ChapterPDF Available

8. The role of Theory of Mind, grammatical competence and metapragmatic awareness in irony comprehension

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

The paper investigates the roles of Theory of Mind, receptive language skills, and metapragmatic awareness in irony comprehension. In Experiment 1, 5-8 year-old typically developing Hungarian-speaking children completed a series of false belief tasks, receptive syntax and vocabulary tests and an irony comprehension test, where they were asked to attribute intentions to an actor uttering an ironic utterance as part of a story. In Experiment 2, the children who had shown no evidence of irony comprehension in Experiment 1 were divided into two groups. One group underwent a metapragmatic awareness instruction programme, where the use and purpose of everyday irony were discussed. The other group did not participate in this programme. An irony comprehension test was then administered to both groups of children. We found that while neither syntax and vocabulary scores nor false belief task performance reliably correlated with irony comprehension, metapragmatic abilities made a significant and pronounced contribution.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Márta Szücs and Anna Babarczy
8 The role of Theory of Mind, grammatical
competence and metapragmatic
awareness in irony comprehension
Abstract: The paper investigates the roles of Theory of Mind, receptive language
skills, and metapragmatic awareness in irony comprehension. In Experiment 1,
58 year-old typically developing Hungarian-speaking children completed a
series of false belief tasks, receptive syntax and vocabulary tests and an irony
comprehension test, where they were asked to attribute intentions to an actor
uttering an ironic utterance as part of a story. In Experiment 2, the children
who had shown no evidence of irony comprehension in Experiment 1 were
divided into two groups. One group underwent a metapragmatic awareness
instruction programme, where the use and purpose of everyday irony were
discussed. The other group did not participate in this programme. An irony com-
prehension test was then administered to both groups of children. We found
that while neither syntax and vocabulary scores nor false belief task perfor-
mance reliably correlated with irony comprehension, metapragmatic abilities
made a signicant and pronounced contribution.
1 Introduction
Verbal irony can be informally dened as an act of communication where a
speaker is saying one thing, but means the exact opposite of what she is saying.
In Gricean terms, irony is treated as an implicature triggered by the outing of
the maxim of Quality, that is, Do not say what you believe to be false(Grice
1989: 34). The post-Gricean relevance-theoretic framework reinterprets irony
and argues that it is an instance of interpretive echoic language use, through
which the speaker expresses disagreement with a thought attributed to another
person (Sperber and Wilson 1986/1995; Wilson and Sperber 2004; Wilson 2013).
According to Relevance Theory, to understand an ironic expression, the hearer
has to understand not only the basic proposition expressed by an utterance,
DOI 10.1515/9781501505089-008
Márta Szücs, Department of Hungarian Language and Literature, The University of Szeged
Anna Babarczy, Department of Cognitive Science, Budapest University of Technology and
Economics
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
but also the fact that it is being interpretively used. In other words, for a typical
ironic statement, the listener needs to realise that the speaker is expressing an
attitude towards a thought of someone else, rather than a belief of her own.
In this respect, from a relevance-theoretic perspective, the ability to attribute
intentional states to others, commonly known as Theory of Mind, is believed to
be a fundamental component of pragmatic competence, since it is this ability
that allows the hearer to realise that the speakers communicative intentions
are not explicitly expressed by the encoded semantic meaning of her utterance.
Perner and Wimmer (1985) describe two levels of belief attribution that play a
crucial role in childrens understanding of social interactions and appear at
dierent stages of their development: rst-order beliefs involve the representa-
tion of another persons thoughts about the real world and appear around the
4th year of age in typically developing children, while second-order beliefs
involve the representation of another persons beliefs about someone elses
thoughts and appear a couple of years after children have developed rst-order
Theory of Mind abilities (cf. Miller 2009; Frith and Frith 2010).
