, regardless of the basis of that categorization,
increases ingroup favoritism and intergroup discrimi
-
nation (e.g., Tajfel, 1970; Tajfel et al., 1971). The ques
-
98
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
tion of interest in social identity theory is why people
will demonstrate intergroup discrimination in a mini
-
mal groups design when they stand to gain nothing for
themselves, either from belonging to these groups or
by acting in ways that favor their minimally assigned
group.
Intergroup discrimination has been said to stem
largely from two underlying motivations. The first,
sometimes referred to as the self-esteem hypothesis
(e.g., Abrams & Hogg, 1988), maintains that people
are motivated to discriminate among groups as a means
to secure a positive self-view. Building upon
Festinger’s (1954) social comparison theory, Tajfel
(1972) proposed that people are not only motivated to
secure favorable contrasts between themselves and
others, but also between their group and other groups.
Discriminating between groups, then, is a way for peo
-
ple to feel good about themselves by casting their
group in a more favorable light (also see Turner, 1978,
1982). Over the past few decades a great deal of re
-
search has explored the relation between self-esteem
and intergroup discrimination. Two corollaries of the
self-esteem hypothesis have been derived and tested
from this model. The first is that people should feel
better about themselves following an intergroup dis-
crimination task. A number of studies report evidence
consistent with this proposition (Hogg, Turner,
Nascimento-Schulze, & Spriggs, 1986, Exp. 1;
Lemyre & Smith, 1985; Oakes & Turner, 1980), al-
though some others have not (e.g., Hogg &
Sunderland, 1991; Hogg & Turner, 1987). The second
corollary of the self-esteem hypothesis is that people
should demonstrate stronger intergroup discrimination
following a threat to their self-esteem. In support of
this proposition, Hogg and Sunderland (1991) found
that participants who received failure feedback on a
word association task demonstrated greater intergroup
discrimination than those who had received success
feedback (also see Brown, Collins, & Schmidt, 1988).
In general, then, there is considerable evidence that
self-esteem and social categorization are substitutable,
although the relation between self-esteem and inter
-
group discrimination appears to be moderated by addi
-
tional variables, such as the extremity of self-esteem,
the degree to which people identify with the group, and
the extent to which groups and their members may feel
under threat (Abrams & Hogg, 1988; Hogg, 2003;
Long & Spears, 1997; Rubin & Hewstone, 1998).
The second motivation that has been proposed to
underlie social identity theory is uncertainty reduction
(Hogg, 2001). As described earlier, uncertainty is a
problem when people are motivated to achieve control
over their lives. However, the quest for certainty is dif
-
ficult because there is scant evidence that objectively
confirms that people are indeed correct in their knowl
-
edge or opinions. In the absence of objective informa
-
tion, people must resort to seeking out cues that sug
-
gest that their beliefs are correct. For example, one
such cue relevant to social identity theory is perceived
agreement with others. To the extent that people feel
that there is a widely-shared consensus about a belief,
their confidence in that belief should increase. Hogg
and colleagues (e.g., Hogg & Abrams, 1993; Hogg &
Mullin, 1999) proposed that people can reduce their
sense of uncertainty on a particular topic if they feel
that they belong to a relatively homogeneous group. To
the extent that people are surrounded by those who ap
-
pear to be similar to themselves, they may infer that
their own beliefs on certain domains are also shared by
those similar others, and hence suggest that their per
-
sonal opinion is correct. Hogg and colleagues pro
-
posed that this relative homogeneity can be achieved
by intergroup discrimination. In addition to highlight
-
ing the distinction between groups, intergroup discrim
-
ination calls attention to the homogeneity within
groups, and “imposes order and ascribes meaning to a
potentially bewilderingly complex social field” (Hogg,
2003, p. 473).
In one test of the uncertainty hypothesis, Grieve and
Hogg (1999) demonstrated that participants showed a
more pronounced intergroup bias in a minimal groups
paradigm when they had earlier engaged in a task that
had no obvious solution and thus left them feeling un-
certain, relative to when they had not experienced in-
duced uncertainty (see Hogg & Mullin, 1999, for a re-
view of other relevant studies). Similarly, Shah,
Kruglanski, and Thompson (1998) found that a height-
ened need for closure leads to more pronounced
ingroup biases. Moreover, in their classic study,
Festinger, Riecken, and Schachter (1956) found that
when cult members’ doomsday beliefs were proved
wrong they started to proselytize, apparently in an at
-
tempt to get consensual validation for their beliefs that
no longer appeared to be correct. Relatedly,
McKimmie, Terry, and Hogg (2003) found that percep
-
tions of group support reduced participants’ feelings of
dissonance. Pinel and colleagues (2004) found that the
negative experience of existential isolation can be
mended by connecting with others who share the same
subjective experiences, thereby contributing to feel
-
ings of certainty. A desire for certainty can be relieved
through compensation in another domain such as
belongingness. Thus, motives for uncertainty reduc
-
tion and belongingness are capable of being substi
-
tuted for each other.
There are a number of other instances in which we
see interdependence among the domains of
self-esteem, certainty, and belongingness. For exam
-
ple, Navarette, Kurzban, Fessler, and Kirkpatrick
(2004) found that a manipulation of social isolation led
people to be more critical of someone who wrote an
anti-U.S. essay. That is, when individual’s feelings of
belongingness were threatened they came to desire the
certainty that their country’s ways of operating were
99
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
above the criticisms that the essay writer had proposed.
Zadro, Williams, and Richardson (2004) found that
even rejection by a computer program was sufficiently
threatening as to lower people’s feeling of
belongingness, control, self-esteem, and perceptions
of a meaningful existence. The blurring of the bound
-
aries between motivations for certainty and
self-esteem can be seen in the debate regarding
whether the unease experienced in cognitive disso
-
nance is fundamentally about inconsistency or about
self-esteem threat (Aronson, 1968; Festinger, 1957;
Steele, 1988). Furthermore, sociometer theory pro
-
poses that self-esteem and affiliative needs are deeply
intertwined (Leary & Baumeister, 2000; Leary et al.,
1995). Specifically, the model maintains that
self-esteem serves to indicate when individual’s rela
-
tionships are at risk for disruption. The sensitivity of
the sociometer is such that whenever relationships ap
-
pear vulnerable, self-esteem is likely to suffer. This is
proposed to be true even when the relationships at risk
are of little importance to the individual, or if the rela
-
tionships are only indirectly vulnerable due to an inad
-
equacy of an individual’s performance in other do
-
mains (Baumeister, Wotman, & Stillwell, 1993; Leary
et al., 1995). The interdependence between motiva-
tions for belongingness and self-esteem suggests that
these two motivations may serve a common function.
In sum, there is considerable evidence for instances
of interdependence among the three domains re-
viewed. In some circumstances, threats to self-esteem,
certainty, and belongingness can be compensated by
boosts in the other domains. We suggest that all of
these threats amount to assaults on the relational
frameworks that account for one’s selves, one’s outside
world, and one’s relation to the outside world. As such,
it follows that to a certain extent these domains should
appear to be largely substitutable with each other, inso
-
far as one may draw on one domain to reaffirm mean
-
ing when relations in another domain have been
compromised.
Fluid compensation of symbolic immortality
needs. Substitutability across domains is particu
-
larly evident in research on TMT. Mortality salience
has been linked to a variety of motivational tendencies,
including the three domains reviewed earlier. First,
mortality salience has been shown to lead people to
pursue various strategies to enhance or maintain
self-esteem (Greenberg et al., 1992; Harmon-Jones et
al., 1997; Mandel & Heine, 1999). For example,
Mikulincer and Florian (2002) found that the
self-serving attributional bias becomes more pro
-
nounced after mortality salience. The logic of TMT is
that people can experience symbolic immortality by
perceiving themselves as living up to the standards of a
culture, and consequently becoming associated with
enduring features of the culture (e.g., Solomon et al.,
1991). A desire for symbolic immortality leads to simi
-
lar consequences as threats to self-esteem and thus can
also be viewed as substitutable with self-esteem
threats.
Second, encounters with uncertainty also appear to
be substitutable with desires for symbolic immortality.
Numerous studies have demonstrated that mortality sa
-
lience leads to a heightened desire for certainty
(Deschene, 2002; Landau, Johns, et al., 2004; Van den
Bos, 2001; Van den Bos & Miedema, 2000). For exam
-
ple, Dechesne and Wigboldus (2001) found that partic
-
ipants who were reminded of their own mortality were
quicker to discern a pattern amongst a set of letters rel
-
ative to those who were not so reminded. According to
TMT, the heightened desire for certainty that follows
mortality salience is an attempt to reinforce one’s cul
-
tural worldview.
Third, belongingness needs are also affected by
mortality salience manipulations. A number of studies
have found that mortality salience prompts affiliative
tendencies (e.g., Mikulincer, Florian, & Hirschberger,
2004; Pyszczynski et al., 1996). One such response to
mortality salience is a heightened desire to discrimi
-
nate one’s group from others. For example,
Harmon-Jones, Greenberg, and Solomon (1996) found
that people who had been assigned to groups based on
their preference for one of two paintings showed more
of an intergroup bias if they were previously primed
with mortality salience than if they had not been
primed with death, thereby paralleling other work that
has employed uncertainty and self-esteem manipula-
tions (e.g., Grieve & Hogg, 1999; Hogg & Sunderland,
1991). A second way that people strive to fulfill
belongingness needs in the face of mortality salience is
that they strive to form more social relations. For ex
-
ample, Taubman Ben-Ari, Findler, and Mikulincer
(2002) found that mortality salience manipulations led
to a greater willingness to initiate social interactions,
particularly among those who were securely attached.
Wisman and Koole (2003) found that mortality sa
-
lience manipulations led people to prefer to sit in a
group than to sit alone, even when members of the
group endorsed beliefs that were antithetical to partici
-
pants’ own beliefs. Threats to one’s sense of
belongingness and desires for symbolic immortality
can be said to be, at least in some circumstances,
interchangeable.
TMT is by all accounts a hydraulic model. Not only
do threats to one’s meaning framework via mortality
salience lead to the compensatory responses identified
previously, but boosts to an individual’s sense of mean
-
ing reduce the impact of mortality salience. For exam
-
ple, boosts to self-esteem have been shown to eliminate
the effects of mortality salience on both worldview de
-
fense and death thought accessibility (Harmon-Jones
et al., 1997; Mikulincer & Florian, 2002). Likewise,
engaging in self-affirmation mollifies the impact of
100
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
mortality salience on worldview defense (Schmeichel
& Martens, 2005). Manipulations of variables related
to perceived certainty (or examinations of people who
vary in dispositional levels of these variables) find a re
-
duced impact of mortality salience manipulations (e.g.,
Dechesne, 2002; Dechesne, Janssen, & van
Knippenberg, 2000; cf., Jost, Fitzsimons, & Kay, 2004;
Van den Bos & Miedema, 2000). Furthermore, people
whose belongingness needs are sated insofar as they
report having secure attachments (Mikulincer &
Florian, 2000) or are seated with others (Wisman &
Koole, 2003) do not show worldview buffering re
-
sponses to mortality salience, although those whose
belongingness needs are deprived do. In sum, the
threats to one’s relational framework elicited by mor
-
tality salience can be compensated by boosts to one’s
relations in the domains of self-esteem, certainty, and
belongingness.
