ArticlePDF Available

The (In)Definition of Reality: Reframing and Contested Topsight

Authors:

Abstract

Perhaps reality as such cannot be represented, or defined. It has to be defined with respect to a specific activity, and it has to be represented from a given perspective, a selective one. In this attempt at a definition of reality as "what happens between the lines" I am proposing a perspective by emphasizing what happens between the lines — instead of emphasizing, for instance, the lines themselves. The lines might stand for "what is" obviously there, reality as presupposed or unproblematic, reality as something shared by its inhabitants. But an interactional perspective on reality must go beyond that portion of reality or that interactional activity which is shared (or is "true") for all interactants, in order to give a fuller portrait of those aspects of reality which are not shared, which may be false or nonexistent to some of the participants, or which may be perceived only by some of them. This perspective on reality requires the use of narratological concepts, such as retrospection or the notion of topsight. Date Written: February 29, 2016 Keywords: Social Interaction, Phenomenology, Attention, Symbolic Interactionism, Frame Theory, and Reality
1
The (In)definition of Reality:
Reframing and Contested Topsight
José Angel GARCÍA LANDA
Universidad de Zaragoza
I shall put forward here a definition of reality, or perhaps a particular take or
perspective on reality. Reality is what happens between the lines.
But perhaps reality as such cannot be represented, or defined. It has to be
defined with respect to a specific activity, and it has to be represented from a
given perspective, a selective one. In this attempt at a definition I am proposing a
perspective by the very fact of emphasizing what happens between the lines
instead of emphasizing, for instance, the lines themselves. The lines might stand
for "what is" obviously there, reality as presupposed or unproblematic, reality as
something shared by its inhabitants. But an interactional perspective on reality
must go beyond that portion of reality which is shared (or "true") for all
interactants, in order to give a fuller portrait of those aspects of reality which are
not shared, which may be false or nonexistent to some of the participants, or
which may be perceived only by some of them.
Still, perhaps we do need a definition of reality which is more comprehensive,
more balanced and less paradoxical. I will therefore modify my original
statement, and further specify that reality is the play, the dynamic interaction, or
the dialectic, between what happens for the public record, and what happens
between the lines. Or again, reality is constituted by the interactional play
between shared frames of action (those "lines" which are unproblematically on
the page) and other frames which, though they may be active for some of the
participants, are not generally shared. Reality is a play of realitiesthe explicit
one, and other secret, discreet or alternative realities which coexist in a given
situation.
Reality, then, lends itself to a definition (although perhaps the definition is not
actually written on any labels or captions). It is defined by presuppositions, by
habits, by socially regulated modes of interaction, by institutions, routines,
scripts, and frames of interactional communication. These frames, schemas, and
presuppositions have been studied by theorists of cognition, of pragmatics, of
interpersonal communication, such as Bateson, Schank and Abelson, Sperber and
Wilson, etc. It is perhaps Erving Goffman's frame analysis that provides the most
comprehensive and most suggestive version of the structure of reality
including the structure of multiple interacting realities.
Goffman provides a powerful model for the analysis of interactional reality:
dramatism. Human interaction is organized in principle by shared templates
which define and narrativize the situation and provide roles for the participants.
It is through these shared templates or frames that we are able to shape reality
as to what is at stake, what is happening, in a given moment or situation. What
happens (officially) at any moment is, for instance, a meeting at the workplace, a
concert, a party, a friendly conversation over a beer: any of these archetypal
2
scripts which orchestrate social reality inasmuch as it is living theatretheatre
played by social actors in real-life dramatic companies, and in a social space
which has a theatrical structure. This is the perspective on social life provided by
Goffman in The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life, in Interaction Ritual, or in
Strategic Interaction.
What takes place between the lines is what Goffman calls a secondary channel
it is an alternative strip of activity which could also be described as a
superimposed narrative linea subplot which does not involve all of the
participants in the main frame of activity or primary channel, but only some of
themor perhaps just one, the observer of that hidden dimension of reality
which is taking place between the lines, the one who sees what the other
participants cannot seethose aspects of reality that escape them and are, in a
sense, both there and not there.
It is within this structural set of perspectival relationships that we can describe
the concept of topsight. Topsight is the privileged perspectival position enjoyed
by those participants who see what others don't see, the position of those
observers who are aware of the secondary as well as the primary channel of
interactional activity. Topsight need not be an absolute position, since there may
be a number of secondary channels or sub-frames imposed on the main frame of
activity, and there is no telling that one of them has absolute dominance over the
others. Topsight, then, is relative to other interactant's lack of awareness of a
given secondary frame, within a comprehensive frame of activity.