The relevance-theoretic echoic interpretation of irony therefore predicts that
second-order Theory of Mind abilities, in Perner and Wimmers sense, are a
prerequisite to irony comprehension. This prediction is supported by empirical
evidence collected by Happé (1993), who found that autistic subjects who passed
rst-order false belief tests correctly interpreted metaphors but failed to under-
stand ironic utterances, while those who passed second-order false belief tests
tended to comprehend irony as well. The performance of a small sample of
typically-developing young children in this study also reected this pattern:
again, only those participants in the control group who passed both rst-order
and second-order false belief tests understood irony. Given the results obtained,
Happés conclusion was that performance in Theory of Mind tasks is a very good
predictor of irony comprehension.
Other studies, however, have failed to support Happés interpretation of her
results. For instance, Sullivan,Winner and Hopeld (1995) and Sullivan, Winner
and Tager-Flusberg (2003) studied typically-developing children and children
with Williams syndrome, and found that second-order mental state attribution
ability precedes ironic joke comprehension by approximately two years suggest-
ing that while second-order false belief attribution may be a necessary condition
of irony comprehension, it is not a sucient one. Other factors also appear to be
at play, one of which may be grammatical ability.
The relationship between pragmatic competence and syntactic or lexical
development has also been hotly debated. Some experimental evidence suggests
that childrens pragmatic development is dissociated from their grammatical
competence, since there appears to be a stage of language development when
130 Márta Szücs and Anna Babarczy
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
they have diculty interpreting non-logical or non-literal meanings adi-
culty that cannot be attributed to lexical or syntactic decits (cf. Papafragou
and Musolino 2003; Bernicot and Laval 2004; Noveck 2004). Yet, other studies
have revealed correlations between receptive language skills and the com-
prehension of non-literal language, especially in relation to speech acts and
metaphors (cf. Leinonen et als 2003; Norbury 2005; De Mulder 2011).
Similarly, the relationship between linguistic ability in general and irony
comprehension is far from straightforward. Filippova and Astington (2008) and
Angeleri and Airenti (2014), for instance, found receptive vocabulary to have
an eect on irony comprehension in 59 and 36 year-old typically-developing
children. In both cases, however, the childrens performance on the vocabulary
task showed a strong positive correlation with their false-belief understanding,
and regression analyses revealed little additional eect of the vocabulary skills.
On the other hand, in Cutica, Bucciarelli and Baras (2006) non-verbal implica-
ture task where a picture representing an actors communicative intentions had
to be selected, patients with left hemisphere brain damage showed poor perfor-
mance if the story involved irony, such as clapping when someone was clumsy,
even though they did not display impaired performance in Theory of Mind tasks.
A meta-analysis by Milligant, Astington and Dack (2007) suggests that there
tends to be a correlation between language ability and false-belief understand-
ing, although the strength of the relationship varies greatly, which might be
a part of the explanation for the contradictory results concerning false belief
task performance and non-literal language comprehension. Even so, the meta-
analysis strongly suggests that the direction of the relationship is from language
ability to false-belief performance rather than vice versa.
Turning to a far less intensively studied explanatory factor, little attention
has been placed, in the developmental literature, on the relationship between
non-literal language comprehension and metapragmatic awareness. Metaprag-
matic awareness, which is dened as the ability to reect on language use in a
conscious way (cf. Verschueren 2000; Wilkinson and Milosky 1987) can be seen
as a kind of interface between the linguistic and the extralinguistic level of
language use (cf. Ca1994), which presupposes not only linguistic but also
contextual and world knowledge (cf. Collins 2013). In one of the few studies in
the area, Bernicot, Laval and Chaminaud (2007) investigated the development of
metapragmatic awareness and non-literal language comprehension in 6, 8 and
10 year-old typically-developing children. In this study, the childrens com-
prehension of non-literal language comprising semantic-inference implicatures,
indirect requests, idioms and sarcasm was measured in a phrase-picture match-
ing task, followed by a short interview where the children were asked to explain
The role of Theory of Mind 131
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
their initial responses. The results obtained showed that dierent types of non-
literal language exhibit dierent developmental patterns. Notably, the compre-
hension of ironic-sarcastic implicatures appeared relatively late, and, in contrast
with the other types of non-literal language studied, was accompanied by meta-
pragmatic knowledge when it was present. That is, there might be a connection
between the development of irony comprehension and metapragmatic aware-
ness, even though the nature of Bernicot, Laval and Chaminauds study does
not allow us to directly establish such a cause-and-eect relationship.
