ChapterPDF Available

Linnaeus, Carl

Authors:
Carl Linnaeus
*
Affiliation
Staffan Müller-Wille
Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Cambridge
Cambridge, United Kingdom
sewm3@cam.ac.uk
++44-786-1020240
1. Synonyms (if possible)
Carolus Linnaeus, Carolus Linnæus, Carl von Linné, Karl von Linné, Charles Linné.
2. Related Topics
Natural history; natural philosophy; botany; zoology; mineralogy; taxonomy; nomenclature; natural
system; Baconianism; Paracelsianism; balance of nature; physicotheology.
3. Introduction
Linnaeus was no philosopher, neither by profession, nor by inclination. He prided himself on writing
simple prose, and disliked public disputes. His idiosyncratic natural philosophy built on baroque
syncretism and rash theorizing by analogy, but always carried the mark of the naturalist and physician. As
such, his work is exemplary of what Louis Althusser has called the “spontaneous philosophy” of
scientists (Althusser 1990). This can explain why his impact on the history of philosophy was nonetheless
profound. His self-styled “reform” of botanical and zoological taxonomy redefined the terms of
philosophical debates about classification, and his concept of an “economy of nature” identified an
entirely new level of phenomena at which life could be seen to operate on an evolutionary scale.
4. Biography
Born on May 23, 1707, in Stenbrohult, a small parish in the economically disadvantaged Swedish
province Småland, Linnaeus studied medicine at the universities of Lund and Uppsala from 1726 to 1734.
He could not afford the fees to attend lectures regularly, but from early on developed a talent for
attracting patronage. At both universities, professors supported his keen interest in natural history by
offering him board and lodging, private tutoring, and perusal of their libraries. From 1729, he was able to
*
Published in Encyclopaedia of Earl Modern Philosophy, edited by D. Jalobeanu and C. Wolfe, Cham: Springer, DOI:
https://doi-org.ezp.lib.cam.ac.uk/10.1007/978-3-319-20791-9_565-1.
sustain himself, first by lecturing in the botanical garden of Uppsala, then by securing funds for scientific
travels to Lapland (1732) and Dalarna (1734), a province renowned for its copper mines.
In these years, Linnaeus compiled several book manuscripts, which he brought with him alongside a
Sámi costume (fig. 1) when he visited Holland from 1734 to 1737, initially to obtain his medical
doctorate at the university of Harderwijk, and then to work as curator of the large botanical collection of
the Dutch-English merchant-banker George Clifford III (16851760). Clifford also financed trips to
London and Paris. During these years, he managed to publish no less then fourteen books, most of them
dealing with botany. Two publications in particular laid the ground for his immediate fame throughout the
republic of letters: Systema naturae (1735), a folio volume of just eleven pages that presented the three
kingdoms of nature in a tabular arrangement of classes, orders, genera and species; and Flora lapponica
(1737), a catalogue of plant species native to Lapland, considered uncharted territory at the time.
[Fig. 1: Linnaeus posing in a Samí dress in front of his publications. Mezzotint produced by Robert
Dunkarton and Henry Kingsbury in 1805 after a portrait in oil painted by Martinus Hoffmann in the
Netherlands 1737. © The Trustees of the British Museum; for information on copyright go to
https://www.britishmuseum.org/collection/image/819589001.]