Divergent threats lead to convergent responses.
Further evidence for the substitutability across do
-
mains can be seen by examining the diverse array of
psychological threats that lead to the same kinds of
specific responses. For example, hostile reactions to
someone who criticizes one’s country has been ob-
served following manipulations such as mortality sa-
lience (H. A. McGregor et al., 1998), inducing a feel-
ing that one’s life is meaningless (Heine, MacKay,
Proulx, & Charles, 2005), temporal discontinuity (I.
McGregor et al., 2001), or by imagining that one has
been burglarized or socially isolated (Navarette et al.,
2004). Intergroup biases have been identified follow-
ing mortality salience manipulations (Greenberg et al.,
1990), a heightened need for closure (Shah et al.,
1998), feelings of uncertainty (Grieve & Hogg, 1999),
threats to self-esteem (Hogg & Sunderland, 1991), and
when people are unable to affirm their values (Fein &
Spencer, 1997). Affiliative motives have been fostered
by encounters with uncertainty (e.g., Festinger,
Riecken, & Schachter, 1956), mortality salience ma
-
nipulations (Mikulincer et al., 2004), worldview
threats (e.g., Hart, Shaver, & Goldenberg, 2004), and
self-esteem threats (Cialdini et al., 1976). A tendency
to rely on stereotypes has been identified by people
who have been reminded of their own mortality
(Schimel, Simon, & Greenberg, 1999), those whose
spatial-symbolic self was threatened (Burris &
Rempel, 2004), and by those high in need for closure
(Dijksterhuis et al., 1996). A tendency to punish people
who break cultural norms is evident among people who
are high in need for closure (Doherty, 1998), people
who were led to feel meaningless (Heine et al., 2005),
or people who were reminded of their mortality
(Rosenblatt et al., 1989). Observing that such diverse
phenomena lead to the same kinds of responses sug
-
gests the extent to which they substitutable for each
other. In each case mental representations of expected
relationships have been shattered, and in each case ex
-
pected relations have been reaffirmed elsewhere.
In sum, there is much evidence that self-esteem mo
-
tivations, preferences for certainty, affiliative needs,
and motivations for symbolic immortality are
substitutable drives. Divergent threats across these do
-
mains lead to convergent responses. Moreover, boosts
in one domain (e.g., self-esteem) diminish the effects
of threats in others (e.g., desire for symbolic immortal
-
ity; e.g., Harmon-Jones et al., 1997). The
substitutability, or equifinality, of different phenomena
suggests that they are in service of the same underlying
goal (Baumeister & Leary, 1995; Lewin, 1935;
Ovsiankina, 1928; Shah et al., 2003; Tesser, 2000). The
fluid compensation processes that have observed be
-
tween these different domains suggests that motiva
-
tions to maintain self-esteem, achieve certainty, estab
-
lish and maintain interpersonal relationships, and
avoid thoughts of one’s mortality are not ends in and of
themselves, but are means to a higher end. This end, we
propose, is a motivation to maintain meaning. It is far
more parsimonious to view these various motivations
as stemming from a single overarching concern (viz., a
desire for meaning) than to view these as separate, in-
dependent, processes.
One alternative account to our claim that the moti-
vations in the domains are substitutable is that a trans-
fer of affect or arousal could perhaps explain the find-
ings that an experience (e.g., an uncertainty or
mortality salience manipulation) can affect the engage-
ment in another behavior (e.g., increased intergroup
discrimination or dislike of an anti-U.S. essay writer).
For example, Zillman, Katcher, and Milavsky (1972)
found that after people exercised they would engage in
more aggressive activity. It does not seem reasonable
to propose that this is because exercise and aggression
are expressions of a similar underlying need; rather, it
appears that the arousal experienced from the exercise
carried over to affect people’s aggressive behaviors in
another context (also see Berkowitz, 1990; Schacter &
Singer, 1962). However, this transfer of arousal
account would seem to be hard-pressed to explain
many of the findings that we reviewed previously.
First, many of the reviewed studies included additional
dependent measures to serve as controls (e.g., evaluat
-
ing essay writers on nonmeaning-threatening topics;
Harmon-Jones et al., 1997; Heine et al., 2005) and
these did not reveal any effects of the meaning threat.
Rather, the meaning threat only led to specific mean
-
ing-boosting responses, rather than more critical re
-
sponses in general. Second, many of these studies
(again, particularly the TMT studies) included condi
-
tions that were designed to instill negative affect but
not meaning threats (e.g., by asking people to imagine
taking an exam or imagining worrisome thoughts;
Greenberg et al., 1995; H. McGregor et al., 1998), and
none of these revealed any evidence for worldview de
-
101
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
fense. Hence, differences between the studies reviewed
in support of the MMM and previous studies support
-
ing transfer of arousal or affect effects ameliorate con
-
cerns that the latter could account for the patterns ob
-
served and predicted by the MMM.
Is meaning the primary motive? One potential
challenge to our model is that because we are propos
-
ing that there is such similarity among needs for cer
-
tainty, self-esteem, belongingness, symbolic immor
-
tality, and meaning, it is possible that we have
identified the wrong motivation that unites them all.
For example, if these motivations are all so similar
could it instead be that a need for certainty, rather than
a need for meaning, underlies them? Or, perhaps the
fundamental human motivation guiding all of these dif
-
ferent responses is the need to belong. Given the sub
-
stantial degree of overlap that we are proposing, how
can we identify which motivation lies at the origin of
our motivational ontology?
This is a difficult question to answer empirically be
-
cause the overlap between these different motivations
requires that they are all closely connected and are thus
likely activated simultaneously. However, it is impor-
tant to make a distinction between saying that a moti-
vation for meaning underlies motivations for
self-esteem, certainty, belongingness, and symbolic
immortality and saying that these four motivations are
nothing but expressions of the desire for meaning.
There would certainly seem to be facets of these four
psychological processes that are distinct from each
other. That is, although a desire to maintain meaning
cuts across all of these psychological processes there is
more to each of these processes than just a motivation
for meaning. The imperfect overlap of these four pro
-
cesses is evident when considering some of the specific
experimental findings. For example, studies that found
that a heightened need for closure led to more pro
-
nounced ingroup biases (e.g., Shah et al., 1998) would
be difficult to explain by arguing that the process origi
-
nated with a threat to self-esteem. We do agree that
there is room to debate which motivation is more pri
-
mary in each of the individual experiments that have
been reviewed, however, we think that the one account
that is parsimonious across each and every instance is
that people are striving to affirm coherent structures of
expected relationships.
More important to this point is that people need
mental representations of expected relationships to
have these other things. If one wants to predict events
in the outside world, or the thoughts, feelings and be
-
haviors associated with themselves and others, one
needs stable mental representations that bear some re
-
lation to these phenomena. If one wants to intention
-
ally intervene in their environment and control events
to bring about desired outcomes, such intervention is
-
n’t possible unless these same relational structures are
in place. If one wants to feel connected to something
outside themselves—places, belongings, family,
friends, lovers, a society, a culture—the impulse and
ability to form such complex relationships both fuels
this desire and makes it possible. This is true regardless
of the other needs met by such relationships, be it the
need for self-esteem, the need for certainty, the need to
belong, or the need to symbolically endure.
Testable Predictions for the MMM
A model as broad and encompassing as the MMM
should afford many testable and falsifiable predictions.
Specifically, the model predicts that threats to an indi
-
vidual’s meaning will lead to efforts to affirm an alter
-
native viable relational framework when given the op
-
portunity. Although a great deal of research has been
conducted that is consistent with the MMM, there are
many directions that future research could be pursued
to directly test the model. First, as we have argued, the
four domains of empirical findings that we have re
-
viewed (viz., motivations for self-esteem, certainty, af
-
filiation, and symbolic immortality) are hypothesized
to be substitutable. That is, threats in any of these do-
mains should be compensated for by a boost in any of
the others. Although there is much research that we re-
viewed that is in support of our thesis, there are a num-
ber of combinations of these four domains that have yet
to be investigated. The MMM would predict, for exam-
ple, that people should be more motivated to discern a
pattern in some noise following a significant
self-esteem threat delivered via negative personality
feedback. Alternatively, one would expect that people
should strive to affiliate with others following a manip
-
ulation that heightens their need for cognitive closure.
The MMM predicts that these compensatory responses
should be evident provided that the meaning threats are
significant and effectively delivered, and that there are
sound measures of attempts to redirect attention to al
-
ternative meaning systems. In sum, these four domains
of meaning threats and four domains of mean
-
ing-boosting responses provide at least 16 cells within
which predictions from the MMM can be tested and
potentially falsified.
The MMM does not only propose mean
-
ing-affirming responses to meaning threats. The
MMM is a hydraulic model and, as such, predicts that
people should experience less of a meaning threat
when they have experienced a boost to an alternative
relational framework. For example, people who have
affirmed their values or have received a self-esteem
boost have been found to experience less cognitive dis
-
sonance upon making a difficult choice (e.g., Heine &
Lehman, 1997; Steele & Liu, 1983). Thus far, the ma
-
jority of research on hydraulic relations between
meaning boosts and threats has been conducted within
102
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
a TMT framework, which has identified a variety of
meaning boosts that diminish the impact of mortality
salience (e.g., Dechesne, Janssen, & van Knippenberg,
2000; Harmon-Jones et al., 1997; Mikulincer &
Florian, 2002; Schmeichel & Martens, in press; Van
den Bos & Miedema, 2000; Wisman & Koole, 2003).
We propose that further evidence of the hydraulic na
-
ture of meaning maintenance could be obtained by
findings that boosts to people’s self-esteem, perceived
certainty, and belongingness would lessen the impact
of various threats, including mortality salience, but
also self-esteem threats, feelings of uncertainty, or in
-
terpersonal rejection. In sum, meaning boosts in any of
the four domains are predicted to reduce the impact of
threat in any of the other four domains.
Please note that we are not proposing that the four
domains of self-esteem, certainty, belongingness, and
symbolic immortality are an exhaustive list of the ways
that people can gain meaning in their lives. In addition
to these 4 domains, there are likely other sources of
threats to meaning and successful meaning boosting
strategies. For example, some manipulations that have
led to compensatory meaning-gaining responses in
-
clude thinking of the presence of dust mites (Burris &
Rempel, 2004), a temporal discontinuity task (I.
McGregor et al., 2001), imagining that one has been
burglarized (Navarette et al., 2004), or questioning
how meaningful one’s life is (Heine et al., 2005). It is
not clear that these manipulations fit into motivations
for self-esteem, certainty, affiliation, or symbolic im-
mortality. We suspect that there are likely many other
threats to meaning that could be experimentally manip-
ulated and that would show comparable mean-
ing-boosting responses. For example, we anticipate
that if participants could be led to believe that their per
-
ceptions of the world were out of touch with reality,
such as when people participate in an Asch-like line
judgment task in which they discover that they failed to
accurately perform a simple visual task, they would
consequently seek to assert alternative frameworks.
Likewise, meaning-seeking responses would be pre
-
dicted to occur if participants were led to encounter
large anomalies in time perception by having them at
-
tend to a malfunctioning clock; if they were led to be
-
lieve that their self-concept was inconsistent and con
-
tradictory; if they encountered Bruner-Postman kinds
of irregular stimuli (i.e., playing cards of a certain suit
being the wrong color); or even if they watched a sur
-
real mind-blowing movie such as Mulholland Drive.