The eects of metapragmatic awareness, albeit not in relation to non-literal
language comprehension, were also studied by Robinson and Robinson (1982),
who used metapragmatic training to improve awareness of instruction clarity in
45 year-old children. The training signicantly improved the childrens ability
to both give clear instructions and ask for clarication when given ambiguous
instructions. This, in turn, suggests that explicit metapragmatic training can
boost specic pragmatic abilities of preschool children.
Against this background, the investigation of the relationship between false
belief attribution, grammatical skills and metapragmatic awareness, on the one
hand, and irony comprehension, on the other, seems like a worthwhile venture.
The present study further explores this relationship, with a view to (a) shedding
additional light on the relative roles of false belief attribution and receptive
grammatical ability in irony comprehension, and (b) nding evidence for a
cause-and-eect relationship between metapragmatic awareness and irony com-
prehension that may be independent of false belief attribution and grammatical
abilities.
2 Experiment 1
A non-literal language comprehension test suitable for Hungarian-speaking pre-
school children was devised. The test contained not only ironic but also meta-
phorical and indirect speech items, but the present analysis focuses only on
irony. Apart from the non-literal language comprehension test, the group of
children participating in the study were also tested on a series of false belief
tasks, a receptive grammar test and a receptive vocabulary test. A subgroup of
these children also participated in a metapragmatic awareness instruction pro-
gramme for the purposes of Experiment 2, which will be described in Section 3.
132 Márta Szücs and Anna Babarczy
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
2.1 Participants
Seventy-one typically-developing monolingual Hungarian preschool children, 32
girls and 39 boys (age range 4;0 to 7;2, mean age 5;7) from two kindergartens in
two university towns in eastern Hungary participated in the experiment. Five
of the children could not be reached for the vocabulary test session and were
excluded from analyses involving vocabulary scores. (see Table 1 for details).
Table 1: Participant details
N (Boys, Girls) Mean Age Age Range
Irony comprehension test,
False belief tasks, TROG
71 (39, 32) 5;8 4;07;2
PPVT 66 (35, 31) 5;7 4;07;2
2.2 Materials and Procedures
2.2.1 The false belief tasks
Four traditional false belief tasks were used to assess the childrens meta-
representational skills: two tasks testing rst-order and two tasks testing second-
order false belief attribution. Each task involved the description of a story or a
situation and ended in a question regarding the intentions or beliefs of one of
the story characters. To pass the test, the child needed to answer this question
correctly.
The rst-order false belief tasks assessed whether a child can attribute a
false belief to a story character or to another person. To give a correct answer,
the child must be able to look beyond (or inhibit) his/her own knowledge of
reality and appreciate the false belief of the other person. In this experiment
the Hungarian translations of two well-known tests were used: the Sally-Anne
test (Baron-Cohen, Leslie & Frith 1985, 1986), which uses the unexpected transfer
paradigm, and the Smarties test (Hogrefe, Wimmer and Perner 1986), which uses
the unexpected content/deceptive box paradigm.
Second-order false belief tasks are more complex, and require participants
to attribute a false belief about another persons belief to a story character. In
order to reduce the eects of test complexity, we used two relatively short and
simple tasks that had been specically designed to reduce processing demands:
the Birthday test (Herold 2005) and the Robot test (Coull, Leekam and Bennett
2006), both of which are based on the unexpected transfer paradigm.
The role of Theory of Mind 133
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
2.2.2 The irony comprehension test
The non-literal language comprehension test we administered was similar to
Happés test (1993), but the general structure was modied, rstly, to make the
context stories less explicit in order to avoid echoing eects with young children,
and secondly, to increase the number of forced choice answers from two to three
in order to reduce the probability of selecting correct answers by chance and
allow for an analysis of error types.