Returning to Sweden, Linnaeus initially practiced as a physician in Stockholm. In 1739, he married Sara
Lisa Moræa (1716-1806), daughter of the miner and physician Johan Moræus (16721742), whom he had
met when travelling through Dalarna. He remained active as a naturalist as well during this time, holding
public lectures and excursions in botany and co-founding the Royal Academy of Sciences in 1739,
together with engineer and amateur physicist Mårten Triewald (16911747), industrialist Jonas Alströmer
(16851761), Count Anders Johan von Höpken (17121789) and Baron Sten Carl Bielke (17091753),
the latter two members of the Riksdag of Estates (Riksens ständer, or ståndsriksdag). The composition of
this group is typical of the “patriotic” circles that Linnaeus moved in, and from which he received
patronage. In 1741, Linnaeus was appointed to the chair of theoretical medicine at Uppsala University,
with teaching responsibilities in botany, chemistry, diagnostics, and dietetics. He stayed in this position
until his death on January 10, 1778, continuing his astonishing literary output. His political connections,
forged in his Stockholm years, brought him financial support in the 1740s from the Estates to carry out
well-organized trips through several Swedish provinces (Västergøtland, Öland, Gotland and Scania) in
order to survey natural resources in the spirit of the then dominant economic ideology of cameralism
(Koerner 1999). The 1740s also saw the publication of Flora suecica (1745) and Fauna suecica (1746).
Alongside this, Linnaeus continued to update and expand his taxonomic works in numerous re-editions,
culminating in Species plantarum (1753) and the so-called tenth edition of Systema naturae (1758-59,
which constitute the formal starting point of modern taxonomy and nomenclature.
Linnaeus acquired the empirical material for these publications through a far-flung network of
correspondents who sent him seeds, living and preserved specimens, as well as descriptions and drawings,
both in manuscript and print. In addition, he managed to secure opportunities for some of his students to
accompany merchant ships and scientific expeditions around the globe. Some of the better-known among
Linnaeus’s “apostles” are Pehr Kalm (17161799), who travelled to North America 17281751, Daniel
Solander (17331782), who went with Joseph Banks (1743–1820) on Cook’s first circumnavigation
(17681771), and Carl Peter Thunberg (17431828), who travelled as a surgeon with the Dutch East
India Company all the way to Japan (17711778) (on Linnaean travel, see Sörlin 2000). Closer to home,
numerous occasions for academic speeches, presidency over 186 academic dissertations, and publications
in almanachs and learned journals, both in Sweden and abroad, resulted in an array of minor essays on
medical, natural historical and natural philosophical subjects. When Linnaeus died on January 10, 1778,
leaving his chair to his son Carl (17411783), he had become an institution, as witnessed by the fact that
Species plantarum and Systema naturae continued to be re-edited under his name until the 1830s. (For
biographies, see Blunt 1971, Broberg 2019; a full bibliography of Linnaeus’s works, including re-editions
and translations, is provided by Soulsby 1933, with more than 4000 references.)
5. Natural Philosophy
Linnaeus was largely self-taught, and the tutelage that he did enjoy came from a motley crew of academic
teachers (Malmeström 1964). Johan Stensson Rothman (16841763), lector in physics and logic at Växjö
gymnasium, liked to describe himself as an “Aristotelian Cartesian. Kilian Stobæus (16901742),
professor in natural philosophy and experimental physics in Lund, was primarily interested in mineralogy,
especially fossils, but he also taught Linnaeus physiology in private lessons (he was a Stahlian). Olof
Rudbeck the younger (16601740) in Uppsala held the chair in theoretical medicine, but was mainly
engaged in reducing all languages to the language spoken by Adam and Eve. Anders Celsius (1701
1744), professor of astronomy, was a chief representative of Leibniz-Wolffian philosophy, which
dominated Swedish university teaching at the time (on Linnaeus’s teachers and their backgrounds, see
Broberg 2019). By the end of 1729, Linnaeus had built up a personal library of 200 volumes, which not
only included classical authors like Hippocrates and Aristotle, but also many obscure magical and
alchemical works (Cain 1992).
