ArticlePDF Available

A Convex Stochastic Optimization Problem Arising from PortfolioSelection

Authors:

Abstract

A continuous-time financial portfolio selection model with expected utility maximization typically boils down to solving a (static) convex stochastic optimization problem in terms of the terminal wealth, with a budget constraint. In literature the latter is solved by assuming {\it a priori} that the problem is well-posed (i.e., the supremum value is finite) and a Lagrange multiplier exists (and as a consequence the optimal solution is attainable). In this paper it is first shown, via various counter-examples, neither of these two assumptions needs to hold, and an optimal solution does not necessarily exist. These anomalies in turn have important interpretations in and impacts on the portfolio selection modeling and solutions. Relations among the non-existence of the Lagrange multiplier, the ill-posedness of the problem, and the non-attainability of an optimal solution are then investigated. Finally, explicit and easily verifiable conditions are derived which lead to finding the unique optimal solution.
Mathematical Finance, Vol. 18, No. 1 (January 2008), 171–183
A CONVEX STOCHASTIC OPTIMIZATION PROBLEM ARISING
FROM PORTFOLIO SELECTION
HANQING JIN,ZUO QUAN XU,AND XUN YUZHOU
The University of Oxford
A continuous-time financial portfolio selection model with expected utility maxi-
mization typically boils down to solving a (static) convex stochastic optimization prob-
lem in terms of the terminal wealth, with a budget constraint. In literature the latter is
solved by assuming a priori that the problem is well-posed (i.e., the supremum value
is finite) and a Lagrange multiplier exists (and as a consequence the optimal solution
is attainable). In this paper it is first shown that, via various counter-examples, neither
of these two assumptions needs to hold, and an optimal solution does not necessarily
exist. These anomalies in turn have important interpretations in and impacts on the
portfolio selection modeling and solutions. Relations among the non-existence of the
Lagrange multiplier, the ill-posedness of the problem, and the non-attainability of an
optimal solution are then investigated. Finally, explicit and easily verifiable conditions
are derived which lead to finding the unique optimal solution.
KEY WORDS: portfolio selection, convex stochastic optimization, Lagrange multiplier, well-
posedness, attainability.
1. INTRODUCTION
Given a probability space (, F,P), consider the following constrained stochastic opti-
mization problem:
Maximize Eu(X)
subject to E[Xξ]=a,X0isarandom variable,
(1.1)
where a>0isaparameter, ξ>0agiven scalar-valued random variable, u(·):IR
+→ IR +
a twice differentiable, strictly increasing, strictly concave function with u(0) =0,u(0+)=
+∞,u(+∞)=0. Define V(a)=supE[Xξ]=a,X0is a r.v. Eu(X).
It is well known that many continuous-time financial portfolio selection problems
with expected utility maximization boil down to solving problem (1.1). In the context
of a portfolio model, u(·)isthe utility function (all the assumed properties on u(·)have
economic interpretations), ξis the so-called pricing kernel or state price density, ais the
initial wealth (hence the first constraint is the budget constraint), and Xis the terminal
wealth to be determined. Once an optimal Xto (1.1) is found, the portfolio replicating
Xis the optimal portfolio for the original dynamic portfolio choice problem, if the
The study is supported by the RGC Earmarked Grants CUHK 4175/03E, CUHK418605, and Croucher
Senior Research Fellowship.
Manuscript received February 2006; final revision received July 2006.
Address correspondence to Xun Yu Zhou, Mathematical Institute and Nomura Centre for Mathematical
Finance, University of Oxford, 24-29 St Giles’, Oxford, OX1 3LB, UK; e-mail: zhouxy@maths.ox.ac.uk.
C
2008 The Authors. Journal compilation C
2008 Blackwell Publishing Inc., 350 Main St., Malden, MA 02148,
USA, and 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK.
171
172 H. JIN, Z. Q. XU, AND X. Y. ZHOU
market is complete. For details see, e.g., Cvitanic and Karatzas (1992), Karatzas (1997),
Karatzas and Shreve (1998), and Korn (1997).
In literature (1.1) is usually solved by the Lagrange method, which is summarized in
the following theorem.
THEOREM 1.1. If (1.1) admits an optimal solution Xwhose objective value is finite,
then there exists λ>0such that X=(u)1(λξ ).Conversely, if E[(u)1(λξ )ξ]=a<+∞
and E[u((u)1(λξ ))] <+∞,then X =(u)1(λξ)is optimal for (1.1) with parameter a.
This theorem provides an efficient scheme to find the optimal solution for Problem (1.1):
For any a>0, solve the Lagrange equation E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]=aif one could —to deter-
mine a Lagrange multiplier λ, and then X=(u)1(λξ)isthe optimal (automatically
unique as the utility function is strictly concave) solution for (1.1), if Eu(X)isfinite.
However, there are many issues about Problem (1.1) that are left untouched by the
preceding theorem/scheme. To elaborate, in general there are the following progressive
issues related to an optimization problem such as (1.1):
(i) Feasibility:whether there is at least one solution satisfying all the constraints
involved. For (1.1), since X=ais a feasible solution, the feasibility is not an
issue.1
(ii) Well-posedness:whether the supremum value of the problem with a non-empty
feasible set is finite (in which case the problem is called well-posed) or +∞
(ill-posed). An ill-posed problem is a mis-formulated one: the trade-off is not
set right so one could always push the objective value to be arbitrarily high.2
(iii) Attainability:whether a well-posed problem admits an optimal solution. It may
or may not.
(iv) Uniqueness:whether an attainable problem has a unique optimal solution. It
is not an issue for (1.1), since uniqueness holds automatically due to the strict
concavity of the utility function.