To take a simple example, the main frame may be provided by a meeting at work.
The participants are all aware of each other's presence. However, their roles are,
as far as the meeting is concerned, those of spectators or listeners, given that just
now the boss is doing a presentation. It may well happen that two participants at
the meeting may begin to interact, whispering about their plans for the evening,
while the boss preaches on and all the others dutifully listen. Now these two
employees have assumed a different role in the social theatrethey are not
merely there in their official capacity; they have assumed a temporary role as
private individuals. Just now we'll not investigate any further whether they are
lifting their official mask for a moment, or merely donning an additional mask.
However that may be, reality multiplies itself and acquires another level of
articulation through this secret interactional move, a move which is defined as
secondary by its very location within the wider frame within which it is
embedded.
But if this secret or discreet piece of interaction is perceived and spied upon by a
third partyby another employee who feigns she is not listening, or, why not, by
the reader of my examplethen the structure of reality is no longer doubled, but
tripled, or multiplied, in a game of interactional perspectives. Much of the
structure of a narrative account of this meeting, or indeed of any interactional
encounter, would consist in a description of the perspectival relationships
among the agents as they are established and new dimensions of reality appear,
or in the gradual and artistic unfolding of existing perspectival relationships
3
which reveals the existing interactional and cognitive situation to a reader or a
virtual observer.
Let us examine another example of the observational frame in an analysis of
narrative structures. Take this poem from Stephen Crane's The Black Riders (IX),
a micro-narrative in its own right:
I STOOD UPON A HIGH PLACE,
AND SAW, BELOW, MANY DEVILS
RUNNING, LEAPING,
AND CAROUSING IN SIN.
ONE LOOKED UP, GRINNING,
AND SAID, "COMRADE! BROTHER!"
Here the narrator is standing "upon a high place", which we might take as
symbolizing his perspectival and discursive topsight in the textual structure,
above the other characters. The devils are involved in their own interactional
frame ("running, leaping, and carousing in sin"), and in the first sentence of the
micro-narrative they are unaware that they are being observed. The narrator,
the "I", commands two strips of activity: he is aware, like the devils, of the more
widely shared frame, the devils' carousal. He is also aware of another strip of
activity, namely his own awareness of the situationthe fact that the party is
being watched from above by a non-participant, and the devils' ignorance of this.
The second frame is more limited as regards participation; in principle the "I" is
the only one taking part in it. The devils' party has become for him an objectified
event, a spectacle which, however disgusting, can be safely enjoyed by a
spectator who contemplates it from the outside; this interactional strip is self-
enclosed as far as the devils are concerned, and the frame is like a theatrical
fourth wall which prevents the devils from taking part in the focalizer's
observational frame. Note that the frame is for the devils the very limit of
realityin a certain sense is not even a frame because for them there is nothing
outside the frame.
Of course, the perspectival structure posited by the first sentence is undone or
deconstructed in the second sentence, which provides a narrative resolution
through frame-breaking. Although frames are constantly being broken, any
frame-breaking has a somewhat paradoxical air about it (Genette's métalepses
come to mind), and indeed two different realities, or two different dimensions of
reality are meeting through these frame-breakings, and a new reality has to
emerge dialectically. In our example, the upright and dignified verticality of the
"I" is threatened by the piercing gaze of the devil, which, ascending upwards
from below, and breaking through the perspectival containers, seems to threaten
the very purity of heaven, and to sully with its foulness the very soul of the
readerbecause it was the reader, gazing down on the words and letters of the
poem, those black devils involved in their own game(cf. The Black Riders,
XLVI)it was the reader who was "I," towering over the page, looking down,
vicariously, over the narrator's shoulder. The reader, too, thought he was safe in
his own extratextual frame, but he is safe no more, because the text can gaze
back at him and the devil recognizes him for his brother. Even a sister can feel a
4
jolt at the invasion of her private frame, and at her being demoted from her
privileged topsight.
Reality is suddenly reorganized, reworkedbecause human reality is an
interactional reality, managed through frames and their operations, through
their being established and operated, through their recyclings and
displacements, and through their rearrangements, dissolutions and sudden
merges.