This peculiar academic upbringing may explain why it is difficult to allocate Linnaeus to any school early
modern philosophical thought. Aristotle is cited, but only his zoological works. One can find
endorsements of Cartesian scepticism and Bacon’s inductivism (Müller-Wille 2008), but there is no
evidence that Linnaeus ever read Newton, Boyle or Locke, or any of the French enlightenment
philosophers like Voltaire, Diderot or Rousseau. In matters of contemporary natural philosophy, Linnaeus
seems to have trusted Boerhaave. However, he could also rely on a mix of earlier, Paracelsian and
Hermeticist authors, especially in his mineralogical and medical works (Wikman 1970). He explicitly
rejected both preformation and epigenesis (as formulated by Harvey), and, while he generally followed
Boerhaave’s iatromechanism in his physiological outlook, citing authors such as Santorio Santorio (1561-
1631), Friedrich Hoffmann (1660-1742) or Stephen Hales (16771761), he also considered electricity as a
fundamental life force, especially in his later writings (Broberg 1975). In striking contrast to his natural
history, which relied on painstaking observations of empirical details, Linnaeus’s natural philosophy was
speculative, often out-of-date, and sometimes simply uninformed (Lindroth 1983). As a consequence, it
had almost no impact on the major debates in eighteenth-century natural philosophy.
A good example of Linnaeus’s ventures into natural philosophy is provided by his speculations on sexual
reproduction. His interest in this subject was piqued when his teacher Rothman introduced him to
Sebastian Vaillant’s Discours sur la structure des fleurs (1718), and it soon evolved into a central theme
(Müller-Wille 2018). In 1730, Linnaeus developed a method to classify plants into classes and orders on
the basis of the number and arrangement of “male” and “female” organs. Known as the “sexual system”
(systema sexuale), its subversive play on gender stereotypes made it very popular in the eighteenth
century (Schiebinger 1993; Shteir 1999). A chapter on “sexuality” (sexus) was also included in
Fundamenta botanica (1736), and later expanded into an essay entitled Sponsalia plantarum (1746; the
title can be translated as “plant marriages”). The point of this essay was to reject spontaneous generation
(generatio æquivoca) in favour of a view that all organisms, including plants, reproduce sexually (omne
vivum ex ovo, a clear affront to the age-old idea of a scale of nature). Evidence was largely provided by
interpreting observations of flower mechanisms in analogy with animal fertilization (Müller-Wille
2007a).
In the 1750s and 1760s, Linnaeus’s writings on reproduction took on a more speculative tone. Taking
cues from Theophrastus (c. 371 c. 287 BC) and Andrea Cesalpino (15191603), Linnaeus posited that
all living beings consist of two substances, medulla (“marrow”, in animals associated with the nervous
system) and cortex (“bark”). The former was supposed to be endowed with the capacity to grow and
multiply indefinitely, the latter to provide nourishment and protection, thereby constraining growth. The
medullar substance, he further claimed, was transmitted by the mother, the cortical substance by the
father, and their antagonistic interaction gave the offspring its specific form (Generatio ambigena, 1759).
This theory had a crucial integrating function for Linnaeus. It not only explained to him why offspring
exhibit both maternal and paternal traits, but also why one should expect taxonomically similar plant
species to have similar medical effects on the human body (Fundamentum fructificationis, 1762; Hövel
1999). It became the cornerstone of Linnaeus’s most peculiar and obscure work, Clavis medicina duplex,
exterior & interior (1766), in which he tried to correlate human diseases, therapies, tastes, odours, and
herbal remedies (Stevens and Cullen 1990).
6. Systema naturæ
Linnaeus himself considered Clavis to be “one of the greatest jewels in medicine”, but it seems to have
“dropped dead from the presses” (Broberg 2012, 45). This does not mean that Linnaeus’s engagement
with theories of generation and sexual reproduction had no legacy at all. For one, plant sexuality and
development remained a major biological theme, which especially Romantic Naturphilosophen like Johan
Wolfgang von Goethe (17491838) picked up from Linnaeus (Kelley 2012). In addition, Linnaeus had
developed the theme in part to account for the production of new species by hybridization (Plantæ
hybridæ, 1751; Metamorphoses plantarum, 1755), and in 1759 carried out a single hybridization
experiment (Disquisitio de sexu plantarum, 1760) that formed the starting point for a research tradition
that led all the way to Gregor Mendel’s famous experiments (Müller-Wille and Orel 2007). Whatever
philosophical sense Linnaeus himself made of them, the phenomena that he highlighted, and partly
produced, could not be ignored by contemporary philosophers.