Clearly, Theorem 1.1 covers only the case when the problem is well-posed and the
attainability holds, by assuming a priori that a Lagrange multiplier exists [indeed, in the
context of portfolio selection the existing work always assumes that the Lagrange multi-
plier exists; see theorem 2.2.2 on page 7 of Karatzas (1997) and page 65 of Korn (1997)].3
Moreover, in theorem 2.2.2 on page 7 of Karatzas (1997) and assumption 6.2 on page 773
of Cvitanic and Karatzas (1992), it is assumed up front that the underlying problem is
well-posed.4In this paper, we will first show, through various counter-examples, that none
of the aforementioned assumptions that have all along been taken for granted needs to
hold true. Then, we will address the following questions: When does the Lagrange mul-
tiplier exist? What if it does not? What does it have to do with the well-posedness and
1Feasibility could be by itself an interesting problem if more complex constraints are involved. See
Section 3 of Bielecki et al. (2005) for an example.
2Again, well-posedness is an important, sometimes very difficult, problem in its own right; see
Jin and Zhou (2008) for a behavioral portfolioselection model where the well-posedness becomes an eminent
issue. Also see Korn and Kraft (2004) for more ill-posed examples.
3In these references it is assumed that f(λ)=E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]<+∞ for any λ>0, which is equivalent to
the existence of the Lagrange multiplier for any a>0; see Section 2 for details.
4Some of the references cited here deal with models with consumptions; yet the essence of the Lagrange
method remains the same.
CONVEX STOCHASTIC OPTIMIZATION PROBLEM ARISING FROM PORTFOLIO SELECTION 173
attainability? What are the conditions ensuring the existence of a unique optimal solution
for (1.1) for a given a>0orforany a>0?
The aim of this paper is to give a thorough treatment of (1.1), including answers to
the above questions. In particular, Section 2 reveals the possibility of non-existence of
the Lagrange multiplier. Section 3 studies the implications of the non-existence of the
Lagrange multiplier, and Section 4 shows the possibility of ill-posedness even with the
existence of the Lagrange multiplier. Finally, Section 5 presents easily verifiable conditions
for uniquely solving (1.1).
2. NON-EXISTENCE OF LAGRANGE MULTIPLIER
It is possible that the Lagrange multiplier simply does not exist, which will be demon-
strated in this section via several examples.
First off, define
f(λ)=E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]>0.(2.1)
Then f(·)isnon-increasing (notice that f(·)may take value +∞). The following lemma
is evident given the monotonicity of (u)1(·) and the monotone convergence theorem.
LEMMA 2.1. If f (λ0)<+∞ for some λ0>0, then f (·)is continuous on (λ0,+∞)and
right continuous at λ0,with f (+∞)=0.
It follows from Lemma 2.1 that if f(λ0)<+∞ for some λ0>0, then the Lagrange
multiplier exists for any 0 <aa0:=E[(u)1(λ0ξ)ξ]. In particular, if
f(λ)<+∞ ∀λ>0,(2.2)
then the Lagrange multiplier exists for any a>0. This is why in existing literature (2.2)
is usually assumed up front [see, e.g. (2.2.11) on page 37 of Karatzas (1997) and (24) on
page 65 of Korn (1997)]. Now, we are to show that this assumption may not hold even
for simple cases.
EXAMPLE 2.1. Take u(x)=x,x0,P(ξt)=1et,t0. In this
example, u(x)=1
2x,(u)1(y)=(2y)2, and f(λ)=E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]=1
4λ2Eξ1=+
for any λ>0. Therefore E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]=aadmits no solution for any a>0.
In the above example the Lagrange multiplier does not exist for any a >0. In the
following examples, Lagrange multipliers exist for some a >0, and do not for other
a>0.
EXAMPLE 2.2. Define p(x)=ex1xx2/2!x3/3!
x2=+∞
n=2
xn
(n+2)! ,g(x)=p(1
x),h(x)=
g1(x),x>0. Take
u(x)=
xh(x)+1/h(x)
0
p(y)
y2dy,x>0,
0,x=0,
and P(ξt)=1e1/t,t>0; or 1follows the exponential distribution with
parameter 1.
In this example, p(·)isstrictly increasing with p(0+)=0,p(+∞)=+; hence g(·)
is strictly decreasing with g(0+)=+,g(+∞)=0, and h(·)iswell-defined and strictly
decreasing with h(0+)=+,h(+∞)=0. All these functions are smooth.
174 H. JIN, Z. Q. XU, AND X. Y. ZHOU
For the utility function u(·), notice that x
0
p(y)
y2dy =x
0
n=0
yn
(n+4)! dy =+∞
n=0
xn+1
(n+4)!(n+1)
is well-defined for any x>0, and
lim
x0+xh(x)=lim
y→+∞ g(y)y=lim
y→+∞ p1
yy=0,
which means that u(·)isright-continuous at 0. Furthermore, for any x>0
u(x)=h(x)+xh(x)p(1/h(x))
1/h(x)2
h(x)
h(x)2
=h(x)+xh(x)p(1/h(x)) h(x)
=h(x)+xh(x)g(h(x)) h(x)
=h(x).
Therefore u(·)isconcave and u(0+)=h(0+)=+,u(+∞)=h(+∞)=0. Moreover,
u(x)=h(x), and (u)1(y)=g(y)=+∞
n=2
1
(n+2)!yn.Onthe other hand, from the distribu-
tion of ξit follows easily that Eξn=n!forany nIN.
Now let us calculate f(λ)=E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]forany λ>0:
f(λ)=E[g(λξ)ξ]
=E+∞
n=2
1
(n+2)!λnξ(n1)
=+∞
n=2
(n1)!
(n+2)!λn
=+∞
n=2
1
(n+2)(n+1)n1
λn
.
By the convergence of series, we know that f(λ)<+∞ if and only if λ1.
Define a1=f(1) =E[(u)1(ξ)ξ]=+∞
n=2
1
(n+2)(n+1)n=1
12 . Then for any 0 <aa1,
we can find a Lagrange multiplier λ1 such that E[(u)1(λξ )ξ]=a.Onthe other hand,
the Lagrange multiplier is non-existent when a>a1.
In the preceding examples ξis related to the exponential distribution, whereas in
applying to portfolio selection ξis typically lognormal. The next example shows such a
case.