Stephen Crane's text might be further analysed along these lines. But our
concern is now with the notion of frame itself, and its role in the managing of
reality through attention. Note that in this example, we have called the devils'
party the main frame, on the criterion that it is the more generally shared one.
There is a potential ambiguity here, however, because the narrator's
observational frame is more potent in another senseprecisely because it is not
generally shared, because it is hidden, it makes for dominance, and is the "outer"
frame in its own perspectival structure, the comprehensive observational
situation which includes an enclosed object of observation. Still, the observer's
frame, while it provides the outermost frame, could not exist without an object
which is framed by it; in this sense it is subordinate to the devils' pandemonic
party, i.e. to the most widely shared interactional frame, or primary channel. It is
advisable to keep in mind this perspectival ambivalence. The perspectives of the
many provide the general interactional game on which the dominant
perspectives of the few are built as a second story. But this secondary or
embedded story encompasses within its perspectival structure, quite
paradoxically, the general frame as a field dominated by the observers' topsight,
by a viewpoint which itself escapes observation, or tries to.
In our account, the subject who perceives most of these interactional frames and
perspectival relationships is that silent woman, the observer of the employees'
small talk at the meeting; or the implied author of The Black Riders, designing a
narrative structure in which narrative topsight is paradoxically questioned. It is
such cognitive (or narrative) subjects that provide our model for cognitive
topsight, those who perceive most dimensions of reality the "I"s who (in our
account) observe the interactional landscape from a high place, the watchtower
of topsight, or of hindsight, as the case may be. This "I" who stands highest, or
who comes last of all, is the observer who observes those-who-believe-that-they-
are-observing-without-being-observed. It is a quasi-divine perspectival topsight; a
misleading one, therefore, and one which is analyzed by Lacan in his famous
seminar on Edgar Allan Poe's story "The Purloined Letter". (This structure
invites recursion, and I have pursued this line of analysis further in my paper
"Acritical Criticism, Critical Criticism"). We have seen that Crane's poem, too,
may be read as a miniature model of this deconstructive move.
Yet another example. We converse with someone; we listen and watch her face
and body movements. What she says is one thinga function of the officially
established activity, whether work or leisure. On-record discourse is the main
frame or primary channelit is what is said. But what is shown may be
something else. We watch a multimedia performanceinvolving proxemics,
5
intonation, gestures, kinesics, paralanguage, style, eye contact, interactional
rhythmn. The body and its theatricality, the secondary channel, is often more
worth attending to; it tells the truth which is half-concealed by the words. Or, if
the encounter resists interpretation, at least it is there that we try to disclose the
elusive reality of the matter; not in the scripted words, but in the full theatrical
spectacle, and especially in the gestures, or sub-gestures. Topsight is here an
object of desire, a virtual position defining cognitive control, but one which must
be imagined rather than fully inhabited.
Perhaps we should provide a new definition of the reality effect, to use Barthes'
phrase, or a different approach to that effect. As I see it, the reality effect is not so
much where Barthes located it in that famous article (in irrelevant or non-
significant detailsalthough it is there too, to some extent); it is to be found, first
and foremost, in that play of perspectives where two different realities clash or
come to terms with each other; two (or more) realities defined by different
interactional frames. The anomic interface between these realities is the
battleground or the sports field where reality is managed and organized. To be
sure, it is being interactionally managed all the time, but it is in the meeting of
games of in the space between them (is it baseball or football that we are playing
here?) that roles must be reworked and rules must be improvised, at the very
least to the extent of preventing general embarrassment. It is in such
dramaturgically uncertain situations, and they happen all the time, that reality
falls apart. And while it is being managed and restructured it reveals itself for
what it is, a set of interactionally organized reality games which sustain the
edifice of appearances. Reality at its rawest also reveals itself as an
indeterminate no man's land between those games, and as the social engineering
which builds briges between them, in a variety of styles ranging from the pitiful
to the masterful.
There are many realities, possibly more than our philosophy would allow for, but
they are no more equal than Orwell's animals. The dominant reality is the
official, publicly recognized one, organized into familiar interactional ceremonies
which are universally or at least widely shared. It must be acknowledged to have
a degree of public priority, and an authority which appears to be the authority of
evidence itself. Actually, such primary realities seem to be so solid that we
usually forget that they are a function of the theatre of everyday life. More
specific reality games (e.g. a theatrical function embedded in everyday life) seem
by contrast transitory, obviously fictional, and they contribute to the reality
effect of the primary frame: if Hamlet is a play, surely I'm outside the frame and
I'm not in a play myself? The authority of the real is thereby reinforced, even
though it will appear that this force of the obvious is generated by a perspectival
or structural effect.