This is especially true of his main work, Systema naturæ, published in Amsterdam in 1735. The neat
arrangement of all known minerals, plants and animals on eleven folio pages measuring 53 x 42 cm does
not accidentally recall the image of an atlas (fig. 2). In fact, Linnaeus had originally planned to publish it
under the title Geographia naturæ. However, the arrangement of genera and species in columns and rows
that represent orders and classes does not reflect any concrete, physical order of nature. It entirely resulted
from applying a small set of distinguishing features, like dentition in mammals, beak form in birds, or
number and position of stamina and pistils in the case of plants. The “system” thus seemed nothing more
than the product of a mind aspiring to bring order to nature through the medium of language alone
(Foucault 1966; Pratt 1985; Lesch 1990).
[Fig. 2: Two pages displaying the “kingdom of animals” from Carl Linnaeus, Systema naturæ
(Amsterdam, 1735). Source: Wikimedia Commons (public domain).]
The criticism that Linnaeus’s system was “artificial” was already formulated by George Louis Leclerc,
Comte de Buffon (1707–1788), in his “Premier discours de la manière d’étudier et de traiter l’histoire
naturelle, which introduced the first volume of his monumental Histoire naturelle, générale et
particulière (1749–1788). Historians of ideas have traced back Buffon’s scepticism towards Linnaeus’s
project of cutting nature at its joints to the influence of John Locke (Lyon 1976; Sloan 1976), while
Linnaeus’s realism has been identified with an essentialist tradition, going back to Aristotle (Cain 1958;
Larson 1971; Mayr 1982, ch. 4). Still others, including Foucault, have seen a lot of common metaphysical
ground shared by the respective projects of Buffon and Linnaeus, despite Buffon’s harsh critique
(Foucault 1966; Schmitt 2010).
The confusion is partly due to the fact that Linnaeus’s sexual system quickly became the paragon of
eighteenth-century botanical and zoological “systems”, despite the fact that he himself considered it to be
“artificial”. In fact, it was Linnaeus who drew the distinction between “artificial” systems and “the”
natural system, and contemporaries acknowledged this as one of his main achievements (Lefèvre 1999
and Müller-Wille 2014). Artificial systems, he contended, resulted from the ancient method of logical
analysis per genus et differentiam and tended to result in classifications that separated otherwise similar
organisms. The natural system, in contrast, built on inductive methods of description and comparison, and
related groups of organisms in a web of mutual similarities, just like “territories on a geographical map”,
as Linnaeus stated in a famous aphorism in Philosophia botanica (1751; Rheinberger 1986; Barsanti
1992; Müller-Wille 2007b). The distribution of traits in organisms, and the curious taxonomic patterns it
produced, thus became itself a central epistemic object of eighteenth-century natural history, raising deep
questions about the nature of species, the continuity of the “great chain of beings”, and the potential
historicity of natural processes (Daudin 1926; Lepenies 1976; Stevens 1994; Larson 1994; Lefèvre 1999;
Winsor 2015; Dietz 2016).
What gave Linnaeus’s realist assumptions about the “natural system” lasting pertinence were not so much
emphatic statements as when he claimed in Philosophia botanica (1751) that it is “not the character that
produces the genus, but the genus that produces the character” – but the fact that these assumptions were
built into the taxonomic tools he created. That names could be understood as conventional “labels”, and
the Linnaean hierarchy of classes, orders, genera and species as a hierarchic system of containers, or
“boxes within boxes”, presupposed that species and other taxonomic groups of higher rank could be
treated as “things” to be named, described, compared, rearranged and exchanged (Müller-Wille and
Charmantier 2012; Müller-Wille 2017). In this sense of a “metaphysics in action”, Linnaeus and his
followers defined the terms of a philosophical debate about “natural kinds” that lingers with us to this
very day (Daston 2004; McOuat 2001).
7. Œconomia naturæ
It has often been stated that Linnaeus’s science was heavily influenced by his religious outlook.