Moreover, we propose that these events would be less
threatening to people’s relational frameworks if they
were preceded by a boost to the person’s meaning, such
as through a value affirmation task or a manipulation to
make the person feel more certain. We hypothesize fur
-
ther that perceived anomalous relations in the realm of
the self or the realm of the relations between the self
and external world will lead to more significant efforts
to regain meaning compared with experiencing anom
-
alous relations in the realm of the external world. Put
another way, the more central the perceived relations to
one’s life, the more connections that will be open and
thus vulnerable to an anomalous experience. Hence, a
disruption to a framework such as this would bring
about an urgent need to assert a coherent relational
framework.
Last, because people’s meaning-making exercises
will be greatly influenced by what relations are
consensually constructed within their culture, we ex
-
pect there to be significant cultural differences in the
kinds of events that serve to threaten or boost meaning.
For example, self-esteem does not appear to be a pri
-
mary source of meaning in hierarchical collectivistic
societies such as in East Asia, and thus we predict that
there should be little evidence of compensatory re
-
sponses to self-esteem threat there (e.g., Heine et al.,
1999). Conversely, we reason that “face” is a more fo
-
cal source of meaning in East Asia, and that threats to
face should lead to pronounced meaning-boosting ef
-
forts in that culture (Heine, 2005). We anticipate that
measuring the extent to which people engage in com
-
pensatory responses after different kinds of threats
may serve as a methodology to help identify the core
sources of meaning within a culture. In sum, there are
many testable and falsifiable predictions that can be
uniquely derived from the MMM.
Contrasting TMT and the MMM
Our initial reasoning for the MMM was an exten
-
sion of our reading of the compelling TMT literature,
and, indeed, there are many parallels between these
two theories. Both theories are existential in nature,
both predict the same kinds of worldview bolstering re
-
sponses to mortality salience, and both emphasize the
fluid domain-general nature of our attempts to restore
meaning. Given this similarity we feel it is crucial to
underscore the important ways in which these two the
-
ories diverge.
TMT and MMM differ in terms of the foundation of
the respective theories. TMT proposes that people are
motivated to achieve symbolic immortality, which is
attained by activation of the dual component anxiety
buffer. In TMT, thoughts of death provoke anxiety by
reminding people of their own mortality. In an effort to
avoid this anxiety, people strive for a sense of symbolic
immortality, which they achieve by bolstering the
structure within which they exist, or their associations
to that structure. Symbolic immortality is said to be de
-
rived from the activation of the dual component anxi
-
ety buffer because the structure is perceived to have a
sense of permanence, and one can become symboli
-
cally associated with this permanence by perceiving
103
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
oneself as a valued part of this structure (e.g.,
Pyszczynski et al., 2004; Solomon et al., 1991).
In contrast, the MMM proposes that people have a
fundamental need to maintain viable mental represen
-
tations of expected relationships. Anything that chal
-
lenges these relational structures will lead to efforts to
construct or affirm alternative structures. Mortality sa
-
lience is one experience that disrupts an individual’s
meaning framework; however, the proposed model
predicts that other threats to meaning would yield com
-
parable efforts to regain meaning.
Given the substantial conceptual overlap between
TMT and MMM, we consider the kind of evidence that
would disentangle the two theories. Because both theo
-
ries view mortality salience as a threat which leads to
compensatory responses, the findings of TMT studies
are also consistent with the predictions of the MMM,
albeit for a different theoretical rationale. In contrast,
however, threats to meaning that do not invoke
thoughts of death would only be predicted to lead to at
-
tempts to construct or reassert meaning frameworks by
the MMM. Hence, the two theories can be distin
-
guished by contrasting their predictions for the re
-
sponses in which people engage when they encounter a
nondeath related meaning threat.
Recently, a number of research programs have con-
trasted how people respond when they encounter
meaning threats that do not involve reference to death
with a mortality salience condition. In one direct series
of tests of the MMM, Heine and colleagues (2005) pro-
vided participants with feedback, via a rigged ques-
tionnaire, that their life was low in meaning or with a
mortality salience manipulation. Participants in both
conditions responded in the same way across a number
of studies. Specifically, participants were more nega
-
tive towards someone who criticized their country
(thereby preserving a desirable set of relations between
oneself and one’s country), more punitive towards a
prostitute (maintaining an orderly set of relations
within the external world), and more desirous of
high-status products compared with those in a control
condition (which allow for positive associations be
-
tween oneself and the world). It is not clear what model
other than the MMM could account for these findings.
Other research programs have yielded findings eas
-
ily integrated into the MMM but counter to the predic
-
tions of TMT. For example, I. McGregor and col
-
leagues (2001) found that having people experience a
temporal discontinuity manipulation led people to
have the same response as a mortality salience manipu
-
lation. Specifically, they showed a heightened inter
-
group bias (which provides people with an orderly and
desirable set of associations between themselves and
their group). There was no difference in participants’
responses between this condition and another condi
-
tion in which mortality salience was manipulated.
Navarette and colleagues (2004) provided people with
a manipulation of “theft salience” (they were to imag
-
ine their homes had been burglarized), or a
manipulation of “social isolation” (they were to imag
-
ine themselves isolated from family and friends), or a
mortality salience manipulation. Subsequently, partici
-
pants evaluated an anti-U.S. essay. Participants in all
three conditions responded with more hostility towards
the anti-U.S. essay writer compared to those in a con
-
trol group. Van den Bos and colleagues (Van den Bos
& Miedema, 2000; Van den Bos, Poortvliet, Maas,
Miedema, & Van den Ham, 2005) asked people to con
-
sider how they feel when they are uncertain or when
their mortality is made salient. People in both condi
-
tions responded with increased anger towards unfair
treatment compared with those in a control condition
(perceived unfairness violates one’s expected relation
-
ships with the world). Miedema, Van den Bos, and
Vermunt (2004) found that participants reacted more
strongly towards variations in fairness when their
self-image had been threatened (by having them recall
situations in which central aspects of their selves were
questioned by people who were very important for
them) relative to a control condition, in ways identical
to those previously identified by mortality salience ma-
nipulations (e.g., Van den Bos & Miedema, 2000).
Burris and Rempel (2006) found that reminding people
of the existence of dust mites led to a preference for
stereotypical targets over counter-stereotypical targets
compared with those in a control condition. They also
found this identical pattern of results when contrasting
mortality salience and control conditions (cf., Schimel
et al., 1999). Although thoughts of dust mites are not
associated with thoughts of mortality, they do chal-
lenge one’s spatial-symbolic self in that they represent
an invasion of one’s space. We propose that they also
threaten one’s meaning frameworks in that they pro
-
duce an invasive, unexpected, and undesired associa
-
tion with the self.
In sum, research has shown that a diverse array of
threats to established relations (i.e., temporal disconti
-
nuity, reminders of the relative meaninglessness of
one’s life, thoughts of burglary or social isolation, feel
-
ings of uncertainty, self-image threats, and thoughts of
dust mites) lead to the same responses as manipula
-
tions of mortality salience to a diverse array of depend
-
ent measures (i.e., intergroup biases, preferences for
high-status products, punitive responses towards a
prostitute, dislike of someone who criticizes one’s
country, anger towards unfair treatment, and prefer
-
ence for stereotypical targets). In all of these studies
the effects from the nondeath meaning threats were as
strong as the effects of mortality salience manipula
-
tions, although we note that some efforts to manipulate
meaning have not replicated TMT findings (e.g.,
Baldwin & Wesley, 1996; Landau, Johns, et al., 2004).
Taken together, the diversity of operationalizations and
predicted responses in the studies reviewed previously
104
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
lends support to the robustness of the meaning-making
compensatory process while weakening alternative ac
-
counts of any individual study. Apparently, meaning
threats elicited through numerous means influence
people in the same ways as does mortality salience.
These findings would seem to be a challenge to the
logic of TMT. One possibility consistent with TMT is
that the threats to meaning described previously lead to
TMT-like responses because meaning threats weaken
the anxiety buffer and allow death thoughts to reach
consciousness, thereby leading to efforts to regain
symbolic immortality. However, we would challenge
this alternative account in two respects. First, there is
little evidence that death thoughts are activated by
these other meaning threats. Word completion tasks re
-
veal that none of these manipulations led to increased
death thought accessibility (Burris & Rempel, 2004; I.
McGregor, Zanna, & Holmes, 1998; Navarette et al.,
2004; Van den Bos et al., 2005), however, we note
some other manipulations, such as relationship prob
-
lems (Florian, Mikulincer, & Hirschberger, 2002), and
thoughts of physical sex among neurotics
(Goldenberg, Pyszczynski, McCoy, & Greenberg,
1999), have been shown to heighten death thought ac-
cessibility, findings that are not easily explained by the
MMM. It is difficult to maintain that the meaning re-
construction efforts are due to the activation of death
thoughts when these studies have failed to find it. Sec-
ond, the MMM is a far more parsimonious account of
findings from studies in which mortality salience is not
manipulated. The MMM explains nondeath related
studies as well as TMT findings by maintaining any
number of significant threats to one’s meaning frame-
work will lead to a response to affirm an alternative
framework.
We do suggest, however, that not all meaning
threats are created equal. We submit that the most sig
-
nificant threat to one’s relational frameworks is
thoughts of one’s pending death. Heidegger (1953/
1996) regarded humans’ desire to avoid death as a
placeholder for the more fundamental desire to estab
-
lish stable webs that tie together elements of external
reality, and that finally entangle our human selves
within them. Death rips apart these connections, and in
so doing, renders humans’ existence ultimately and un
-
avoidably fragmentary, and therefore meaningless.
Disruption of meaning frameworks that are less central
to the self would be expected to cause a less urgent re
-
sponse to assert an alternative framework.
In addition to the conceptual reasons for why re
-
minders of death provide such strong threats to mean
-
ing, we submit that there might be a methodological
reason as well. Mortality salience has the unique virtue
of being a manipulation that is extremely difficult to ra
-
tionalize away. Threats to self-esteem, manipulations
of uncertainty, or staged interpersonal rejections can be
effectively disarmed by reinterpreting the threat such
that one’s self-esteem really hasn’t been threatened,
that one really doesn’t feel uncertain, or that the
rejectors are not seen as competent or valued relation
-
ship partners. As anyone who has tried to deliver fail
-
ure feedback to research participants can testify, quite
often the manipulated threat is not received with the in
-
tent that it was delivered. In an attempt to reinterpret
the threat, participants can conjure up external attribu
-
tions (e.g., “I didn’t get enough sleep last night.”), dis
-
count the importance of the task (e.g., “Who really
cares about anagram-solving skills anyways?”), or be
-
come suspicious about the whole experiment (e.g.,
“There is no way that I could have done that poorly!”).
In sharp contrast, there is no reinterpreting away the
fact that some day one will die. Hence, we imagine that
mortality salience may indeed prove to be the most
powerful and reliable manipulation to threaten peo
-
ple’s meaning frameworks in the laboratory.