EXAMPLE 2.3. Take a positive random variable ξsatisfying 0 <E[ξ(n1)]<+∞n
1 and limn→+∞ E[ξ(n1)]
E[ξn]=0(e.g., when ξis lognormal). Define an=1
n2E[ξ(n1)],n2,
and p(x)=+∞
n=2anxn,g(x)=p(1
x),h(x)=g1(x),x>0. Take
u(x)=
xh(x)+1/h(x)
0
p(y)
y2dy,x>0,
0,x=0.
Exactly the same analysis as in Example 2.2 yields that u(·)isautility function satisfying
all the required conditions, with u(x)=h(x) and (u)1(x)=g(x)=+∞
n=2anxn.
CONVEX STOCHASTIC OPTIMIZATION PROBLEM ARISING FROM PORTFOLIO SELECTION 175
Now, for any λ>0,
f(λ)=E[g(λξ)ξ]=E+∞
n=2
anλnξ(n1)=+∞
n=2
1
n2λn.
Hence f(λ)<+∞ if and only if λ1. As a result, the Lagrange multiplier exists if and
only if 0 <aa1,where a1=f(1) =E[(u)1(ξ)ξ]=+∞
n=2
1
n2=π26
6.
3. IMPLICATIONS OF NON-EXISTENCE OF LAGRANGE MULTIPLIER
So, if the Lagrange multiplier does not exist, what can we say about the underlying
optimization problem (1.1)? Theorem 1.1 implies that the non-existence of the Lagrange
multiplier is an indication of either the ill-posedness or the non-attainability of (1.1). In
this section we elaborate on this.
THEOREM 3.1. If E[(u)1(λξ )ξ]=+for any λ>0, then V(a)=+for any a >0.
Proof . Fix λ0>0 and a>0. Since E[(u)1(λ0ξ)ξ]=+, one can find a set AF
such that E[(u)1(λ0ξ)ξ1A](a,+∞). Define h(λ)=E[(u)1(λξ)ξ1A], λ[λ0,+∞).
Then h(·)isnon-increasing and continuous on [λ0,+∞) with h(+∞)=0; hence there
exists λ1
0such that h(λ1)=a.
Denote X1=(u)1(λ1ξ)1A,which is a feasible solution for Problem (1.1) with pa-
rameter a, and V(a)E[u(X1)1A]E[X1u(X1)1A]=E[(u)1(λ1ξ)λ1ξ1A]=λ1a>
λ0a. (Here we have used the fact that u(x)xu(x)x>0owing to the concavity of
u(·) and that u(0) =0.) Since λ0>0isarbitrary, we arrive at V(a)limλ0→+∞ λ0a=
+∞.
This theorem indicates that if the Lagrange multiplier does not exist for all a >0,
then (1.1) is ill-posed for all a >0. Example 2.1 exemplifies such a case. Now, if the
Lagrange multiplier does not exist for only some a (such as in Examples 2.2 and 2.3), is it
still possible that (1.1) is well-posed for the same a?Tostudy this, we need the following
lemma.
LEMMA 3.1. V(a)<+∞,a>0if and only if a>0such that V(a)<+∞.
Proof .Itsuffices to prove that if V(a)<+∞ for some a>0 then V(b)<+∞ for
any b>0.
For ba,wehave
V(b)=sup
E[Xξ]=b,X0
Eu(X)=sup
E[Xξ]=a,X0
Eu b
aX
sup
E[Xξ]=a,X0
b
aEu(X)=b
aV(a)<+∞,
where the first inequality is due to the concavity of u(·) and u(0) =0.
For any 0 <b<a,
V(b)=sup
E[Xξ]=b,X0
Eu(X)=sup
E[Xξ]=a,X0
Eu b
aX
sup
E[Xξ]=a,X0
Eu(X)=V(a)<+∞,
where the first inequality is due to u(·) being increasing. The proof is complete.
176 H. JIN, Z. Q. XU, AND X. Y. ZHOU
COROLLARY 3.1. If V(a)<+∞ for some a >0, then there exists a0>0such that
Problem (1.1) admits a unique optimal solution for all 0<aa0.
Proof .Itfollows from Theorem 3.1 that there exists λ0with E[(u)1(λ0ξ)ξ]<+∞;
consequently the Lagrange multiplier exists for any 0 <aa0:=E[(u)1(λ0ξ)ξ]by
Lemma 2.1. On the other hand, Lemma 3.1 yields that V(a)<+∞ for all a; hence
the desired result follows by virtue of Theorem 1.1.
Now let us continue with Example 2.3.
EXAMPLE 3.1. In Example 2.3, take λ=2. We have proved that a2:=E[(u)1(2ξ)ξ]<
+∞. Denote X=(u)1(2ξ). Then
Eu(X)=Eu(g(2ξ))
=E2ξg(2ξ)+1/(2ξ)
0
p(y)
y2dy
=2a2++∞
n=2
an
n1E[(2ξ)(n1)]
=2a2++∞
n=2
2(n1)
n2(n1)
<+∞.
Theorem 1.1 suggests that Xis the unique optimal solution for (1.1) with parameter a2
and, in particular, V(a2)=Eu(X)<+∞.ByLemma 3.1, we know V(a)<+∞ for any
a>0, i.e., (1.1) is well-posed for any a>0.
However, we have proved in Example 2.3 that E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]=aadmits no solution
for any a>a1. Therefore Problem (1.1) with parameter a>a1is well-posed; yet it admits
no optimal solution (i.e., the problem is not attainable).
4. ILL-POSEDNESS WHEN LAGRANGE MULTIPLIER EXISTS
The last section demonstrated that one of the possible consequences of the non-existence
of a Lagrange multiplier is the ill-posedness of the underlying optimization problem.
This section aims to show via an example that Problem (1.1) may be ill-posed even if the
Lagrange multiplier does exist for any a >0.
EXAMPLE 4.1. Let
u(x)=x,0x1,
1ln 2 +ln(1 +x),x>1,
and ξbe a positive random variable such that E[ln 1
ξ]=+.Itiseasy to check that u(·)
has all the required properties, and
(u)1(x)=
1
x1,0<x0.5,
1
4x2,x>0.5.