References to God and his role in creation do indeed abound in his work. One of his earliest, formative
experiences was reading Johann Arndt’s (15551621) Vier Bücher von wahrem Christenthumb (1610),
which used Paracelsian cosmology to argue that the “book of nature” was a particularly valuable object of
religious contemplation. In a similar fashion, Linnaeus emphasized again and again that the role of the
naturalist was to exalt God by contemplating his creation, and showing how every being serves a purpose,
both with respect to each other, and to human economy (De curiositate naturali 1748; Cui bono 1752).
Building on the precedent set by John Ray (16271705) and William Derham (16571735), and in line
with Christian Wolffs (16791754) Vernünfftige Gedanken von den Absichten der natürlichen Dinge
(1723), Linnaeus played an underappreciated role as one of the chief propagators of physico-theological
arguments by design in the eighteenth century (Malmeström 1926).
Yet there are some notable idiosyncrasies in Linnaeus’s physico-theological thought as well. As far as
creation was concerned, he defended a strikingly simplistic vision. At the beginning of time, God had
created a pair of individuals or, in the case of hermaphrodites, a single individual for each species,
placed in its respective habitat on a mountainous island near the equator. The subsequent history of the
earth then consisted in nothing but propagation and a concurrent expansion of landmasses through coastal
sedimentation, leading to the present-day distribution of continents and the floras and faunas that inhabit
them (Oratio de telluris habitabilis incremento, 1744). Linnaeus argued for this view by “calculating
backwards”: that is, by assuming that the number of individuals in each species diminishes if one moves
back in time from generation to generation. In addition, empirical observations of “diminishing waters” in
his home country lent empirical support to the idea that the continents had been growing. Linnaeus’s
arguments, then, where entirely naturalistic and “actualist” – he rejected the Biblical idea of a Great Flood
, and he ended up in a considerable brawl with his colleagues in theology over it as a consequence
(Frängsmyr 1983).
Later commentators have gone so far as to call Linnaeus’s theory of creation peculiar, almost puerile”
(Broberg 2019, 179). Such retrospective judgements miss the fact that this theory formed the backbone of
Linnaeus’s highly influential concept of an “economy of nature” (Oeconomia naturae, 1749). Expanding
the concept of an “animal economy”, which referred to the division of labour between different organs in
individual animal bodies, to nature at large, Linnaeus argued that each species produces offspring at a rate
that was exactly proportionate not only to its own needs, but also to the needs of all other species in
whose life it played a vital role. Two features are remarkable about this concept. First, that “ecological
relations”, as we would call them, were conceptualized as entirely symmetrical. Prey did not only serve
predators as food, but predators also served their prey by controlling their numbers. Even parasites and
contagious diseases could be seen as “useful” (Politia naturae, 1760). And second, that the concept of a
“proportion” between two independent processes, (re-)production and consumption, lent itself to
quantification (Limoges 1972; Egerton 2007).
For Linnaeus, the economy of nature depended entirely on the “laws” instituted by God. Each species had
its predestined “place” (statio) in nature, and nature as a whole formed a balanced system. It is easy to
see, however, that this balance was highly precarious. One only needed to assume as Thomas Malthus
(17661834) famously did in his Essay on the Principle of Population (1798) a slight mismatch in rates
of reproduction and available resources for a picture of the economy of nature to emerge that included
competition, supersession and eventual extinctions among species. It is this feature that kept Linnaeus’s
economy of nature alive as a theoretical concept well into the nineteenth century. Both Augustin Pyrame
de Candolle (17781841) and Charles Lyell (17971875) relied on it in their early explorations of the
“struggle for existence”, and it continued to play a foundational role in Charles Darwin’s
conceptualization of nature as a dynamic system in which “all organic beings are striving, it may be said,
to seize on each place in the economy of nature” (Pearce 2009).
Ironically, then, it was precisely Linnaeus’s species fixism in part religiously justified, but also geared
towards his grand taxonomic project of cataloguing the species of the world that lead later figures to
consider the ecological and geographical distribution of plant and animal species as entirely contingent.
