ResearchPDF Available

What is Environmental Aesthetics

Authors:

Abstract

One of the most encouraging signs in the widespread interest in environmental values is the recognition of the importance of the aesthetic. Aesthetic values are a large part of what draws people to environmental activities and issues. But this is not as simple as it may seem. Many ideas and issues are easily confused here, and not the least of these is the nature of environmental aesthetics. Confusion often surrounds those committed to the idea of environmental aesthetics. It is like discord in a family in which everyone loves everyone else but no one can say anything without misunderstanding and discord. In neither case is this inevitable. Let me take the easy task and talk about environmental aesthetics. Like so many disagreements, profound as well as trivial, people with environmental concerns share many of the same interests and values but don't know how to talk about them with one another. clearly and understandably. Much of the difficulty comes from a confusion about what is understood by 'aesthetics.' Philosophers and other scholars see aesthetics as a branch of philosophy concerned with understanding the intrinsic values we ascribe to works of art and to natural beauty. What does appreciation consist of here? Where is the value located that we recognize in appreciation? How do other values bear on aesthetic value? In what ways do our knowledge and understanding play a part in recognizing these values, values not only aesthetic but others, such as moral, economic, and historical?
1
WHAT IS ENVIRONMENTAL AESTHETICS?
One of the most encouraging signs in the widespread interest in environmental values is
the recognition of the importance of the aesthetic. Aesthetic values are a large part of
what draws people to environmental activities and issues. But this is not as simple as it
may seem. Many ideas and issues are easily confused here, and not the least of these
is the nature of environmental aesthetics.
Confusion often surrounds those committed to the idea of environmental aesthetics. It
is like discord in a family in which everyone loves everyone else but no one can say
anything without misunderstanding and discord. In neither case is this inevitable. Let
me take the easy task and talk about environmental aesthetics.
Like so many disagreements, profound as well as trivial, people with environmental
concerns share many of the same interests and values but don't know how to talk
about them with one another. clearly and understandably. Much of the difficulty comes
from a confusion about what is understood by 'aesthetics.' Philosophers and other
scholars see aesthetics as a branch of philosophy concerned with understanding the
intrinsic values we ascribe to works of art and to natural beauty. What does
appreciation consist of here? Where is the value located that we recognize in
appreciation? How do other values bear on aesthetic value? In what ways do our
knowledge and understanding play a part in recognizing these values, values not only
aesthetic but others, such as moral, economic, and historical?
1. environment
Perhaps we can begin by considering what environment is. In Western cultures we are
accustomed to segregating and objectifying whatever we are trying to understand. This
is the time-honored approach of scientific inquiry and it has funded remarkable
advances in knowledge, knowledge that exemplifies Francis Bacon's understanding of
man's power over nature. While this approach has transformed the conditions and
quality of human life, the heedless exploitation of the gifts of nature have desensitized
us to the state of our environment and has led us to the point of self-destruction, where
2
the very conditions of human life are threatened: water, air, food, and psychological and
social well-being.
This situation belies the philosophical premise underlying the domination and
exploitation of nature. It demonstrates the undeniable fact that we cannot wholly
objectify nature. We cannot segregate nature or separate ourselves from environment.
We are, flesh and bone, the product of the environment with which we coexist. Not only
our activities but our thoughts and feelings are profoundly influenced by climate,
topography, wind, and water conditions. We are, in other words, inseparable from our
environment. That is why one should speak of environment rather than "the"
environment. When we talk about "the" environment, we tend to treat it as something
independent of us, as a separate place. It is as if we could objectify environment, give it
limits-- circumscribe it. On the other hand, speaking simply of "environment" recognizes
that environment is indeterminate, that its extent varies with the situation. Moreover and
most importantly, "environment" is not "out there" but includes me as an active part.
Environment is always "here."
2. two senses of 'aesthetics
But what does this have to do with aesthetics? 'Aesthetics' is the key term here and it is
used with two different meanings. One refers to appreciation and the other to
philosophical understanding.