CONVEX STOCHASTIC OPTIMIZATION PROBLEM ARISING FROM PORTFOLIO SELECTION 177
Hence
f(λ)=E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]=1
λE[(1 λξ)1λξ 0.5]+E1
4λ2ξ
1λξ>0.53
2λ<+∞ ∀λ>0.
As a result, the Lagrange multiplier exists for any a>0. However, for any λ>0,
Eu(u)1(λξ)=E[(1 ln 2 ln(λξ ))1λξ 0.5]
+E1
2λξ
1λξ>0.5Eln 1
ξ
1λξ0.5ln(λ)=+.
REMARK 4.1. In existing literature it is usually assumed, either explicitly [see, e.g.,
(2.2.13) on page 37 of Karatzas (1997)] or implicitly, that the problem is well-posed for
all a. The preceding example proves that the well-posedness is not guaranteed even when
the Lagrange multiplier exists.
5. OPTIMAL SOLUTION
Having discussed on the ill-posedness and non-attainability, we are now in a position to
study the optimal solution of (1.1). The problems with Theorem 1.1 are two-fold. On
one hand, the required conditions that the Lagrange equation E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]=aadmits
a positive solution and that E[u((u)1(λξ ))] <+∞ do not necessarily hold (as already
demonstrated), and on the other hand even if the conditions do hold, they are implicit
and/or hard to verify. In this section, we will present conditions that are explicit and easy
to use.
Recall that f(λ)=E[(u)1(λξ )ξ]>0. If f(λ)=+for any λ>0, then it follows
from Theorem 3.1 that V(a)=+for any a>0, which is a pathological case. Hence we
assume that there exists a λ>0 such that f(λ)<+∞. Denote λ0=inf{λ>0: f(λ)<
+∞} <+∞ and a0=f(λ0+) (notice that a0=+is possible, and a0=f(λ0)when
λ0>0).
PROPOSITION 5.1. Suppose λ0<+∞.We have the following conclusions.
(i) If a0<+∞, then Problem (1.1) with parameter a>0 admits a unique optimal
solution if and only if E[u((u)1(λ0ξ))] <+∞ and aa0.
(ii) If a0=+, then Problem (1.1) admits a unique optimal solution for any a>
0ifandonly if E[u((u)1(ξ))] <+∞.
Proof .Inview of Theorem 1.1 and Lemma 3.1 (i) is clear. To prove (ii), if a0=+,
by Lemma 2.1, f(·)iscontinuous on (λ0,+∞) with f(λ0+)=+and f(+∞)=0; hence
the Lagrange multiplier exists for any a>0. Now, if E[u((u)1(ξ))] <+∞, using u(x)
xu(x) with x=(u)1(ξ), we have
+∞ >E[u((u)1(ξ))] E[(u)1(ξ)ξ]=:a1.
It follows from Theorem 1.1 that V(a1)=E[u((u)1(ξ))] <+∞. Lemma 3.1 further
yields V(a)<+∞,a>0. The desired result is now a consequence of Theorem 1.1.
Now we derive some sufficient conditions, explicit in terms of u(·)orξ,for the existence
of a unique optimal solution to (1.1). First we have the following simple case.
178 H. JIN, Z. Q. XU, AND X. Y. ZHOU
THEOREM 5.1. If ε=essinf ξ>0, then Problem (1.1) admits a unique optimal solution
for any a >0.
Proof .Givena>0. For any feasible solution Xof Problem (1.1),
Eu(X)u(EX)uE[Xξ]
ε=ua
ε.
Therefore V(a)<+∞.
Meanwhile, for any λ>0,
f(λ)=E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]1
λE[u((u)1(λξ))] 1
λu((u)1(λε)) <+∞.
This proves the existence of the Lagrange multiplier λ>0forany a>0. By Theorem 1.1,
Xλ=(u)1(λξ)isthe unique optimal solution for (1.1).
Let us make some preparations for our main result.
Define R(x)=−xu (x)
u(x)0asthe Arrow–Pratt index of risk aversion of the utility func-
tion u(·).
LEMMA 5.1. If lim infx→+∞R(x)>0, then lim supx→+∞
u(kx)
u(x)<1forany k>1.
Proof . Because lim infx→+∞R(x)>0, there exist M>0,K>0, such that R(x)K
for any xM.Forany xM,k>1,
u(kx)
u(x)1=u(kx)u(x)
u(x)
=kx
x
u(y)dy
u(x)
=−kx
x
R(y)u(y)/ydy
u(x)
≤−kx
x
R(y)u(kx)/ydy
u(x)
=−u(kx)
u(x)kx
x
R(y)/ydy
≤−
u(kx)
u(x)Kkx
x
1/ydy
=−u(kx)
u(x)Kln k.
Therefore u(kx)
u(x)1
1+Kln kwhich implies lim supx→+∞
u(kx)
u(x)1
1+Kln k<1.
LEMMA 5.2. limsupx0+
(u)1(λx)
(u)1(x)<+∞ for any 0<λ<1if and only if
lim supx→+∞
u(kx)
u(x)<1for any k >1.
CONVEX STOCHASTIC OPTIMIZATION PROBLEM ARISING FROM PORTFOLIO SELECTION 179
Proof .Wefirst claim that limsupx0+
(u)1(λx)
(u)1(x)<+∞ for any 0 <λ<1ifandonly
if 0<¯
λ<1 such that lim supx0+
(u)1(¯
λx)
(u)1(x)<+∞.
To prove this claim, suppose lim supx0+
(u)1(¯
λx)
(u)1(x)<+∞ for some 0 <¯
λ<1. Then
lim sup
x0+
(u)1(¯
λ2x)
(u)1(x)
=lim sup
x0+
(u)1(¯
λ2x)
(u)1(¯
λx)
(u)1(¯
λx)
(u)1(x)
lim sup
x0+
(u)1(¯
λ2x)
(u)1(¯
λx)lim sup
x0+
(u)1(¯
λx)
(u)1(x)
<+∞.