This constituted a problem that exercised Immanuel Kant (17241804) in his critique of teleological
judgement (Larson 1994; Töpfer 2019), and provoked reflections on humanity’s place in nature. Much to
the chagrin of contemporaries, Linnaeus had placed the species Homo sapiens in the order
“Anthropomorpha”, alongside apes and the sloth, in Systema naturae, and preceded to divide it up into
four “varieties: whitish Europeans, reddish Americans, tawny Asians, and blackish Africans” (Broberg
1983; Müller-Wille 2015). In one stroke, again showing his genius for “spontaneous philosophy”,
Linnaeus had constituted the object of a “natural history of mankind” (Sloan 1995), and hence the object
of philosophical reflections on race, civilisation and empire that should occupy philosophers around 1800
(Lettow 2014).
8. Cross-References
Life, Mechanization of; Alchemy, Chemistry, and Metallurgy; Natural Theology; Botany and Medicine;
Iatromechanism and Iatrochemistry; Apes; Generation Theory; Nature and Taxonomy, Systems of;
Sexual Dimorphism and Hermaphroditism in Nature; Human Diversity.
9. References
Barsanti G (1992) La scala, la mappa, l’albero. Immagini e classificazioni della natura fra Sei e
Ottocento. Sansoni, Firenze
Blunt W (1971) The compleat naturalist: a life of Linnaeus. Collins, London
Broberg G (1975) Homo sapiens L.: studier i Carl von Linnés naturuppfattning och människolära.
Almquist & Wiksell, Stockholm
Broberg G (2012) The greatest jewel in medicine. In: Hansen L (ed.) Clavis medicinae duplex = The two
keys of medicine / Carl Linnaeus. The IK Foundation, London, pp 761
Broberg G (1983) Linnaeus’s Classifications of Man. In: Frängsmyr T (ed) Linnaeus. The Man and His
Work. University of California Press, Berkeley etc.
Broberg G (2019) Mannen som ordnade naturen: en biografi över Carl von Linné. Natur & Kultur,
Stockholm (English translation in preparation)
Cain AJ (1958) Logic and memory in Linnaeus’ system of taxonomy. Proceedings of the Linnean Society
London 169:144163
Cain AJ (1992) Was Linnaeus a Rosicrucian? Linnean 8:2344
Daston L (2004) Type Specimens and Scientific Memory. Critical Inquiry 31:153182
Daudin H (1926) De Linné à Jussieu: methodes de la classification et idée de série en botanique et
zoologie (1740-1790). Alcan, Paris
Dietz B (2016) Das System der Natur: Die kollaborative Wissenskultur der Botanik im 18. Jahrhundert,
Böhlau, Köln
Egerton Frank N. (2007) A History of the Ecological Sciences, Part 23: Linnaeus and the Economy of
Nature. The Bulletin of the Ecological Society of America 88:7288.
Foucault M (1966) Les Mots et les choses: une archéologie des sciences humaines. Gallimard, Paris
Frängsmyr T (1983) Linnaeus as a Geologist. In: Frängsmyr T (ed.) Linnaeus: The man and his work.
University of California Press, Berkeley etc., pp 110155
Hövel G (1999) “Qualitates vegetabilium”, “vires medicamentorum” und “oeconomicus usus plantarum”
bei Carl von Linné (1707 - 1778). Dt. Apotheker-Verl., Braunschweig
Kelley TM (2012) Clandestine Marriage: Botany and Romantic Culture. Johns Hopkins University Press,
Boston
Koerner L (1999) Linnaeus: nature and nation. Harvard University Press, Cambridge/MA
Lepenies W (1976) Das Ende der Naturgeschichte: Wandel kultureller Selbstverständlichkeiten in d.
Wissenschaften d. 18. u. 19. Jh. Hanser, München
Lettow S (ed) (2014) Reproduction, Race, and Gender in Philosophy and the Early Life Sciences. SUNY
Press, New York
Larson JL (1971) Reason and Experience. The Representation of Natural Order in the Work of Carl
Linnaeus. University of California Press, Berkeley etc.