Popular meaning differs from the philosophical. It identifies the aesthetic as an
important value, beauty, that is present along with the other interests we have in
environment. Just as humans are not distinct from nature nor especially favored by
nature, aesthetic values are embedded in natural conditions. Our experiences with the
natural world are suffused with aesthetic values, from the greening of the grass in early
spring to the ever-changing cloud formations in the sky. We find delight and renewal in
these simple perceptions, not to mention the poignant intimacy of a flower and
spectacular vistas across the landscape. And it is well that we recognize these
aesthetic values. They bring free delight to our lives and may evoke a sense of our
3
ephemeral participation in those processes. This pleasurable awareness has been
called "the aesthetic appreciation of nature. "
But what such appreciation consists in, how it can be described, and how and why it
should be cultivated are other, different questions, philosophical questions. Sensitive
awareness and appreciation of the sensory conditions in environmental experience fill
the greater part of our lives, whether we engage with the cosmic glories of a sunset,
poke our way through the squalor of a slum, or try to find our way through the drab
uniformity of a suburban development. We delight in glimpsing the glistening skin of a
seal as it breaks the surface of the water, in the expanse of the landscape we inhabit as
it radiates from us in every direction, just as we thrill to the pristine surface of a fresh
snowfall that hides every blemish and irregularity, or marvel in the impartiality and
profusion of nature with the delicate greens of leaves bursting their casings in early
spring. It enriches us to be aware of such sensory qualities and to enjoy them for their
intrinsic appeal and unique qualities.
This is the aesthetic appreciation of environment. It is 'aesthetic' in the adjectival sense
and life is the better for recognizing and enjoying the perceptual qualities of
environment. This appreciation is not the same as the meaning we give to such
experiences and our understanding that tries to identify what that aesthetic value is.
This is aesthetics as a noun, as a cognitive discipline, as the name of a field of
philosophical inquiry. The word ‘aesthetic’ comes from the Greek aisthesis, literally,
perception by the senses, and whatever more we would like to say about this, sensory
awareness is a central part of the experience we call aesthetic. To my mind, this is its
core philosophical meaning.
Thus there is a basicdifference between aesthetic appreciation (experience) and our
understanding of such experiences (aesthetic theory). The first is an experience of
active receptivity, while the second is a cognitive act of describing and explaining that
experience. When we say that we should approach such experiences with openness
and without preconceptions, we are expressing an idea about aesthetic appreciation
(philosophical aesthetics). When we insist that moral and social values should be
excluded from aesthetic appreciation, we are making a philosophical claim, just as in
4
the assertion that artists should be free to follow their creative intuitions and not be
bound by social, political, or moral conventions.
Appreciation can be developed. Some environmental values are so direct that it takes
no more than noticing them to evoke appreciation, although such attention is not
automatic and can be enhanced by focusing our attention. It is easy to be
environmentally blind and simply unaware of the quality of light or the temperature of
the air. We may fail to notice the décor of a room or the color of a person’s eyes.
Having these pointed out can make us aware of environmental values that, of course,
are everywhere and always present to a receptive sensibility. Moreover, these
aesthetic environmental values are not always positive. Who has not noticed the smells
of an incinerator or a fast-food restaurant; who has not been besieged by the attention-
seeking signage along a commercial strip or forced into a protective stupor by the
soporific sounds of Muzak in a restaurant or waiting room?
All these are experiences of aesthetic value. But when we try to understand them,
when we discuss why some are pleasant and positive and others are not, whether their
value is situated in the object, in our feelings or other responses, or in the total situation
in which we experience them, we are entering into an aesthetic query. Such inquiry
happens, too, when we compare differing experiences and judgments of aesthetic
value. Aesthetic inquiry informs the debate on whether moral criteria are relevant in
judging a movie or aesthetic criteria in planning a slum clearance project.
It is important to be clear about the difference between appreciation and understanding.
It does not promote environmental values to confuse the two; on the contrary, it
enriches our encounters with these values in recognizing that they are different. So
perhaps it would be best to leave debates about aesthetic environmental values to the
discussion table and center on our experiences of aesthetic value as we delight in our
walks in the woods or strolls in an historic district.