The Problem of Suicide
The differences in the theoretical foundations of
TMT and MMM are perhaps most evident when we
consider the problem of suicide. Camus (1955)
claimed “There is but one truly serious philosophical
problem, and that is suicide” (p. 3). Why might it be
that someone would wish to take their own life? Camus
suggested that
Dying voluntarily implies that you have recognized,
even instinctively, the ridiculous character of habit,
the absence for any profound reason for living, the in-
sane character of daily agitation, and the uselessness
of suffering…there is a direct connection between this
feeling and the longing for death. (Camus, 1955,
p. 10)
If it is, as TMT suggests, that the need for meaning
reduces to the need to avoid the latent anxiety that re
-
sults from an awareness of one’s own mortality, how
then could it be that in the absence of meaning, people
long for death? If people sometimes choose death over
meaninglessness, it scarcely seems possible that death
can be considered their greatest fear, or that the need
for meaning can reduce to the desire to be buffered
from an awareness of one’s own imminent death. The
MMM presents an alternative motivational ontology,
wherein the need for meaning exists independently of
the will to exist, and is sufficiently powerful that, if un
-
met, the resulting distress may goad one into ending
one’s own life. We agree with Heidegger (1953/1996,
p. 245) that “angst about death must not be confused
with fear of one’s demise. We suggest that if there is
any reductive relationship between death and meaning
-
lessness, it is the fear of death that primarily reduces to
the need for meaning, insofar as humans fear death be
-
cause death may render life meaningless. When indi
-
105
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
viduals are unable to construct the coherent mental
representations of expected relationships that allow
them to maintain a perception of control over their
existences, or derive a sense of purposeful connection
in their daily activities, they occasionally, and tragi
-
cally, choose death.
Conclusions
The MMM proposes that a diverse array of human
motivations, including motivations for self-esteem,
certainty, affiliation, and symbolic immortality, can be
understood as stemming from a common underlying
drive: People possess an associative impulse by which
they seek to relate objects and events to each other and
to the self. This desire to perceive relations results in
people viewing their worlds and the events within them
through the prism of their mental representations.
These representations are constructions, and often do
not accurately reflect objective relations within the
world. When people become aware of events that can
-
not be accommodated in their relational structures,
they experience a threat to their sense of meaning.
These threats to meaning are dealt with in a few ways:
people may reinterpret the events so that they are no
longer inconsistent with their mental representations
or they may revise their representations so that they are
capable of incorporating the new troublesome event
(Kuhn, 1962/1996). In addition to these more re-
searched strategies, the MMM offers the novel propo-
sition that people might respond to meaning threats by
reaffirming an alternative framework. The goal is to be
attending to a viable and coherent framework of rela
-
tions, and people will be motivated to assert one even if
it does not appear related to the source of threat that
motivated their search in the first place.
There are various sources of threat to people’s
meaning frameworks. People might encounter a threat
to their self-esteem that reduces their sense that they
are relating to their worlds in a functional way. People
encounter occasions in which they feel uncertain about
relations between elements of the world around them,
making them feel unable to predict future events. Peo
-
ple may be rejected by others, thereby ostracizing them
from any consensual indicators that they are function
-
ing well. Or there are times when people consider their
future mortality and this realization shatters all rela
-
tions between the self and its external world. These
threats, we submit, lead people to respond by asserting
alternative frameworks that do not appear to contain
any anomalous relations. Affirmations of a coherent
relational structure will serve to nullify the threat
caused by the hitherto identified irregularities. Because
the proposed goal of our meaning maintenance efforts
is to be attending to a viable meaning framework, it is
not necessary to deal directly with the threatening
anomaly. Any compelling and available network of re
-
lations can suffice, thereby underscoring the fluid com
-
pensatory nature of the MMM. For example, threats to
uncertainty can be compensated by feelings of
belongingness (Hogg, 2003), or threats to mortality sa
-
lience can be compensated by boosts in self-esteem
(Harmon-Jones et al., 1997). Indeed, threats within the
domains of self-esteem, certainty, belongingness, or
symbolic immortality should all be ameliorated by as
-
serting meaning frameworks within any of the other
domains. Because each of these four psychological
processes can be substituted by the others suggests that
they are serving a common purpose. That purpose is to
maintain meaning.
The MMM integrates a number of diverse litera
-
tures on human motivation. Although the MMM is
surely not all that is behind the specific motivations for
self-esteem, certainty, belongingness, and symbolic
immortality, we propose that elucidating a common
motivation that cuts across these human drives will fa
-
cilitate future conceptual and empirical inquiries into
identifying why people behave in the ways they do.
References
Abrams, D., & Hogg, M. A. (1988). Comments on the motivational
status of self-esteem in social identity and intergroup discrimi-
nation. European Journal of Social Psychology, 18, 317–334.
Antonovsky, A. (1979). Health, stress and coping. San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass.
Aristotle. (1987). De Anima. London: Penguin Books.
Aronson, E. (1968). Dissonance theory: Progress and problems. In
R. Abelson, E. Aronson, W. McGuire, T. Newcomb, M.
Rosenberg, & P. Tannebaum (Eds.), The cognitive consistency
theories: A source book (pp. 5–27). Chicago: McNally.
Asch, S. (1946). Forming impressions of personality. Journal of Ab
-
normal and Social Psychology, 41, 1230–1240.
Audy, J. R. (1980). Man the lonely animal: Biological roots of loneli
-
ness. In J. Hartog, J. R. Audy, & Y. A. Cohen (Eds.), The anat
-
omy of loneliness (pp. 111–128). New York: International Uni
-
versities Press.
Baldwin, M. W., & Wesley, R. (1996). Effects of existential anxiety
and self-esteem on the perception of others. Basic and Applied
Social Psychology, 10, 75–95.
Barkow, J. H. (1989). Darwin, sex, and status: Biosocial approaches
to mind and culture. Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto
Press.
Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering. Cambridge, England: Cam
-
bridge University Press.
Baumeister, R. F. (1991). Meanings of life. New York: Guilford.
Baumeister, R. F., & Jones, E. E. (1978). When self-presentation is
constrained by the target’s knowledge: Consistency and com
-
pensation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 36,
608–618.
Baumeister, R. F., & Leary, M. R. (1995). The need to belong: Desire
for interpersonal attachments as a fundamental human motiva
-
tion. Psychological Bulletin, 117, 497–529.
Baumeister, R. F., Wotman, S. R., & Stillwell, A. M. (1993). Unre
-
quited love: On heartbreak, anger, guilt, scriptlessness, and hu
-
106
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
miliation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64,
377–394.
Becker, E. (1973). The denial of death. New York: Free Press.
Berkowitz, L. (1990). On the formation and regulation of anger and
aggression: A cognitive-neoassociationistic analysis. American
Psychologist, 45, 494–503.
Bloom, B. L., White, S. W., & Asher, S. J. (1979). Marital disruption
as a stressful life event. In G. Levinger & O. C. Moles (Eds.),
Divorce and separation: Context, causes, and consequences
(pp. 184–200). New York: Basic Books.
Bowlby, J. (1969). Attachment and loss: Vol. 1. Attachment. New
York: Basic Books.
Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1995). Why does culture increase hu
-
man adaptability? Ethology and Sociobiology, 16, 125–143.
Brown, J. D., Collins, R. L., & Schmidt, G. W. (1988). Self-esteem
and direct versus indirect forms of self-enhancement. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 55, 445–453.
Bruner, J. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni
-
versity Press.
Bruner, J., & Postman, L. (1949). On the perception of incongruity:
A paradigm. Journal of Personality, 18, 206–223.
Burris, C. T., & Rempel, J. K. (2004). “It’s the end of the world as we
know it”: Threat and the spatial-symbolic self. Journal of Per
-
sonality and Social Psychology, 86, 19–42.
Cacioppo, J. T., & Petty, R. E.. (1982). The need for cognition. Jour
-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 42, 116–131.
Camus, A. (1955). An absurd reasoning. The myth of Sisyphus and
other essays (pp. 3–49). New York: Vintage.
Cantnor, N., & Mischel, W. (1979). Prototypes in person perception.
In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psy-
chology (Vol. 12, pp. 3–52). New York: Academic.
Chandler, M., Lalonde, C., Sokol, B., & Hallett, D. (2003). Personal
persistence, identity development and suicide. Monographs of
the Society for Research in Child Development, 68, 1–129.
Cialdini, R. B., Borden, R. J., Thorne, A., Walker, M. R., Freeman,
S., & Sloan, L. R. (1976). Basking in reflected glory: Three
(football) field studies. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 34, 366–375.
Creel, S. C., Newport, E. L., & Aslin, R. N. (2004). Distant melodies:
Statistical learning of nonadjacent dependencies in tone se
-
quences. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 30, 1119–1130.
Crocker, J., & Park, L. E. (2004). The costly pursuit of self-esteem.
Psychological Bulletin, 130, 392–414.
Dechesne, M. (2006). Individual differences in terror management re
-
search:Thecaseof need for closure.Manuscript in preparation.
Dechesne, M., Janssen, J., & Van Knippenberg, A. (2000). Deroga
-
tion and distancing as terror management strategies: The mod
-
erating role of need for closure and permeability of group
boundaries. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79,
923–932.
Dechesne, M., & Kruglanski, A. (2004). Experimental existential
-
ism and the concept of closure. In J. Greenberg, S. L. Koole, &
T. Pyszczynski (Eds.), Handbook of experimental existential
psychology (pp. 247–262). New York: Guilford.
Dechesne, M., & Wigboldus, D. (2001). [Terror management in a
minimal worldview paradigm.] Unpublished raw data.
Delongis, A., Folkman, S., & Lazarus, R. (1988). The impact of daily
stress on health and mood: Psychological and social resources
as mediators. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54,
486–495.
Dijksterhuis, A., van Knippenberg, A., Kruglanski, A. W., &
Schaper, C. (1996). Motivated social cognition: Need for clo
-
sure effects on memory and judgment. Journal of Experimental
Social Psychology, 32, 254–270.
Doherty, K. T. (1998). A mind of her own: Effects of need for closure
and gender on reactions to nonconformity. Sex Roles, 38,
801–819.
Dunbar, R. I. M. (1992). Neocortex size as a constraint on group size
in primates. Journal of Human Evolution, 20, 469–493.
Dunbar, R. I. M. (1993). The co-evolution of neocortical size, group
size and language in humans, Behavioural and Brain Sciences,
16, 681–735.
Dunbar, R. I. M. (1997). Grooming, gossip, and the evolution of lan
-
guage. London: Faber & Faber.
Ellemers, N., Spears, R., & Doosje, B. (Eds.). (1999). Social identity.
Oxford, England: Blackwell.
Epstein, S. (1981). The unity principle versus the reality and pleasure
principles, or the tale of the scorpion and the frog. In M. D.
Lynch, A. A. Norem-Hebeisen, & K. Gergen (Eds.),
Self-concept: Advances in theory of a theory and research (pp.
27–38). Cambridge, MA: Ballinger.
Fein, S., & Spencer, S. J. (1997). Prejudice as self-image mainte
-
nance: Affirming the self through derogating others. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 73, 31–44.
Festinger, L. (1954). A theory of social comparison processes. Hu
-
man Relations, 7, 117–140.
Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dissonance. Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Festinger, L., Riecken, H. W., & Schachter, S. (1956). When proph
-
ecy fails. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Fiser, J., & Aslin, R, (2001). Unsupervised statistical learning of
higher-order spatial structures from visual scenes. Psychologi
-
cal Science, 12, 499–502.
Florian, V., Mikulincer, M., & Hirschberger, G. (2002). The anxi
-
ety buffering function of close relationships: Evidence the re
-
lationship commitment acts as a terror management mecha-
nism. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 82,
527–542.
Freud, S. (1930/1991). Civilization and its discontents. In A. Dick-
son (Ed.), Sigmund Freud: 12. Civilization, society, and reli-
gion (pp. 245–341). New York: Penguin.
Fromm, E. (1947). Man for himself: An inquiry into the psychology
of ethics. New York: Rinehart.
Goffman, E. J. (1973). The presentation of self in everyday life.
Woodstock, NY: Overlook Press.
Goldenberg, J. L., Pyszczynski, T., McCoy, S. K., & Greenberg, J.
(1999). Death, sex, love, and neuroticism: Why is sex such a
problem? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77,
1173–1187.
Goodwin, J. S., Hunt, W. C., Key, C. R., & Sarnet, J. M. (1987). The
effect of marital status on stage, treatment, and survival of can
-
cer patients. Journal of the American Medical Association, 258,
3125–3130.
Greenberg, J., Koole, S. L., & Pyszczynski, T. (2004). Handbook of
experimental existential psychology. New York: Guilford.
Greenberg, J., Porteus, J., Simon, L., Pyszczynski, T., & Solomon, S.
(1995). Evidence of a terror management function of cultural
icons: The effects of mortality salience on the inappropriate use
of cherished cultural symbols. Personality and Social Psychol
-
ogy Bulletin, 21, 1221–1228.
Greenberg, J., Pyszczynski, T., Solomon, S., Rosenblatt, A., Veeder,
M., Kirkland, S., & Lyon, D. (1990). Evidence for terror man
-
agement theory II: The effects of mortality salience on reactions
to those who threaten or bolster the cultural worldview. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 58, 308–318.
Greenberg, J., Simon, L., Harmon-Jones, E., Solomon, S.,
Pyszczynski, T., et al. (1995). Testing alternative explanations
for mortality salience effects: Terror management, value acces
-
sibility, or worrisome thoughts? European Journal of Social
Psychology, 12, 417–433.
Greenberg, J., Solomon, S., Pyszczynski, T., Rosenblatt, A., Burling,
J., et al. (1992). Why do people need self-esteem? Converging
evidence that self-esteem serves an anxiety-buffering function.
Journal of Personality and Social psychology, 63, 913–922.
107
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
Grieve, P., & Hogg, M. A. (1999). Subjective uncertainty and inter
-
group discrimination in the minimal group situation. Personal
-
ity and Social Psychology Bulletin, 25, 926–940.
Halloran, M. J., & Kashima, E. S. (2004). Social identity and
worldview validation: The effects of ingroup identity primes
and mortality salience on value endorsement. Personality and
Social Psychology Bulletin, 30, 915–925
Harmon-Jones, E., Greenberg, J., & Solomon, S. (1996). The effects
of mortality salience on intergroup bias between minimal
groups. European Journal of Social Psychology, 26, 677–681.
Harmon-Jones, E., & Mills, J. (1999). Cognitive dissonance: Prog
-
ress on a pivotal theory in social psychology. Washington, DC:
American Psychological Association.
Harmon-Jones, E., Simon, L., Greenberg, J., Pyszczynski, T., Solo
-
mon, S., & McGregor, H. (1997). Terror management theory
and self-esteem: Evidence that increased self-esteem reduces
mortality salience effects. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 72, 24–36.
Hart, J., Shaver, P. R., & Goldenberg, J. L. (2004, January). Attach
-
ment, self-esteem, worldview, and terror management: Evi
-
dence for a tripartite security system. Paper presented at the
Fifth Conference of the Society for Personality and Social Psy
-
chologists, Austin, TX.
Heidegger, M. (1953/1996). Being and time. New York: State Uni
-
versity of New York Press.
Heider, F. (1958). The psychology of interpersonal relations. New
York: Wiley.
Heine, S. J. (2003). An exploration of cultural variation in self-en
-
hancing and self-improving motivations. In V. Murphy-Berman
& J. J. Berman (Eds.), Nebraska symposium on motivation: Vol.
49. Cross-cultural differences in perspectives on the self (pp.
101–128). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
Heine, S. J. (2005). Constructing good selves in Japan and North
America. In Culture and Social Behavior: The Tenth Ontario
Symposium (pp. 115–143). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates, Inc.
Heine, S. J., Harihara, M., & Niiya, Y. (2002). Terror management in
Japan. Asian Journal of Social Psychology, 5, 187–196.
Heine, S. J., & Lehman, D. R. (1997). Culture, dissonance, and
self-affirmation. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
23, 389–400.
Heine, S. J., Lehman, D. R., Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (1999).
Is there a universal need for positive self-regard? Psychological
Review, 106, 766–794.
Heine, S. J., MacKay, M., Proulx, T., & Charles, S. (2005). Death
and meaning loss: An alternative account of terror manage
-
ment findings. Unpublished manuscript, University of British
Columbia.
Hogg, M. A. (2001). Self-categorization and subjective uncertainty
resolution: Cognitive and motivational and facets of social
identity and group membership. In J. P. Forgas, K. D. Williams,
& L. Wheeler (Eds.), The social mind: Cognitive and motiva
-
tional aspects of interpersonal behaviour (pp. 323–349). New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Hogg, M. A. (2003). Social identity. In M. R. Leary & J. P. Tangney
(Eds.), Handbook of self and identity. New York: Guildford.
Hogg, M. A., & Abrams, D. (1993). Towards a single-process uncer
-
tainty-reduction model of social motivation in groups. In M. A.
Hogg & D. Abrams (Eds.), Group motivation: Social psycho
-
logical perspectives (pp. 173–190). London: Harvester
Wheatsheaf.
Hogg, M. A., & Mullin, B. A. (1999). Joining groups to reduce uncer
-
tainty: Subjective uncertainty reduction and group identifica
-
tion. In D. Abrams & M. A. Hogg (Eds.), Social identity and so
-
cial cognition (pp. 249–279). Oxford, England: Blackwell.
Hogg, M. A., & Sunderland, J. (1991). Self-esteem and intergroup
discrimination in the minimal group paradigm. British Journal
of Social Psychology, 30, 51–62.
Hogg, M. A., & Turner, J. C. (1987). Intergroup behaviour,
self-stereotyping and the salience of social categories. British
Journal of Social Psychology, 26, 325–340.
Hogg, M. A., Turner, J. C., Nascimento-Schulze, C., & Spriggs, J.
(1986). Social categorization, intergroup behaviour, and
self-esteem: Two experiments. Revista de Psicologia Social, 1,
23–37.
House, J. S., Landis, K. R., & Umberson, D. (1988). Social relation
-
ships and health. Science, 241, 540–545.
Humphrey, N. K. (1976). The social function of intellect. In P. P. G.
Bateson & R. A. Hinde (Eds). Growing points in ethology (pp.
303–317).Cambridge, England: UniversityofCambridge Press.
James, W. (1997). The meaning of truth. New York: Prometheus.
(Original work published 1911)
Janoff-Bulman, R. (1992). Shattered assumptions. New York: Free
Press.
Jost, J. T., Fitzsimons, G., & Kay, A. C. (2004). The ideological ani
-
mal: A comparison of system justification, terror management,
and just world theories. In J. Greenberg, S. L. Koole, & T.
Pyszczynski (Eds.), Handbook of experimental existential psy
-
chology (pp. 263–283). New York: Guilford.
Kierkegaard, S. (1997). Either/Or. In H. Hong & E. Hong (Eds.), The
essential Kierkegaard (pp. 37–84). Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press. (Original work published 1843)
Kierkegaard, S. (1997). The sickness unto death. In H. Hong & E.
Hong (Eds.), The essential Kierkegaard (pp. 350–372). Prince
-
ton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work published
1848)
Kruglanski, A., & Freund, T. (1983). The freezing and unfreezing of
lay inferences: Effects of impressional primacy, ethnic stereo-
typing, and numerical anchoring. Journal of Experimental So-
cial Psychology, 19, 448–468.
Kruglanski, A. W., & Webster, D. M. (1991). Group members’ reac-
tions to opinion deviates and conformists at varying degrees of
proximity to decision deadline and of environmental noise.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 61, 212–225.
Kruglanski, A. W., & Webster, D. M. (1996). Motivated closing of
the mind: “Seizing” and “freezing. Psychological Review, 103,
263–283.
Kuhn, T. (1996). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1962)
Landau, M. J., Johns, M., Greenberg, J., Pyszczynski, T., Martens,
A., Goldenberg, J. L., et al. (2004). A function of form: Terror
management and structuring the social world. Journal of Per
-
sonality and Social Psychology, 87, 190–210.
Landau, M. J., Solomon, S., Greenberg, J., Cohen, F., Pyszczynski,
T., Arndt, J., et al.. (2004b). Deliver us from evil: The effects of
mortality salience and reminders of 9/11 on support for Presi
-
dent George W. Bush. Personality and Social Psychology Bul
-
letin, 30, 1136–1150.
Leary, M. R. (2004). The function of self-esteem in terror manage
-
ment theory and sociometer theory: Comment on Pyszczynski
et al. (2004). Psychological Bulletin, 130, 478–482.
Leary, M. R., & Baumeister, R. F. (2000). The nature and function of
self-esteem: Sociometer theory. In M. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in
experimental social psychology (Vol. 32, pp. 1–62). San Diego,
CA: Academic.
Leary, M. R., Tambor, E. S., Terdal, S. K., & Downs, D. L. (1995).
Self-esteem as an interpersonal monitor: The sociometer hy
-
pothesis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 68,
518–530.
Lehman, D. R., Ellard, J. H., & Wortman, C. B. (1986). Social sup
-
port for the bereaved: Recipients’ and providers’ perspectives
on what is helpful. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychol
-
ogy, 54, 438–446.
Lemyre, L., & Smith, P. M. (1985). Intergroup discrimination and
self-esteem in the minimal group paradigm. Journal of Person
-
ality and Social Psychology, 49, 660–670.
108
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
Lewin, K. (1935). A dynamic theory of personality: Selected papers
(D. E. Adams & K. E. Zener, Trans.). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Lifton, R. J. (1976). The life of the self. New York: Basic Books.
Long, K., & Spears, R. (1997). The self-esteem hypothesis revisited:
Differentiation and the disaffected. In R. Spears, P. J. Oakes, N.
Ellemers, & S. A. Haslam (Eds.), The social psychology of ste
-
reotyping and group life (pp. 296–317). Oxford, England:
Blackwell.
Mandel, N., & Heine, S. J. (1999). Terror management and market
-
ing: He who dies with the most toys wins. Advances in Con
-
sumer Research, 26, 527–532.
Markus, H. (1977). Self-schemata and processing information about
the self. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 35,
63–78.
Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self: Implica
-
tions for cognition, emotion, and motivation. Psychological Re
-
view, 98, 224–253.