From induction it follows limsupx0+
(u)1(¯
λnx)
(u)1(x)<+∞ for any nIN . Since
lim supx0+
(u)1(λx)
(u)1(x)is non-increasing in λ, lim supx0
(u)1(λx)
(u)1(x)<+∞ for any 0 <λ<1.
Similarly, one can prove that lim supx→+∞
u(kx)
u(x)<1forany k>1ifandonly if ¯
k>1
such that lim supx→+∞
u(¯
kx)
u(x)<1.
Now, suppose L=lim supx0+
(u)1(1
2x)
(u)1(x)<+∞ (notice that L1). Then there exists
δ>0 such that for any x(0],
(u)1(1
2x)
(u)1(x)2L
1
2xu(2L(u)1(x))
1
2u(2L(u)1(x))
u((u)1(x))
u(2Ly)
u(y)1
2,y(u)1(δ)
lim sup
x→+∞
u(2Lx)
u(x)1
2.
Therefore lim supx→+∞
u(kx)
u(x)<1forany k>1.
The proof for the other direction is similar.
Recall that we have defined f(λ)=E[(u)1(λξ )ξ] and λ0=inf{λ>0: f(λ)<+∞}.
PROPOSITION 5.2. Suppose one of the following conditions is satisfied:
(i) lim infx→+∞R(x)>0.
(ii) lim supx→+∞
u(kx)
u(x)<1for some k >1.
(iii) lim supx0
(u)1(λx)
(u)1(x)<+∞ for some λ(0, 1).
Then the Lagrange multiplier exists for any a >0if and only if λ0<+∞.
Proof . The necessity is obvious. To prove the sufficiency, note that if λ0<+∞, then
there exists λ1>0 such that f(λ1)<+∞,which by the monotonicity of f(·) further
implies that f(λ)<+∞∀λ>λ
1.Forany λ(0
1], denote k=λ/λ1(0,1].
180 H. JIN, Z. Q. XU, AND X. Y. ZHOU
Since one of the three given conditions is satisfied, by Lemmas 5.1 and 5.2 it must
have 1 L=lim supx0
(u)1(kx)
(u)1(x)<+∞. Hence there exists δ>0 such that (u)1(kx)
(u)1(x)<2L
for any x(0
1δ]. Now, for any λ>0,
E(u)1(λξ)ξ1ξδ=E(u)1(λξ )
(u)1(λ1ξ)(u)1(λ1ξ)ξ1ξδ
2LE[(u)1(λ1ξ)ξ1ξδ]
2Lf (λ1),
E(u)1(λξ)ξ1ξ>δ=1
λE(u)1(λξ)(λξ )1ξ>δ
1
λEu((u)1(λξ))1ξ>δ
1
λu((u)1(λδ)).
Hence,
f(λ)=E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]
=E(u)1(λξ)ξ1ξδ+E(u)1(λξ )ξ1ξ>δ
2Lf (λ1)+1
λu((u)1(λδ))
<+∞.
This shows that in fact λ0=0, and hence the equation f(λ)=aadmits a positive solution
λ(a)forany a>0.
REMARK 5.1. The preceding proof also shows that under the condition of Proposition
5.2, the following claims are equivalent:
(i) The Lagrange multiplier exists for any a>0.
(ii) λ0<+∞.
(iii) λ0=0.
(iv) f(1) <+∞ .
(v) f(λ)<+∞λ>0.
THEOREM 5.2. Under the condition of Proposition 5.2, Problem (1.1) admits a unique
optimal solution for any a >0if and only if E[u((u)1(ξ))] <+∞.
Proof .Itsuffices to prove the sufficiency. If E[u((u)1(ξ))] <+∞, then f(1) =
E[(u)1(ξ)ξ]E[u((u)1(ξ))] <+∞.Thus λ0=0 and a0=f(λ0+)=+.Itfollows
from Proposition 5.1 then that Problem (1.1) admits a unique optimal solution.
The conditions in the preceding theorem, lim infx→+∞ xu (x)
u(x)>0 and E[u((u)1×
(ξ))] <+∞,are very easy to verify. For example, a commonly used utility function is
u(x)=xα,0<α<1. The two conditions are satisfied when ξis lognormal.
REMARK 5.2. Example 3.1 shows that the conclusion of Theorem 5.2 can be false in
the absence of its condition.
CONVEX STOCHASTIC OPTIMIZATION PROBLEM ARISING FROM PORTFOLIO SELECTION 181
COROLLARY 5.1. If E[ξα]<+∞α1,then, under the condition of Proposition 5.2,
Problem (1.1) admits a unique optimal solution for any a >0.
Proof .Itsuffices to prove that E[u((u)1(ξ))] <+∞ holds automatically. Un-
der the condition of Proposition 5.2, there is L2 such that (u)1(x)<
L(u)1(2x)x(0,1). Denote L0=supx[1
2,1](u)1(x)<+∞.Forany x(0, 1),
find nIN s o that 1
22nx<1. Then (u)1(x)<L(u)1(2x)<L2(u)1(22x)<
···<Ln(u)1(2nx)LnL0Llog2xL0=xlog2LL0.Byvirtue of the fact that
u(+∞)=0, we may assume that u(x)L1xx(u)1(1). Therefore for any x
(0, 1), we have u((u)1(x)) L1(u)1(x)<L0L1xlog2L. Finally, E[u((u)1(ξ))]
E[u((u)1(ξ))1ξ<1]+u((u)1(1)) L0L1E[ξlog2L]+u((u)1(1)) <+∞.
REMARK 5.3. If ξis lognormal, then the assumption that E[ξα]<+∞α1 holds
automatically. [In the contextof portfolio selection with the prices of the underlying stocks
followinggeometric Brownian motion, ξis typically a lognormal random variable—under
certain conditions of course; for details see Remark 3.1 in Bielecki et al. (2005)]. On the
other hand, this assumption could be weakened to that E[ξα0]<+∞ for certain α0(the
value of which could be precisely given). We leave the details to the interested readers.