Stillor, what is more, in contrast with this primary frame of everyday life,
Channel 1 of the interactional life-world if you want, the secondary frames which
are built upon it, Channel 2, Channel 3, etc., also have an experiential priority of
their own. A secondary frame opens up a provisional strip of reality in the world,
and this reality may acquire a special intensity, enticing us to an intense
involvement in it. Secondary realities may be just as immersive as any first-
6
degree life-world. Channels 2 or 3, moreover, enjoy an enhanced immediacy
derived precisely from our active involvement in world-buildingfrom their
being in contrast to the primary level of reality, and from the continued existence
of that primary reality as a backdrop, at once a background noise and a ground
floor on which to build the upper stories. If our conversation takes place on the
second floor, it is that floor which provides the immediate ground for our feet,
however much the structure of the whole story may rest on the foundations of
the first floor. After all, the ground floor may be built on an invisible basement,
and in the last analysis the earth itself is a groundless basement floating within a
system of inexplicable forces.
Unofficial or secondary realities, secret interactions and provisional fictions,
therefore, do have a primacy of their own, an ontological priority which derives
from the experiential priority of reality-management. The interactional difficulty
of managing many frames and modes of reality without losing sight of our shared
life-world provides us with a never-ending challenge, one which allows us to
inhabit life as a slippery space of intense semiosis, a no-man's land (nor no-
woman's neither) of interactional risk and uncertainty, rather than a well-
rehearsed and predictable repertory play. Authentic experience is defined as
such between the acts, and behind the scenes in the theatre of everyday life.
References
Barthes, Roland. "The Reality Effect." In French Literary Theory Today: A Reader.
Ed. Tzvetan Todorov. Cambridge: Cambridge UP; Paris: Editions de la
Maison des Sciences de l'Homme, 1982. 11-17.
Bateson, Gregory. Steps to an Ecology of Mind. New York: Ballantine, 1972.
Crane, Stephen. The Black Riders and Other Lines: Published May 11, 1895. Online
at the Stephen Crane Society website.
http://public.wsu.edu/~campbelld/crane/black.htm
2016
http://public.wsu.edu/~campbelld/crane/black.htm
2016
García Landa, José Angel. "Acritical Criticism, Critical Criticism: Critical
Interaction, Reframing and Topsight." In Con/Texts of Persuasion. Ed.
Beatriz Penas et al. Kassel: Edition Reichenberger, 2011. 233-68.
_____. "La perspectiva dominante en El Arte de la Guerra: Más aspectos de un
clásico chino (Topsight in The Art of War: Further Aspects of a Chinese
Classic)." Social Science Research Network 9 Nov. 2014.
http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2520473
2014
Genette, Gérard. Narrative Discourse. Trans. Jane E. Lewin. Foreword by Jonathan
Culler. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1980. Goffman, Erving. jThe Presentation of Self
in Everyday Life. Rev. ed. Garden City (NY): Doubleday-Anchor, 1959.
_____. Interaction Ritual: Essays on Face-to-Face Behavior. New York: Random
House-Pantheon, 1982.
_____. Strategic Interaction. (Conduct and Communication, 1). Philadelphia: U of
Pennsylvania P, cop. 1969. 2nd pr., 1970.
7
_____. Frame Analysis: An Essay on the Organization of Experience. Foreword by
Bennett M. Berger. Boston: Northeastern UP, 1986.
Lacan, Jacques. "Seminar on 'The Purloined Letter'." Trans. Jeffrey Mehlman. In
The Purloined Poe: Lacan, Derrida, and Psychoanalytic Reading. Ed. John P.
Muller and William J. Richardson. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1988. 28-
54.
Schank, Roger C., and Robert P. Abelson. Scripts, Plans, Goals and Understanding:
An Inquiry into Human Knowledge. Hillsdale (NJ): Erlbaum, 1977.
Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson. Relevance: Communication and Cognition. 2nd
ed. Oxford: Blackwell, 1995.
_____
The research for this paper has been supported by the European Social Fund and
the Aragonese Government research programme H69 HERAF: Hermenéutica y
Antropología Fenomenológica.