Arnold Berleant
4 June 2017 (1419 words)
... In addition to place-based memories, photographs focussed on the aesthetics of natural environments (Berleant, 1992(Berleant, , 1997, human and nonhuman relationships (Basu, 2020), belonging and community (Mee & Wright, 2009), and restorative or 'soulful' places (Hooks, 2009). The ten photographs that were mutually chosen to be included in the 'Finding Home' exhibition are reproduced below. ...
Chapter
This contribution confronts the utopia of paradise with the reality of gardens. It explores greentopian relations to nature in the practice of gardening, arguing that, in search of a good relationship with nature, it is not enough to imagine one of paradisiac harmony; it is rather a question of practice—of how we engage with nature in our everyday lives. The garden is a place that integrates both: the utopian promise of living well with nature, and the challenge of putting this idea into practice, which is the very challenge of gardening. It is then shown how the gardener’s involvement with nature is promoted by the exercise of specific virtues. These virtues of gardening are analysed for their greentopian potential, explaining how they contribute to a sustainable, down-to-earth way of dealing and living with nature that promotes both human and non-human flourishing.
Chapter
Gordon compares the materialist ontologies of David Bentley Hart and Gilles Deleuze to propose an aesthetic approach to environmental ethics. Environmental aesthetics is often associated with a principle of ‘disinterestedness’ when evaluating relationships between subjects and their environments; disinterestedness requires that an individual’s aesthetic responses are separate from their desires. The materialist ontologies he explores, however, do not support firm boundaries between individuals and their environments. They are thus open to the possibility of aesthetic approaches to environmental ethics which do not require disinterestedness; the interests and desires of a subject are necessary considerations for an ethical evaluation of their relationship to their environment.
Chapter
I have been a senior lecturer in philosophy of education in a self-described ‘entrepreneurial’ university on the Hertfordshire-London border (UK) since 2014. In the early stages of my career, my main work focussed on philosophy of education, within a school of education that prioritised teacher education as its main work and source of ‘income’. My main teaching area focussed on philosophical studies in education, not initial teacher training. Subsequently my interests broadened and I started a part-time PhD alongside full-time work in environmental aesthetics and educational journeying at a university in Edinburgh. More recently, I have undertaken strategic roles in curriculum development. In 2021 I led a degree validation for a set of postgraduate programmes for inclusive outdoor environmental education in urban and peri-urban environments in the East and South-East of England. The programmes are designed using socio-ecological justice principles and enable students to undertake authentic learning experiences by making social contributions inside and outside of the university. My research and practice-based enquiries have focussed on student-staff partnership in higher education (HE), HE and engaged democratic citizenship, and the neglect of attending to the body in learning.
Chapter
This article examines the ideas of ‘aesthetic pleasure’ and ‘aesthetic appreciation of nature’ in the Anthropocene. In the framework of the current ecological crisis, the anthropogenic roots of which are today beyond dispute, are the aesthetic categories of ‘beautiful’, ‘sublime’, ‘majestic’ etc. still appropriate to describe our experience of nature? Can a landscape – or an animal or a plant – which have undergone changes and modifications due to climate change (a human-induced phenomenon) still be considered beautiful? More generally, is the idea of nature as an object of aesthetic contemplation still legitimate in the Anthropocene?
Chapter
Full-text available
Article
Full-text available
Transit infrastructure is a critical determinant of the layout and sustainability performance of residential landscapes and neighborhoods. Though the spatial aspects of transit design and their associated impact on health, congestion, air pollution, accident rates, and emissions of greenhouse gases are well understood, the experiential-qualitative aspects of mobility have often been ignored in the travel and transport literature. This paper presents the place-understandings of pedestrians and cyclists concerning neighborhood safety in Dushanbe, the capital city of Tajikistan. Community perspectives were captured through drawing and storytelling workshops as a method of public engagement through creative experience. While reporting on the veracity of this collaborative, creative, and place-based methodology, the paper presents workshop outcomes that describe problematic non-auto neighborhood transit experiences that, if unchecked, could constitute a significant challenge to the sustainable post-Soviet transformation of Dushanbe’s residential neighborhoods.
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any references for this publication.