Larson JL (1994) Interpreting Nature. The Science of Living Form from Linnaeus to Kant. John Hopkins
University Press, Baltimore-
Lefèvre W (1999) Natural or Artificial Systems? The 18th-Century Controversy on Classification of
Animals and Plants and its Philosophical Contexts. In: Lefèvre W (ed) Between Leibniz, Newton, and
Kant. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 191209
Lesch JE (1990) Systematics and the geometrical spirit. In: Frängsmyr T et al (eds) The Quantifying
Spirit in the Eighteenth Century. University of California Press, Berkeley, pp 73111
Limoges C (1972) Introduction. In: Charles Linné: L’ équilibre de la nature. Vrin, Paris, pp 724
Lindroth S (1983) The Two Faces of Linnaeus. In: Frängsmyr T (ed.) Linnaeus. The Man and His Work.
University of California Press, Berkeley, pp 162
Lyon J (1976) The “Initial Discourse” to Buffon’s ‘Histoire Naturelle’: The First Complete English
Translation. Journal of the History of Biology 9:133181
Malmeström E (1926) Carl von Linnés religiösa åskådning. Svenska Kyrkans Diakonistyrelse, Stockholm
Malmeström E (1964) Carl von Linné: geniets kamp för klarhet. Bonniers, Stockholm
Mayr E (1982) The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution and Inheritance. Belknap Press,
Cambridge/MA
McOuat GR (2001) From Cutting Nature at its Joints to Measuring it: New Kinds and New Kinds of
People in Biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 32:613645
ller-Wille S (2007a) Figures of inheritance, 1650-1850. In: Müller-Wille S, Rheinberger H-J (eds)
Heredity Produced: At the Crossroads of Biology, Politics, and Culture, 1500-1870. MIT Press,
Cambridge/MA, pp 177204
Müller-Wille S (2007b) Collection and Collation: Theory and Practice of Linnaean Botany. Studies in
History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences 38:541562
Müller-Wille S (2015) Linnaeus and the Four Corners of the World. In: Coles KA et al (eds) The Cultural
Politics of Blood, 15001900. Palgrave Macmillan UK, London, pp 191209
Müller-Wille S (2017) Names and Numbers: “Data” in Classical Natural History, 1758–1859. Osiris
32:109128
ller-Wille S (2018) Linnaeus and the Love Lives of Plants. In: Hopwood N, Flemming R, Kassell L
(eds) Reproduction: Antiquity to the Present Day. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 305318
Müller-Wille S, Charmantier I (2012) Natural history and information overload: The case of Linnaeus.
Studies in History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences 43:415.
Müller-Wille S, Orel V (2007) From Linnaean Species to Mendelian Factors: Elements of Hybridism,
1751-1870. Annals of Science 64:171215
Pratt V (1985) System-Building in the Eighteenth Century. In: The Light of Nature. Essays in the History
and Philosophy of Science presented to A.C. Crombie. Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht etc., pp 421431
Rheinberger H-J (1986) Aspekte des Bedeutungswandels im Begriff organismischer Ähnlichkeit vom 18.
zum 19. Jahrhundert. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 8:237250
Schiebinger L (1993) Nature’s Body: Gender in the making of Modern Science. Beacon Press, Boston
Schmitt S (2010) Introduction. In: Buffon G, Œuvres complètes, vol. 5. Honoré Champion, Paris, pp 776
Shteir PAB (1999) Cultivating Women, Cultivating Science: Flora’s Daughters and Botany in England,
1760 to 1860. The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore
Sloan PR (1976) The Buffon-Linnaeus controversy. Isis 67:356375
Sörlin S (2000) Ordering the world for Europe: science as intelligence and information as seen from the
Northern periphery. Osiris 15:5169.