McGregor, H. A., Lieberman, J. D., Greenberg, J., Solomon, S.,
Arndt, J., Simon, L., et al. (1998). Terror management and ag
-
gression: Evidence that mortality salience motivates aggression
against worldview-threatening others. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 74, 590–605.
McGregor, I., & Marigold, D. C. (2003). Defensive zeal and the un
-
certain self: What makes you so sure? Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 85, 838–852.
McGregor, I., Zanna, M. P., & Holmes, J. G. (1998, May). Identity
threat and attitude polarization: An alternative account of ter
-
ror management phenomena. Poster session presented at the
annual meeting of the Midwestern Psychological Association,
Chicago, IL.
McGregor, I., Zanna, M. P., Holmes, J. G., & Spencer, S. J. (2001).
Compensatory conviction in the face of personal uncertainty:
Going to extremes and being oneself. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 80, 472–488.
McKimmie, B. M., Terry, D. J., & Hogg, M. A. (2003). I’m a hypo-
crite, but so is everyone else: Group support and the reduction
of cognitive dissonance. Group Dynamics, 7, 214–224.
Miedema, J., Van den Bos, K., & Vermunt, R. (2006). The influence
of ego threat on reactions to perceived fairness. Manuscript
submitted for publication.
Mikulincer, M., & Florian, V. (2000). Exploring individual differ
-
ences in reactions to mortality salience: Does attachment style
regulate terror management mechanisms? Journal of Personal
-
ity and Social Psychology, 79, 260–273.
Mikulincer, M., & Florian, V. (2002). The effects of mortality sa
-
lience on self-serving attributions: Evidence for the function of
self-esteem as a terror management mechanism. Basic and Ap
-
plied Social Psychology, 24, 261–271.
Mikulincer, M., Florian, V., & Hirschberger, G. (2004). The terror of
death and the quest for love: An existential perspective on close
relationships. In J. Greenberg, S. L. Koole, & T. Pyszczynski
(Eds.), Handbook of experimental existential psychology, (pp.
287–304). New York: Guilford.
Milardo, R. M., Johnson, M. P., & Huston, T. L. (1983). Developing
close relationships: Changing patterns of interaction between
pair members and social networks. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 44, 964–976
Mischel, W., & Morf, C. C. (2003). The self as a psycho-social dy
-
namic processing system: A meta-perspective on a century of
the self in psychology. In M. R. Leary & J. P. Tangney (Eds.),
Handbook of self and identity (pp. 15–43). New York:
Guilford.
Morling, B., Kitayama, S., & Miyamoto, Y. (2002). Cultural practices
emphasize influence in the United States and adjustment in Ja
-
pan. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 311–323.
Muraven, M., & Baumeister, R.F. (1997). Suicide, sex, terror, paraly
-
sis, and other pitfalls of reductionist self-preservation theory.
Psychological Inquiry, 8, 36–40.
Navarette, C. D., Kurzban, R., Fessler, D. M. T., & Kirkpatrick, L. A.
(2004). Anxiety and intergroup bias: Terror management or
coalitional psychology. Group Processes and Intergroup Rela
-
tions, 7, 370–397.
Nazzi, T., & Gopnik, A. (2002). Sorting and acting with objects in
early childhood: An exploration of the use of causal cues. Cog
-
nitive Development, 18, 299–317.
Neuberg, S. L., & Newsom, J. T. (1993). Personal need for structure:
Individual differences in the desire for simpler structure. Jour
-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65, 113–131.
Norenzayan, A., & Hansen, I. (2006). Beliefs in supernatural agents
in the face of death. Personality and Social Psychology, 32,
174–187
Norenzayan, A., & Heine, S. J. (2005). Psychological universals:
What are they and how can we know? Psychological Bulletin,
31, 763789.
Oakes, P. J., & Turner, J. C. (1980). Social categorization and inter
-
group behaviour: Does minimal intergroup discrimination
make social identity more positive? European Journal of Social
Psychology, 10, 295–301.
Ovsiankina, M. (1928). Die Wiederaufnahme unterbrochener
Handlungen [The completion of interrupted acts].
Psychologische Forschung, 11, 302–379.
Park, L. C., & Folkman, S. (1997). Meaning in the context of stress
and coping. Review of General Psychology, 2, 115–144
Paulhus, D. L., & Trapnell, P. D. (1997). Terror management theory:
Extended or overextended? Psychological Inquiry, 8, 40–43.
Peterson, J. (1999). Maps of meaning: The architecture of belief.
New York: Routledge.
Petty, R. E., Cacioppo, J. T., & Goldman, R. (1981). Personal in-
volvement as a determinant of argument-based persuasion.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 41, 847–855.
Piaget, J. (1960). The child’s conception of the world. London:
Routledge.
Pinel, E. C., Long, A. E., Landau, M., & Pyszczynski, T. (2004). I-shar-
ing and the problem of existential isolation. In J. Greenberg, S. L.
Koole, & T. Pyszczynski (Eds.), Handbook of experimental exis-
tential psychology, (pp. 352–368). New York: Guilford.
Pyszczynski, T., Greenberg, J., & Solomon, S. (1997). Why do we
need what we need? A terror management perspective on the
roots of human social motivation. Psychological Inquiry, 8,
1–20.
Pyszczynski, T., Greenberg, J., & Solomon, S. (1999). A
dual-process model of defense against conscious and uncon
-
scious death-related thoughts: An extension of terror manage
-
ment theory. Psychological Review, 106, 835–845.
Pyszczynski, T., Greenberg, J., & Solomon, S. (2004). Why do peo
-
ple need self-esteem? A theoretical and empirical review. Psy
-
chological Bulletin, 130, 435–468.
Pyszczynski, T., Wicklund, R. A., Floresku, S., Koch, H., Gauch, G.,
Solomon, S., et al. (1996). Whistling in the dark: Exaggerated
consensus estimates in response to incidental reminders of mor
-
tality. Psychological Science, 7, 332–336.
Rank, O. (1941). Beyond psychology. New York: Dover.
Reis, H. T. (1990). The role of intimacy in interpersonal relation
-
ships. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 9, 15–30.
Rokeach, M. (1960). The open and closed mind. Oxford, England:
Basic Books.
Rosenblatt, A., Greenberg, J., Solomon, S., Pyszczynski, T., & Lyon,
D. (1989). Evidence for terror management theory: I. The ef
-
fects of mortality salience on reactions to those who violate or
uphold cultural values. Journal of Personality and Social Psy
-
chology, 57, 681–690.
Ross, M. (1989). Relation of implicit theories to the construction of
personal histories. Psychological Review, 96, 341–357.
Rubin, M., & Hewstone, M. (1998). Social identity theory’s self-es
-
teem hypothesis: A review and some suggestions for clarifica
-
tion. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 2, 40–62.
109
MEANING MAINTENANCE MODEL
Saffran, J. R. (2001). Words in a sea of sounds: The output of infant
statistical learning. Cognition, 81, 149–169.
Sartre, J. P. (1957) Being and nothingness: An essay in
phenomenological ontology. London: Methuen.
Schacter, S., & Singer, J. E. (1962). Cognitive, social, and psycho
-
logical determinants of emotional state. Psychological Review,
69, 379–399.
Schimel, J., Simon, L., & Greenberg J. (1999). Stereotypes and ter
-
ror management: Evidence that mortality salience enhances ste
-
reotypic thinking and preferences. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 77, 905–926.
Schmeichel, B. J., & Martens, A. (2005). Self-affirmation and mor
-
tality salience: Affirming values reduces worldview defense
and death-thought accessibility. Personality and Social Psy
-
chology Bulletin, 31, 658667.
Shah, J. Y., Kruglanski, A. W., & Friedman, R. (2003). Goal systems
theory: Integrating the cognitive and motivational aspects of
self-regulation. In S. J. Spencer & S. Fein (Eds). Motivated so
-
cial perception: The Ontario symposium (Vol. 9, pp. 247–275).
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
Shah, J. Y., Kruglanski, A. W., & Thompson, E. P. (1998). Member
-
ship has its (epistemic) rewards: Need for closure effects on
in-group bias. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
75, 383–393.
Shweder, R. A. (1990). Cultural psychology: What is it? In J. W.
Stigler, R. A. Shweder, & G. Herdt (Eds.), Cultural psychology:
Essays on comparative human development (pp. 1–43). Cam
-
bridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Solomon, S., Greenberg, J., & Pyszczynski, T. (1991). A terror man-
agement theory of social behavior: The psychological functions
of self-esteem and cultural worldviews. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.),
Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 24, pp.
93–159). San Diego, CA: Academic.
Steele, C. M. (1988). The psychology of self-affirmation: Sustaining
the integrity of the self. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in ex-
perimental social psychology (Vol. 21, pp. 261–302). San
Diego, CA: Academic.
Steele, C. M., & Liu, T. J. (1983). Dissonance processes as
self-affirmation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
45, 5–19.
Steele, C. M., Spencer, S. J., & Lynch, M. (1993). Self-image resil
-
ience and dissonance: The role of affirmational resources. Jour
-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64, 885–896.
Stone, J., Wiegand, A. W., Cooper, J., & Aronson, E. (1997). When
exemplification fails: Hypocrisy and the motive for
self-integrity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72,
54–65
Swann, W. B., Jr., Stein-Seroussi, A., & Giesler, R. B. (1992). Why
people self-verify. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol
-
ogy, 62, 392–401.
Tajfel, H. (1970). Experiments in intergroup discrimination. Scien
-
tific American, 223(5), 96–102.
Tajfel, H. (1972). Social categorization. In S. Moscovici (Ed.), Intro
-
duction a la psychologie sociale (Vol. 1, pp. 272–302). Paris:
Larousse.
Tajfel, H., Billig, M., Bundy, R. P., & Flament, C. (1971). Social cat
-
egorization and intergroup behavior. European Journal of So
-
cial Psychology, 1, 149–177.
Tajfel, H., & Turner, J. C. (1979). An integrative theory of intergroup
conflict. In W. G. Austin & S. Worchel (Eds.), The social psy
-
chology of intergroup relations (pp. 33–47). Monterey, CA:
Brooks/Cole.
Taubman Ben-Ari, O., Findler, L., & Mikulincer, M. (2002). The ef
-
fects of mortality salience on relationship strivings and beliefs:
The moderating role of attachment style. British Journal of So
-
cial Psychology, 41, 419–441.
Tesser, A. (2000). On the confluence of self-esteem maintenance
mechanisms. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 4,
290–299.
Tesser, A. (2001). On the plasticity of self-defense. Current Direc
-
tions in Psychological Science, 10, 66–69.
Tesser, A., & Cornell, D. P. (1991). On the confluence of self processes.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 27, 501–526.
Tesser, A., Crepaz, N., Beach, S. R. H., Cornell, D., & Collins, J. C.
(2000). Confluence of self-esteem regulation mechanisms: On
integrating the self-zoo. Personality and Social Psychology
Bulletin, 26, 1476–1489.
Thompson, S., & Janigan, A. (1988). Life schemes: A framework for
understanding the search for meaning. Journal of Social and
Clinical Psychology, 7, 260–280.
Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Tomasello, M., Kruger, A. C., & Ratner, H. H. (1993). Cultural
learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16, 495–552.
Triandis, H. C. (1989). The self and social behavior in differing cul
-
tural contexts. Psychological Review, 96, 506–520.