Recall that in Section 4 we presented an example where Problem (1.1) is ill-posed even
though the Lagrange multiplier exists for any a>0. The following result shows that this
will not occur for certain ξ.
Let F(·)bethe probability distribution function of ξ.Inview of Theorem 5.1, we
assume essinf ξ=0, which in turn ensures F(x)>0x>0.
THEOREM 5.3. If lim infx0+xF(x)
F(x)>0,and E[(u)1(λξ )ξ]=a>0for some λ>0,
then Problem (1.1) with parameter a is well-posed and admits a unique optimal solution.
Proof . Since lim infx0+xF(x)
F(x)>0, there exist M>0 and K>0 such that xF (x)
F(x)1
K
for any 0 <xM. Then
E[u((u)1(λξ))1ξ<M]
=M
0
u((u)1(λx)) dF(x)
=M
0x
M
du((u)1(λy)) dF(x)+M
0
u((u)1(λM)) dF(x)
=λM
0x
M
yd[(u)1(λy)] dF(x)+u((u)1(λM))F(M)
=λM
0x(u)1(λx)M(u)1(λM)+M
x
(u)1(λy)dydF(x)
+u((u)1(λM))F(M)
=λM
0
x(u)1(λx)dF(x)+λM
0M
x
(u)1(λy)dy dF (x)
+[u((u)1(λM)) λM(u)1(λM)]F(M)
=λM
0
x(u)1(λx)dF(x)+λM
0y
0
dF(x)(u)1(λy)dy
+[u((u)1(λM)) λM(u)1(λM)]F(M)
182 H. JIN, Z. Q. XU, AND X. Y. ZHOU
=λM
0
x(u)1(λx)dF(x)+λM
0
F(y)(u)1(λy)dy
+[u((u)1(λM)) λM(u)1(λM)]F(M)
λM
0
x(u)1(λx)dF(x)+KλM
0
yF(y)(u)1(λy)dy
+[u((u)1(λM)) λM(u)1(λM)]F(M)
λ(1 +K)a+[u((u)1(λM)) λM(u)1(λM)]F(M)
<+∞.
Consequently,
E[u((u)1(λξ))]
=Eu((u)1(λξ))1ξ<M+Eu((u)1(λξ))1ξM
Eu((u)1(λξ))1ξ<M+u((u)1(λM))
<+∞.
The desired result follows then from Theorem 1.1.
REMARK 5.4.. The condition lim infx0+xF(x)
F(x)>0 implicitly requires that F(·)be
differentiable in the neighborhood of 0. Notice that this requirement is purely technical
so as to make the result neater. Once could replace the condition lim infx0+xF(x)
F(x)>0
by aweaker one without having to assume the differentiability of F(·) (as hinted by the
preceding proof—the details are left to the interested reader). On the other hand, the
condition is satisfied if ξis lognormal.
Combining Theorems 1.1 and 5.3, we have immediately:
COROLLARY 5.2. Suppose lim infx0+xF(x)
F(x)>0.Then Problem (1.1) with parameter
a>0admits an optimal solution if and only if the Lagrange multiplier λexists corresponding
to a, in which case the unique optimal solution is X=(u)1(λξ ).
The following synthesized result gives easily verifiable conditions under which Prob-
lem (1.1) is completely solved.
THEOREM 5.4. We have the following conclusions.
(i) If lim infx→+∞ xu (x)
u(x)>0,then the following statements are equivalent:
(ia) Problem (1.1) is well-posed for any a >0.
(ib) Problem (1.1) admits a unique optimal solution.
(ic) E[u((u)1(ξ))] <+∞.
(id) λ>0 such that E[u((u)1(λξ))] <+∞.
Moreover, when one of (ia)–(id) holds the optimal solution to (1.1) with
parameter a >0is X=(u)1(λ(a)ξ),where λ(a)is the Lagrange multiplier
corresponding to a.
(ii) If lim supx0+(xF(x)
F(x))<0,then Problem (1.1) is well-posed for any a >0
if and only if E[(u)1(λξ)ξ]<+∞ for some λ>0, in which case there exists
0<a0≤+so that (1.1) admits a unique optimal solution X=(u)1(λ(a)ξ)
for any a >0(if a0=+)orforany 0<aa0(if a0<+∞).
Proof .
(i) If (1.1) is well-posed for any a>0, then Theorem 3.1 yields that f(λ0)<+∞
for some λ0>0. It follows from Proposition 5.2 and Theorem 1.1 that (1.1)
CONVEX STOCHASTIC OPTIMIZATION PROBLEM ARISING FROM PORTFOLIO SELECTION 183
admits a unique optimal solution for any a>0. The desired equivalence is then
a consequence of Theorem 5.2 and Theorem 1.1.
(ii) The first conclusion (“if and only if”) follows from Theorems 3.1 and 5.3. For the
second conclusion, let λ0=inf{λ>0: f(λ)<+∞} <+∞ and a0=f(λ0+).
Then the Lagrange multiplier exists for any a>0 (if a0=+)orforany
0<aa0(if a0<+∞), and Corollary 5.2 completes the proof.
REMARK 5.5. Portfolio selection is essentially an endeavor that an investor, given a
market (represented by ξor its distribution function F(·)), tries to make the best out of
his initial wealth (namely a) taking advantage of the availability of the market, where the
“best” is measured by her preference (i.e., the utility function u(·)). We have shown that
these entities, namely F(·), a, and u(·), must coordinate well, otherwise one may end up
with a wrong model. The assumptions stipulated in Theorem 5.4 tell precisely how this
well-coordination can be translated into mathematical conditions.
6. CONCLUDING REMARKS
The stochastic optimization problem studied in this paper, though interesting in its
own right, has profound applications in financial asset allocation among others. It is
demonstrated that many assumptions that have been taken for granted, such as the well-
posedness of the problem, existence of the Lagrange multiplier, and existence of an op-
timal solution, may be invalid in the first place. In particular, the issue of well-posedness
is equally important, if not more important, than that of finding an optimal solution
from a modeling point of view. Attainability of optimal solutions is another important
matter: if an optimal solution is not attainable, as is the case with Example 3.1, then
one has to resort to finding an asymptotically optimal solution. Mathematically, both
the ill-posedness and the non-attainability are symptomized by the non-existence of the
Lagrange multiplier, as analyzed in details in this paper.