Soulsby BH (1933) A catalogue of the works of Linnaeus, 2nd ed. British Museum, London
Stevens PF (1994) The Development of Systematics: Antoine-Laurent de Jussieu, Nature and the Natural
System. Columbia University Press, New York
Stevens PF, Cullen SP (1990) Linnaeus, the cortex-medulla theory, and the key to his understanding of
plant form and natural relationships. Journal of the Arnold Arboretum 71:179220
Töpfer G (2019) Philosophy of Ecology Long before Ecology. In: Bognon-Küss C, Wolfe CT (eds.)
Philosophy of Biology Before Biology. Routledge, London, pp 13145
Wikman KR (1970) Lachesis and Nemesis. Four Chapters on the Human Condition in the Writings of
Carl Linnaeus. Almqvist & Wiksell, Stockholm
Winsor MP (2015) Considering affinity: An ethereal conversation. Endeavour 39:69-79, 116-126, 179-
187.
Article
Full-text available
With a growing curiosity in anthropomorphic robots, academics and interested parties have started to examine the ethical implications and social impacts of their (mis)use. Gender in anthropomorphic robots is a field that is slowly beginning to receive attention. Yet, its ambiguity has led to treating gender in anthropomorphic robots in a reductionist fashion, pointing to how stereotypical characteristics make certain gender identities and practices legible. I illustrate that the making of gendered bodies goes beyond the oversimplification of stereotypical readable gender cues. Thus, relational and corporeal ways of connecting people and technological artifacts can help to (de)construct the practices of gendering the human body and the body of anthropomorphic robots. This entails ‘alive genders’. By ‘alive genders’ I am referring to an approach which keeps understandings of gender destabilized and evolving. This not only brings awareness to the interdependence of the human body and the body of anthropomorphic robots but helps designers and roboticists to study the gendering of robots as a part of social practices.
Chapter
Full-text available
Many accounts of the history of the race concept place the naturalist Carl Linnaeus (1707–78), and his Systema Naturae (1735), at the beginning of modern concepts of race, in contrast to older notions that did not yet reduce race to physical traits, but presented it as the outcome of an inextricable entanglement of blood, soil, and customs.1 In the slim, 11-page folio Systema Naturae (1735) that laid the foundations for the 22-year-old Swedish medical student’s future claim to fame, “man (Homo)” was presented as part of the animal kingdom in a two-page tabular arrangement of classes, orders, and genera (Figure 9.1). Placing humans among the class of four-footed animals (Quadrupedia)—animals possessing a hairy body (corpus hirsutum), four feet (pedes quatuor), as well as viviparous and breastfeeding females (feminae viviparae, lactiferae)— and, within that class, among the order of the “human-shaped” (Anthropomorpha)—alongside the apes (Simia), and the sloth (Bradypus)— Linnaeus cleverly defined the genus Homo not by some presumably universal morphological or physiological feature, but by the human capacity for self-knowledge. What is interesting about this definition is that it addresses the reader by citing the famous dictum “Know thyself” (Nosce te ipsum), and then proceeds to split up the genus Homo into four distinct groups: the white European, the red American, the tawny Asian, and the black African.2
Article
The late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries saw the transition from natural history to the history of nature. This essay analyzes institutional, social, and technological changes in natural history associated with this epochal change. Focusing on the many posthumous reeditions of Carl Linnaeus’s Systema Naturae that began to appear throughout Europe and beyond from the 1760s onward, I will argue that Linnaean nomenclature and classification reorganized and enhanced flows of data—a term already used in natural history—among individual naturalists and institutions. Plant and animal species became units that could be “slotted” into collections and publications, reshuffled and exchanged, kept track of in lists and catalogs, and counted and distributed in new ways. On two fronts—biogeography and the search for the “natural system”—this brought to the fore new, intriguing relationships among organisms of diverse kinds. By letting nature speak through the “artificial” means and media of early systematics, I argue, new and powerful visions of an unruly nature emerged that became the object of early evolutionary theories. Natural history was an “information science” that processed growing quantities of data and held the same potential for surprising insights as today’s data-intensive sciences.