Turner, J. C. (1975). Social comparison and social identity: Some
prospects for intergroup behaviour. European Journal of Social
Psychology, 5, 5–34.
Turner, J. C. (1978). Social categorization and social discrimination
in the minimal group paradigm. In H. Tajfel (Ed.), Differentia
-
tion between social groups: Studies in the social psychology of
intergroup relations (pp. 101–140). London: Academic.
Turner, J. C. (1982). Towards a cognitive redefinition of the social
group. In H. Tajfel (Ed.), Social identity and intergroup relations
(pp.15–40). Cambridge, England: CambridgeUniversityPress.
Vallacher, R. R., & Wegner, D. M. (1987). What do people think
they’re doing? Action identification and human behavior. Psy-
chological Review, 94, 3–15.
Van den Bos, K. (2001). Reactions to perceived fairness: The impact
of mortality salience and self-esteem on ratings of negative af-
fect. Social Justice Research, 14, 1–23.
Van den Bos, K., & Miedema, J. (2000). Toward understanding why
fairness matters: The influence of mortality salience on reac
-
tions to procedural fairness. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 79, 355–366.
Van den Bos, K., Poortvliet, M., Maas, M., Miedema, J., & Van den
Ham, E. (2005). An enquiry concerning the principles of cul
-
tural norms and values: The impact of uncertainty and mortality
salience on reactions to violations and bolstering of cultural
worldviews. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 41,
91–113.
Vaughan, D. (1986). Uncoupling. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Webster, D. M., & Kruglanski, A. W. (1998). In W. Stroebe & M.
Hewstone (Eds.), European Review of Social Psychology (Vol.
8, pp. 133–173). New York: Wiley.
Wisman, A., & Koole, S. L. (2003). Hiding in the crowd: Can mortal
-
ity salience promote affiliation with others who oppose one’s
worldview? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 84,
511– 526.
Zadro, L., Williams, K. D., & Richardson, R. (2004). Howlow can you
go: Ostracism by a computer is sufficient to lower self-reported
levels of belonging, control, self-esteem, and meaningful exis
-
tence.Journal ofExperimental Social Psychology, 40,560–567.
Zillman, D., Katcher, A. H., & Milavsky, B. (1972). Excitation trans
-
fer from physical exercise to subsequent aggressive behavior.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 83, 247–259.
110
HEINE, PROULX, VOHS
... For diabetes, you have to pay attention when you go out for meals, lots of things to care about. (No. 19) Heart disease and diabetes. I had three stents already. ...
... Hypertension in older adults serves as both a challenge and a catalyst for significant life reevaluation and transformation. Research by Heine et al. [19] and Park [20] reveals how this condition prompts older individuals to rethink their approach to health and life, leading to increased selfawareness and active engagement in health management. Despite recognizing hypertension as a part of aging, many celebrate their resilience and capacity for self-care, contrasting their situation with that of others who may be less capable and functioning. ...
... When people get older, they get sick. It is a natural thing . . . In the past two years, I often went out for exercise, go out to meet friends and etc. Once life is interesting, I don't mind the sickness (hypertension), then my mood is good. (No. 19) Hypertension is common among old people. You know, the older more or less has symptoms anyway . . . I see others had dementia, can't get out of bed or what, but I am still capable. [That is] enough. (No. 17) Additionally, the process of managing hypertension extends beyond mere physical health strategies and involves a deeper exploratio ...
Article
Full-text available
Objectives Hypertension stands as the most prevalent chronic disease globally, making self-care a crucial determinant in the trajectory of the illness. Yet, a significant challenge faced by many elderly individuals with hypertension is the accurate perception of the condition as an embodied symptom. The aim of this paper is to delve into the illness perceptions of older adults with hypertension and further gain insights into their self-management efforts. Methods This qualitative study involved 20 older adults living in community settings, all clinically diagnosed with hypertension. Data collection was conducted using semi-structured interviews from May to August 2022, and the data was subsequently analyzed through thematic analysis. Results Based on data analysis, two primary themes emerged: Illness Ambiguity regarding Hypertension and Self-Mastery of Holistic Health. Illness ambiguity regarding hypertension was manifested by incidental discovery and elusive triggers of recurrence, hypertension management approaches and emotional complexities associated with aging. The participants demonstrated self-mastery as an effective strategy in coping with hypertension as well as other health problems, including psychological flexibility, active body ownership, and meaning-making for illness acceptance. Conclusions Older adults with hypertension faced illness ambiguity regarding their condition; however, they effectively coped by exercising self-mastery and adopting holistic health strategies to maintain their overall well-being. Future interventions in hypertension therapy and psychosocial care should be customized, taking into account these embodied experiences and the sociocultural contexts of the patients.
... In the context of autobiographical narratives, 'meaning' consists of the relations we draw between salient aspects about our experience (e.g., people, places, events, concepts) (Baumeister, 1991;Heine et al., 2006;Park, 2010;Proulx and Inzlicht, 2012). Meaning, on this account, resides in relationships between simple aspects of our experience (e.g., an object and a smell) or complex ones (e.g., an emotion and a familiar location), that often entail a network of associations among multiple elements. ...
... Meaning, on this account, resides in relationships between simple aspects of our experience (e.g., an object and a smell) or complex ones (e.g., an emotion and a familiar location), that often entail a network of associations among multiple elements. Heine et al. (2006) add that meaning concerns the iterative construction and restoring of expected relations between relevant information that humans construct about aspects of the world, and as such, it entails establishing, maintaining, and restoring a sense of familiarity (or predictability) with the world. Of course, simply linking salient elements of our experiences does not necessarily result in the construction of coherent ensembles. ...
... This process can be seen as important for the exploratory phase of active inference, also known as epistemic foraging (Parr and Friston, 2017), where surprising or new facets of environments are encountered and new, updated models of future events need to be constructed. The meaning-making process is seen in the literature as an adaptive response to the occurrence of unexpected circumstances, when expectations are not met, and an imaginative reorganization of our representations of ourselves and our environments is needed (Heine et al., 2006;Park, 2010;Proulx and Inzlicht, 2012). As such, the meaning making process that is at play in narrative self-fashioning can be cast as active inference insofar as it involves resolving uncertainty by ascribing new meaning to unfamiliar, ambiguous, or disruptive events and integrating them with the known, familiar aspects of our experience to update what is now to be expected in the future. ...
Article
Full-text available
While the ubiquity and importance of narratives for human adaptation is widely recognized, there is no integrative framework for understanding the roles of narrative in human adaptation. Research has identified several cognitive and social functions of narratives that are conducive to well-being and adaptation as well as to coordinated social practices and enculturation. In this paper, we characterize the cognitive and social functions of narratives in terms of active inference, to support the claim that one of the main adaptive functions of narrative is to generate more useful (i.e., accurate, parsimonious) predictions for the individual, as well as to coordinate group action (over multiple timescales) through shared predictions about collective behavior. Active inference is a theory that depicts the fundamental tendency of living organisms to adapt by proactively inferring the causes of their sensations (including their own actions). We review narrative research on identity, event segmentation, episodic memory, future projections, storytelling practices, enculturation, and master narratives. We show how this research dovetails with the active inference framework and propose an account of the cognitive and social functions of narrative that emphasizes that narratives are for the future—even when they are focused on recollecting or recounting the past. Understanding narratives as cognitive and cultural tools for mutual prediction in social contexts can guide research on narrative in adaptive behavior and psychopathology, based on a parsimonious mechanistic model of some of the basic adaptive functions of narrative.
... based on their connection with their own selves (King & Hicks, 2021). Additionally, Heine et al. (2006) proposed that a crucial aspect of meaning lies in the relationality between individuals and the events happening around them, as this connection shapes their understanding of the world. However, despite these insights, empirical studies have yet to confirm the association between self-concept clarity and coherence. ...
... Regarding the within-person relationship, all three precursors exhibited significant mediation effects, along with a significant direct association between daily self-concept clarity and daily meaning. These findings provide support for H2b and align with previous theories (Adler et al., 2016;Costin & Vignoles, 2020;Gregg & Sedikides, 2017;Heine et al., 2006). The findings suggest that when individuals had a clearer understanding of themselves, they were more likely to have a purpose to strive for, perceive a sense of coherence throughout the day, feel a sense of personal importance, and ultimately experience a higher sense of meaning on that particular day. ...
Article
Full-text available
Despite the theoretical significance of self-concept clarity in meaning in life in Western thinking, there has been limited empirical investigation in collectivistic cultures. Consequently, the mechanism and boundary conditions of this effect remain unknown in such cultural contexts. To address this gap, we employed a daily-diary method spanning a period of 10 days, which allowed us to examine both the between-person and within-person effects of self-concept clarity on meaning in life, as well as the mediating role of three precursors of meaning (i.e., coherence, purpose, and significance), and the moderating role of independent self-construal among 83 Chinese participants. Multilevel regressions analyses demonstrated that individuals with higher trait self-concept clarity perceived higher meaning in their daily lives (b = 0.28, SE = 0.08, p = .001); and on days when individuals experienced higher daily self-concept clarity than typical, their sense of meaning on that day also tended to be higher (b = 0.39, SE = 0.04, p < .001). Multilevel mediation models showed that at the between-person level, trait self-concept clarity predicted daily meaning through the mediation of significance only (b = 0.15, SE = 0.05, p = .002), while at the within-person level, daily self-concept clarity predicted daily meaning through all three precursors (0.03 < bs < 0.13, ps < .05). The effect of both trait and daily self-concept clarity were stronger among those with a low (vs. high) independent self-construal. Finally, there was a positive lagged effect of daily self-concept clarity on daily meaning (β = 0.12, SE = 0.05, p = .014). These findings highlight the importance of cultivating a clear self-concept for experiencing meaning in daily life, particularly for those with a low independent self-construal in a collectivistic culture.
... When subsequent experiences fail to match our schemata, Piaget "believed that the corresponding disequilibrium motivates us to find other ways to make these experiences make sense" . These and related observations prompted the meaning maintenance model (MMM) (Heine et al., 2006), at the core of which is "the proposition that humans are inexhaustible meaning makers" (p. 91). ...
Article
Full-text available
The human need to find meaning in life and the human need for connection may be two sides of the same coin, a coin forged in the developmental crucible of attachment. Our need for meaningfulness can be traced to our developmental need for connection in the attachment relationship. The free energy principle dictates that in order to resist a natural tendency towards disorder self-organizing systems must generate models that predict the hidden causes of phenomenal experience. In other words, they must make sense of things. In both an evolutionary and ontogenetic sense, the narrative self develops as a model that makes sense of experience. However, the self-model skews the interpretation of experience towards that which is predictable, or already “known.” One may say it causes us to “take things personally.” Meaning is felt more acutely when defenses are compromised, when the narrative self is offline. This enables meaning-making that is less egocentrically motivated. Dreams, psychosis, and psychedelic states offer glimpses of how we make sense of things absent a coherent narrative self. This has implications for the way we understand such states, and lays bare the powerful reach of attachment in shaping what we experience as meaningful.