It is worth noting that the results of this paper have been utilized in solving a sub
problem of the continuous-time behavioral portfolio selection model Jin and Zhou (2008),
where the ill-posedness is more a rule than an exception.
REFERENCES
BIELECKI,T.R., H. JIN,S.R.PLISKA, and X. Y. ZHOU (2005): Continuous-Time Mean–Variance
Portfolio Selection with Bankruptcy Prohibition, Math. Finance 15, 213–244.
CVITANIC,J.,and I. KARATZAS (1992): Convex Duality in Constrained Portfolio Optimization,
Ann. Appl. Probab. 2, 767–818.
KARATZAS,I.(1997): Lectures on the Mathematics of Finance, American Mathematical Society.
KARATZAS, I., and S. E. SHREVE (1998): Methods of Mathematical Finance,New Yo rk: Springer-
Ver l ag.
KORN,R.(1997): Optimal Portfolios, Singapore: World Scientific.
KORN, R., and H. KRAFT (2004): On the Stability of Continuous-Time Portfolio Problems with
Stochastic Opportunity Set, Math. Finance 14, 403–414.
JIN, H., and X. Y. ZHOU (2008): Behavioral Portfolio Selection in Continuous Time, Math.
Finance,forthcoming.
... The proof is essentially from [9], which is however reproduced here for ...
... In the above result we require the existence of the Lagrange multiplier λ > 0. Such an assumption needs to be checked for a more concrete problem. The assumption may not hold even in the classical case without intractable claims; refer to [9] for a comprehensive discussion in the classical case. ...
Article
Full-text available
We study a continuous-time expected utility maximisation problem where the investor at maturity receives the value of a contingent claim in addition to the investment payoff from the financial market. The investor knows nothing about the claim other than its probability distribution; hence the name “intractable claim”. In view of the lack of necessary information about the claim, we consider a robust formulation to maximise her utility in the worst scenario. We apply the quantile formulation to solve the problem, express the quantile function of the optimal terminal investment income as the solution of certain variational inequalities of ordinary differential equations, and obtain the resulting optimal trading strategy. In the case of exponential utility, the problem reduces to a (non-robust) rank-dependent utility maximisation with probability distortion whose solution is available in the literature. The results can also be used to determine the utility indifference price of the intractable claim.
... In economic theory, the undetermined multipliers λ and µ represent 'shadow prices' imposed on system dynamics by environmental constraints, in a large sense [31,32]. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
The draconian regulation required by the inherent instability of cognitive phenomena -- gene expression, immune function, cancer suppression, wound healing, animal consciousness, machine intelligence, network stabilization, institutional cognition, and their many and varied composites -- can be viewed through the lens of the asymptotic limit theorems of both information and control theories. Here, we explore the dynamics and sometimes highly punctuated failures of the regulation of cognition under increasing `noise'. The approach parallels, and indeed generalizes, the Data Rate Theorem of control theory, extending the theorem's requirement of a minimum channel capacity necessary for stabilization of an inherently unstable system. Various models are explored across different basic underlying probability distributions characteristic of the system under study, and across different hierarchical scales, finding the addition of adaptive -- learned -- regulation greatly extends the reach of innate -- e.g., AI-driven or otherwise pre-programmed -- regulation. This work points toward the construction of new statistical tools for the analysis of observational and empirical data across a wide spectrum of inherent pathologies and adversarial challenges afflicting a wide variety of cognitive processes.
... In economic theory, λ and µ are 'shadow prices' imposed on a system by environmental constraints [43,44]. ...
Article
Full-text available
Organized conflict, while confined by the laws of physics—and, under profound strategic incompetence, by the Lanchester equations—is not a physical process but rather an extended exchange between cognitive entities that have been shaped by path-dependent historical trajectories and cultural traditions. Cognition itself is confined by the necessity of duality, with an underlying information source constrained by the asymptotic limit theorems of information and control theories. We introduce the concept of a ‘basic underlying probability distribution’ characteristic of the particular cognitive process studied. The dynamic behavior of such systems is profoundly different for ‘thin-tailed’ and ‘fat-tailed’ distributions. The perspective permits the construction of new probability models that may provide useful statistical tools for the analysis of observational and experimental data associated with organized conflict, and, in some measure, for its management.
... under the condition that ∂ Z i /∂ T i = f i (Z i ) from Eq.(17). In economic theory, λ and µ are envisioned as 'shadow prices' imposed on a system by environmental constraints (Jin et al. 2008;Robinson 1993). ...
Preprint
Full-text available
We derive the classic Yerkes-Dodson effect of applied stress on real-world performance in a highly natural manner from fundamental assumptions on cognition and its dynamics, as constrained by the asymptotic limit theorems of information and control theories. We further examine how differences in an underlying cognitive probability model might associate with different expressions of psychopathology. Vulnerability to psychopathology is framed as a ratio of toxic stress in the context of ‘noise’ and uncertainty to resilience. A ‘thin tailed’ underlying distribution appears to characterize expression of ‘ordinary’ situational depression/anxiety symptoms induced by stress, while a ‘fat tailed’ underlying distribution appears to be associated with brain structure and function abnormalities leading to serious mental illness where symptoms are not only emerging in the setting of severe stress but may emerge in a highly punctuated manner at relatively lower levels of stress. A simple hierarchical optimization model explores the effects of environmental ‘shadow price’ constraints in buffering or aggravating the effects of stress. Extension of the underlying theory to other patterns of pathology, like immune disorders and premature aging, seems apt. Ultimately, the probability models studied here can be converted to new statistical tools for the analysis of observational and experimental data.
... We now discuss the existence of the Lagrange multiplier. This is not a trivial task because, even in the absence of probability distortion, the Lagrange multiplier may not always exist; see Jin, Xu and Zhou [13] for a comprehensive study. ...