Article
Frame Analysis , ouvrage tardif dans l’œuvre d’Erving Goffman, suscita à sa parution, et dans les années qui suivirent, une réception étonnamment controversée pour un chercheur aussi reconnu qu’il l’était à l’époque. Il vaut la peine de reconstituer cet épisode de l’histoire de la sociologie américaine, et de tenter d’en repérer les causes. En effet, au-delà du cas particulier de ce livre, il soulève des questions théoriques récurrentes dans l’histoire mondiale des sciences sociales, tenant notamment aux statuts respectifs de l’interactionnisme et du structuralisme et, plus généralement, à l’importance qu’il convient d’accorder aux catégorisations théoriques.
Article
Full-text available
This paper theorizes critical readings from an interactional / argumentative perspective, providing a semiotic and phenomenological analysis of the scale ranging from consonant, "friendly" criticism, to dissonant, confrontational or "unfriendly" criticism. A number of key critical theories (by theorists such as G. W. F. Hegel, Oscar Wilde, Jacques Lacan, Erving Goffman, Norman Holland, Jacques Derrida, Stanley Fish, Paul Ricoeur, Judith Fetterley, John Muller, Alan Sinfield, and H. Porter Abbott) are examined in the light of this conception of criticism, and situated within the framework of interactional pragmatics, of the dialectics of communication, and of a semiotic theory of truth and of consciousness. _________________________________________ Este artículo teoriza las modalidades de lectura crítica desde una perspectiva interaccional-argumentativa, proponiendo un análisis semiótico y fenomenológico de la escala que se extiende desde la crítica consonante, "amistosa", a la crítica disonante, confrontativa o "antipática". Se examinan diversas teorías críticas a la luz de esta concepción, procedentes de teorizadores como G. W. F. Hegel, Oscar Wilde, Jacques Lacan, Erving Goffman, Norman Holland, Jacques Derrida, Stanley Fish, Paul Ricoeur, Judith Fetterley, John Muller, Alan Sinfield, y H. Porter Abbott, y se sitúan estas teoría es el marco de la pragmática interaccional, de la dialéctica de la comunicación, y de una teoría semiótica de la verdad y de la consciencia.
Article
For both people and machines, each in their own way, there is a serious problem in common of making sense out of what they hear, see, or are told about the world. The conceptual apparatus necessary to perform even a partial feat of understanding is formidable and fascinating. Our analysis of this apparatus is what this book is about. —Roger C. Schank and Robert P. Abelson from the Introduction (http://www.psypress.com/scripts-plans-goals-and-understanding-9780898591385)
Cambridge: Cambridge UP; Paris: Editions de la Maison des Sciences de l'Homme
  • Roland Barthes
Barthes, Roland. "The Reality Effect." In French Literary Theory Today: A Reader. Ed. Tzvetan Todorov. Cambridge: Cambridge UP; Paris: Editions de la Maison des Sciences de l'Homme, 1982. 11-17.
The Black Riders and Other Lines: Published May 11, 1895. Online at the Stephen Crane Society website
  • Stephen Crane
Crane, Stephen. The Black Riders and Other Lines: Published May 11, 1895. Online at the Stephen Crane Society website. http://public.wsu.edu/~campbelld/crane/black.htm 2016 http://public.wsu.edu/~campbelld/crane/black.htm 2016
La perspectiva dominante en El Arte de la Guerra: Más aspectos de un clásico chino (Topsight in The Art of War: Further Aspects of a Chinese Classic)
_____. "La perspectiva dominante en El Arte de la Guerra: Más aspectos de un clásico chino (Topsight in The Art of War: Further Aspects of a Chinese Classic)." Social Science Research Network 9 Nov. 2014. http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2520473
Goffman, Erving. jThe Presentation of Self in Everyday Life
  • Gérard Narrative Genette
  • Discourse
Genette, Gérard. Narrative Discourse. Trans. Jane E. Lewin. Foreword by Jonathan Culler. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1980. Goffman, Erving. jThe Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. Rev. ed. Garden City (NY): Doubleday-Anchor, 1959.
New York: Ballantine, 1972. Crane, Stephen. The Black Riders and Other Lines: Published May 11, 1895. Online at the Stephen Crane Society website
  • Gregory Bateson
Bateson, Gregory. Steps to an Ecology of Mind. New York: Ballantine, 1972. Crane, Stephen. The Black Riders and Other Lines: Published May 11, 1895. Online at the Stephen Crane Society website. http://public.wsu.edu/~campbelld/crane/black.htm 2016 http://public.wsu.edu/~campbelld/crane/black.htm 2016