... Among the multiple identities they possess, consumers are more likely to respond positively to stimuli that resonate with their currently accessible identities (Aaker et al., 2001;Hong et al., 2000;Lau-Gesk, 2003). Consumers are drawn toward products that reflect their identity because they innately seek coherence, meaning, and control (Heine et al., 2006;Swann, 2012). The desire to maintain positive self-views leads consumers to perceive identity-consistent information as more relevant than identity-inconsistent information (Wheeler et al., 2005). ...
Article
Full-text available
It is widely believed that younger generations are at the forefront of sustainability efforts. Given the significance of fostering greater consumer participation in sustainable consumption, this perception prompts an intriguing question: If consumers associate sustainability with younger individuals, can simply instilling a sense of youthfulness increase their engagement in sustainable consumption, regardless of their actual age? Building upon previous research on subjective age—that is, how old one feels—and consumer identity, we propose that consumers will gravitate towards sustainable products when they feel younger than older. This is because such products align well with their perceived age identity, creating a perception of fit. The findings across three studies provide converging evidence that simply making consumers feel younger can result in an increased preference for sustainable products. Study 1 demonstrated that feeling younger increased the selection of more sustainable products over less sustainable ones. Study 2 showed that this effect is mediated by the perceived fit. Study 3 further supported the underlying mechanism by revealing that the focal effect was mitigated when the association between sustainability and younger age was weakened. Study 4 replicated the focal effect in a consequential choice setting. Finally, Study 5 confirmed the proposed effect by using trait subjective age as a predictor.
... The meaning maintenance model [13], integrates the previous strategies. The theory suggests that humans are innate meaning seekers with four main basic needs: the need for certainty, the need to belong, the need for self-esteem, and the need for spiritual permanence. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Background Certainty has an important meaning for an individual, as it gives a sense of security and fulfillment. However, uncertainty occurs every day in real life, causing anxiety and aversion. Therefore, individuals take measures to cope with uncertain feelings. Previous studies have hinted at the important role of approach motivation in alleviating uncertainty and the possibility that loss of a sense of control may induce approach motivations and behaviors, but there is no clear empirical research demonstrating this mechanism. We explored the role of uncertainty in the induction of approach motivation and the moderating role of uncertainty tolerance. Method In the present study, we measured subjects' uncertainty tolerance trait, in addition to the classical forced-choice gambling task, and measured 20 subjects' brainwave changes in uncertain situations, using the lateralization of approach-motivated brain activity to test the above hypotheses using the FRN and the P300 as the response indexes. Result Subjects who received the feedback "+/-/?" in the gambling task were followed by the production of FRN in the right brain and then P300 in the left brain, and the peaks of the P300 wave in the "+" and "-" feedback cases were significantly lower than those of "?". In addition, the peak difference between the left and right brain P300 waves was significantly higher in individuals with low uncertainty tolerance than in those with low uncertainty tolerance. Conclusion We found that subjects experience significant uncertainty after making a high-risk versus high-reward choice and uncertainty is accompanied by approach motivation. After we grouped the subjects according to the level of uncertainty tolerance, we found that the difference between left and right brain P300 was significantly smaller in the high-tolerance group than in the low-tolerance group, suggesting that uncertainty tolerance plays a moderating role in uncertainty-induced approach motivation.
Article
As a political ideology, conservatism is primarily focused on maintaining and restoring past society. This aspect is so central that conservatives’ support for policies is increased simply by framing them as a return to the past. Until now, the underlying process of this temporal framing effect is unclear. Drawing on theories of conservatism as motivated social cognition, four preregistered studies (N total = 2,405) test the hypothesis that it results from conservatives’ epistemic and existential beliefs about the past. Studies 1 and 2 demonstrate that American conservatives’ preference for past-focused political communication is blocked if the past is perceived to be inconsistent with these beliefs. Studies 3 and 4 (a representative UK sample replication) find that the effect is mediated by epistemic and existential beliefs about the past. This research theoretically integrates the earlier-established conservative temporal framing effect into the wider literature of conservatism as motivated social cognition.
Article
Social and political psychologists have focused on how liberals and conservatives differ from one another and have developed a vast literature on individual differences and fixed attributes that distinguish ideological groups. However, ideological orientations might be more contextual and flexible than what is often portrayed in research. We present a novel look at ideological variability as an intra group phenomenon that makes liberals and conservatives nuanced, heterogeneous, and more similar to one another—important perspectives for reducing ideological stereotyping and polarization. In this paper, we review patterns showing ideological variability and overlap in thinking, emotions, attitudes, and behaviors across the lifespan, geographical regions, status groups, and diverse cultures around the world. By understanding the social psychological and situational factors associated with intragroup variability in ideology, we can develop more culturally inclusive models of ideology and map out better solutions to polarization.
Article
Full-text available
Study 1 participants' self-integrity (C. M. Steele, 1988) was threatened by deliberative mind-set (S. E. Taylor & P. M. Gollwitzer, 1995) induced uncertainty. They masked the uncertainty with more extreme conviction about social issues. An integrity-repair exercise after the threat, however, eliminated uncertainty and the conviction response. In Study 2, the same threat caused clarified values and more self-consistent personal goals. Two other uncertainty-related threats, mortality salience and temporal discontinuity, caused similar responses: more extreme intergroup bias in Study 3, and more self-consistent personal goals and identifications in Study 4. Going to extremes and being oneself are seen as 2 modes of compensatory conviction used to defend against personal uncertainty. Relevance to cognitive dissonance and authoritarianism theories is discussed, and a new perspective on terror management theory (J. Greenberg, S. Solomom, & T. Pyszczynski, 1997) is proposed.
Article
Full-text available
Five studies examined the contribution of attachment style to mortality salience effects. In Study 1, mortality salience led to more severe judgments of transgressions only among anxious–ambivalent and avoidant persons but not among secure persons. In addition, whereas anxious–ambivalent persons showed immediate and delayed increases in severity judgments, avoidant persons showed this response only after a delay period. In Study 2, anxious–ambivalent persons showed immediate and delayed increases in death-thought accessibility after death reminders. Avoidant and secure persons showed this effect only after a delay period. Study 3 revealed that worldview defense in response to mortality salience reduced death-thought accessibility only among avoidant persons. Studies 4–5 revealed that mortality salience led to an increase in the sense of symbolic immortality as well as in the desire of intimacy only among secure persons, but not among avoidant and anxious–ambivalent persons.
Article
Full-text available
This article focuses on the question of why fairness matters to people. On the basis of fairness heuristic theory, the authors argue that people especially need fairness when they are uncertain about things that are important to them. Following terror management theory, the authors focus on a basic kind of human uncertainty: fear of death. Integrating these two theoretical frameworks, it is proposed that thinking about their mortality should make fairness a more important issue to people. The findings of three experiments support the authors’ line of reasoning: Asking participants to think about their mortality led to stronger fair process effects (positive effects of perceived procedural fairness on subsequent reactions) than not asking them to think about mortality. It is argued that these findings suggest that fairness especially matters to people when they are uncertain about fundamental aspects of human life such as human mortality.
Article
Full-text available
It is assumed that people seek positive self-regard; that is, they are motivated to possess, enhance, and maintain positive self-views. The cross-cultural generalizability of such motivations was addressed by examining Japanese culture. Anthropological, sociological, and psychological analyses revealed that many elements of Japanese culture are incongruent with such motivations. Moreover, the empirical literature provides scant evidence for a need for positive self-regard among Japanese and indicates that a self-critical focus is more characteristic of Japanese. It is argued that the need for self-regard must be culturally variant because the constructions of self and regard themselves differ across cultures. The need for positive self-regard, as it is currently conceptualized, is not a universal, but rather is rooted in significant aspects of North American culture. Conventional interpretations of positive self-regard are too narrow to encompass the Japanese experience.
Article
Full-text available
Distinct defensive processes are activated by conscious and nonconscious but accessible thoughts of death. Proximal defenses, which entail suppressing death-related thoughts or pushing the problem of death into the distant future by denying one's vulnerability, are rational, threat-focused, and activated when thoughts of death are in current focal attention. Distal terror management defenses, which entail maintaining self-esteem and faith in one's cultural worldview, function to control the potential for anxiety that results from knowing that death is inevitable. These defenses are experiential, are not related to the problem of death in any semantic or logical way, and are increasingly activated as the accessibility of death-related thoughts increases, up to the point at which such thoughts enter consciousness and proximal threat-focused defenses are initiated. Experimental evidence for this analysis is presented.
Article
Full-text available
Two experiments investigated how the dissonance that follows a hypocritical behavior is reduced when 2 alternatives are available: a direct strategy (changing behavior to make it less hypocritical) or an indirect strategy (the affirmation of an unrelated positive aspect of the self). In Experiment 1, after dissonance was aroused by hypocrisy, significantly more participants chose to reduce dissonance directly, despite the clear availability of a self-affirmation strategy. In Experiment 2, participants again chose direct resolution of their hypocritical discrepancy, even when the opportunity to affirm the self held more importance for their global self-worth. The discussion focuses on the mechanisms that influence how people select among readily available strategies for dissonance reduction.
Article
Full-text available
It was predicted that high self-esteem Ss (HSEs) would rationalize an esteem-threatening decision less than low self-esteem Ss (LSEs), because HSEs presumably had more favorable self-concepts with which to affirm, and thus repair, their overall sense of self-integrity. This prediction was supported in 2 experiments within the “free-choice” dissonance paradigm—one that manipulated self-esteem through personality feedback and the other that varied it through selection of HSEs and LSEs, but only when Ss were made to focus on their self-concepts. A 3rd experiment countered an alternative explanation of the results in terms of mood effects that may have accompanied the experimental manipulations. The results were discussed in terms of the following: (a) their support for a resources theory of individual differences in resilience to self-image threats—an extension of self-affirmation theory, (b) their implications for self-esteem functioning, and (c) their implications for the continuing debate over self-enhancement versus self-consistency motivation.
Article
Full-text available
Four experiments examined freely interacting groups to investigate the determinants of group members' reactions to opinion deviates and conformists. In the 1st experiment, the deviate was rejected more when he or she articulated the dissenting opinion in close proximity to the group-decision deadline versus at an earlier point in the group discussion. In the 2nd, 3rd, and 4th experiment, the deviate was rejected more when the group discussion was carried out in a noisy versus a quiet environment. Furthermore, when the conformist's contributions to the group's attempts to reach consensus were made salient (in Experiment 4), he or she was evaluated more positively in a noisy versus a quiet environment. The results were discussed in terms of the notion that group members' tendency to denigrate a deviate or extol a conformist may be stronger when their need for collective cognitive closure is heightened.
Article
Full-text available
This study examined daily stress processes among 75 married couples across 20 assessments during a 6-month period. The somatic and psychological effects of common everyday hassles were investigated. Overall, there was a significant relationship between daily stress and the occurrence of both concurrent and subsequent health problems such as flu, sore throat, headaches, and backaches. The relationship of daily stress to mood disturbance was more complex. The negative effects of stress on mood were limited to a single day, with the following day characterized by mood scores that were better than usual. Furthermore, striking individual differences were found in the extent to which daily stress was associated with health and mood across time. Participants with unsupportive social relationships and low self-esteem were more likely to experience an increase in psychological and somatic problems both on and following stressful days than were participants high in self-esteem and social support. These data suggest that persons with low psychosocial resources are vulnerable to illness and mood disturbance when their stress levels increase, even if they generally have little stress in their lives.