Article
We demonstrate—under what is perhaps a “best case” analysis—that all enterprises of embodied cognition, ranging from the “simply” cognitive to the actively conscious, and from the individual to the mechanical, institutional, and composite, are susceptible to induced patterns of hallucination, panic, and exhaustion on challenging landscapes of fog, friction, and deadly adversarial intent. That is, embodied cognition, of any nature and on any scale or level of organization, is inherently unstable in the sense of the Data Rate Theorem, requiring constant control information for proper function, a circumstance that can be exploited by traditional adversaries or other evolving entities. We further argue, in consonance with C.S. Gray, that dreams of “Wunderwaffen,”“Wundertaktik,” and implacable “Reflexive Control” are themselves siren hallucinations.
Article
Full-text available
In this paper, we consider the optimal investment problem with both probability distortion/weighting and general non-concave utility functions with possibly finite number of inflection points, and apply a Lagrange duality based relaxation approach for solving this problem. Existing literature has shown the equivalent relationships (strong duality) between the relaxed problem and the original one by either assuming the presence of probability weighting or the non-concavity of utility functions, but not both. In this paper, combining both factors, we prove that the absence of concavity in the utilities may result in strictly positive gaps, thus the strong duality may not hold unconditionally. The necessary and sufficient conditions on eliminating such gaps have been provided under this circumstance. We have applied the solution method to obtain closed-form solutions for the optimal terminal wealth and corresponding investment strategies in a special cumulative prospect theory (CPT) example with an appropriately selected inverse S-shaped probability distortion function. Based on the solutions, the joint effects of non-concave utilities combined with the probability weighting on the trading behaviors can be explicitly characterized. We show that, under this particular example, the co-existence of both factors may water down the loss aversion effect induced by only S-shaped utility or probability distortion when the agents are more cash-strapped in the initial budgets. In addition, we find that the op- timal strategies derived from distorted beliefs shall converge to a constant that can be expressed by the standard Merton ratio multiplied by an inflation factor which we name as “distorted” Merton ratio. More importantly, the inflation factor is solely dependent on the probability distortion rather than the features of the utility function.
Preprint
Full-text available
This paper investigates an optimal investment problem under the tail Value at Risk (tail VaR, also known as expected shortfall, conditional VaR, average VaR) and portfolio insurance constraints confronted by a defined-contribution pension member. The member's aim is to maximize the expected utility from the terminal wealth exceeding the minimum guarantee by investing his wealth in a cash bond, an inflation-linked bond and a stock. Due to the presence of the tail VaR constraint, the problem cannot be tackled by standard control tools. We apply the Lagrange method along with quantile optimization techniques to solve the problem. Through delicate analysis, the optimal investment output in closed-form and optimal investment strategy are derived. A numerical analysis is also provided to show how the constraints impact the optimal investment output and strategy.
Article
Full-text available
We study the stochastic control problem of maximizing expected utility from terminal wealth and/or consumption, when the portfolio is constrained to take values in a given closed, convex subset of R^d. The setting is that of a continuous-time, Itô process model for the underlying asset prices. General existence results are established for optimal portfolio/consumption strategies, by suitably embedding the constrained problem in an appropriate family of unconstrained ones, and finding a member of this family for which the corresponding optimal policy obeys the constraints. Equivalent conditions for optimality are obtained, and explicit solutions leading to feedback formulae are derived for special utility functions and for deterministic coefficients. Results on incomplete markets, on short-selling constraints and on different interest rates for borrowing and lending are covered as special cases. The mathematical tools are those of continuous-time martingales, convex analysis and duality theory.
Article
This paper formulates and studies a general continuous-time behavioral portfolio selection model under Kahneman and Tversky's (cumulative) prospect theory, featuring S-shaped utility (value) functions and probability distortions. Unlike the conventional expected utility maximization model, such a behavioral model could be easily mis-formulated (a.k.a. ill-posed) if its different components do not coordinate well with each other. Certain classes of an ill-posed model are identified. A systematic approach, which is fundamentally different from the ones employed for the utility model, is developed to solve a well-posed model, assuming a complete market and general It\^o processes for asset prices. The optimal terminal wealth positions, derived in fairly explicit forms, possess surprisingly simple structure reminiscent of a gambling policy betting on a good state of the world while accepting a fixed, known loss in case of a bad one. An example with a two-piece CRRA utility is presented to illustrate the general results obtained, and is solved completely for all admissible parameters. The effect of the behavioral criterion on the risky allocations is finally discussed.
Article
A continuous-time mean-variance portfolio selection problem is studied where all the market coefficients are random and the wealth process under any admissible trading strategy is not allowed to be below zero at any time. The trading strategy under consideration is defined in terms of the dollar amounts, rather than the proportions of wealth, allocated in individual stocks. The problem is completely solved using a decomposition approach. Specifically, a (constrained) variance minimizing problem is formulated and its feasibility is characterized. Then, after a system of equations for two Lagrange multipliers is solved, variance minimizing portfolios are derived as the replicating portfolios of some contingent claims, and the variance minimizing frontier is obtained. Finally, the efficient frontier is identified as an appropriate portion of the variance minimizing frontier after the monotonicity of the minimum variance on the expected terminal wealth over this portion is proved and all the efficient portfolios are found. In the special case where the market coefficients are deterministic, efficient portfolios are explicitly expressed as feedback of the current wealth, and the efficient frontier is represented by parameterized equations. Our results indicate that the efficient policy for a mean-variance investor is simply to purchase a European put option that is chosen, according to his or her risk preferences, from a particular class of options.
Article
In this paper we present some counterexamples to show that an uncritical application of the usual methods of continuous-time portfolio optimization can be misleading in the case of a stochastic opportunity set. Cases covered are problems with stochastic interest rates, stochastic volatility, and stochastic market price of risk. To classify the problems occurring with stochastic market coefficients, we further introduce two notions of stability of portfolio problems.
  • S E Shreve
KARATZAS, I., and S. E. SHREVE (1998): Methods of Mathematical Finance, New York: Springer- Verlag.