The test consisted of ve short stories, each illustrated by a set of four
pictures to help the children follow and remember the events in the story. Each
story included an ironic statement uttered by one of the characters in the story.
As the test sentences had to be novel non-idiomatic phrases with the individual
words of the sentences familiar to preschool children, the frequencies of the
ironic phrases and the vocabulary they contained were checked against the
Hungarian National Corpus of about 180 million words (http://corpus.nytud.
hu/mnsz; cf. Váradi 2002) and those satisfying our criteria of fewer than 15
occurrences as a phrase but more than 1500 occurrences of the individual words
were selected. Three of the ironic phrases included in the study were unrepre-
sented in the corpus and two occurred with very low frequencies (9 and 13
occurrences, all with literal meaning).
After listening to each story, the children were asked what the characters
meant by their ironic utterances and were given three possible answers to
choose from. The three options were the correct ironic interpretation, a literal
interpretation, and an interpretation of deception. The children were not given
any feedback on their answers. An example is given below:
(1) Story: Katie was helping her mother make cookies. After making the dough
they put it in the oven, and went out to the garden to play.
Unfortunately, the cookies stayed in the oven for too long, and were burnt.
Later Katies father came home, saw the cookies and said:
What soft cookies! (ironic ending)
Question: Why did the father say that?
Answers to choose from:
a. He thought that the cookies are soft (literal)
b. He wanted to trick the mother (deception)
c. He expressed in a funny way that the cookies are hard (ironic)
2.2.3 The Test for Reception of Grammar
The standardised Test for Reception of Grammar test (TROG, Bishop 1983) is an
individually administered, multiple-choice test designed to assess the com-
134 Márta Szücs and Anna Babarczy
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
prehension of grammatical contrasts marked by inection, function words and
word order, among other grammatical phenomena. The Hungarian version of
the test (Lukács, Győri and Rózsa. 2013) consists of 72 items, split up into 18
blocks of 4 items each, in order of increasing diculty. Each block assesses the
childs comprehension of a specic type of grammatical contrast, involving
nouns, verbs, negation, number and person agreement, and relative clauses. In
each item, the subject is shown a set of pictures and asked to point to the one
that matches the phrase or sentence produced by the tester. A block is passed
only if the child responds correctly to all 4 items and the childsnal score is
the number of blocks passed.
2.2.4 The Peabody Picture Vocabulary Test
The Peabody Picture Vocabulary Test (PPVT, Dunn and Dunn 1959) is one of the
most commonly used tests to assess receptive vocabulary. In our study, we used
the Hungarian version of the test (Csányi 1974), which consists of 150 vocabulary
items of gradually increasing diculty. To administer the PPVT, the investigator
presents a series of plates with four black-and-white pictures on each. For each
plate, the investigator utters a word and the child is asked to select the picture
that best represents the words meaning. The test ends when the child has
answered six consecutive items incorrectly. The childs score is the number of
correct answers preceding the failed block.
2.2.5 General Procedure
The children were tested individually in a quiet room on the premises of their
regular kindergartens. Participation was voluntary and participants received
small gifts in way of thanks. The tests were administered in one or two sessions
depending on the needs of the child; if two sessions were needed, these were
separated by at most one week. The tests were administered in the following
order: false-belief tasks, non-literal language comprehension task, the Test for
Reception of Grammar and the Peabody Picture Vocabulary Task.
2.3 Results
2.3.1 The role of false belief attribution ability
The children were classed into three dierent groups based on their performance
in the rst- and second-order false belief tasks.
The role of Theory of Mind 135
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
Table 2: Number and ages of children in each ToM group
ToM group NoToM 1stToM 2ndToM
Number 29 22 20
Age (mean) 5;2 5;11 5;11
Age (range) 4;26;11 4;07;2 4;106;11
The children in the No-ToM group failed either one or both of the rst-order
false-belief tasks. Those who passed both rst-order false belief tests, but failed
one or both of the second-order tests were placed in the 1st-ToM group. Finally,
the children in the 2nd-ToM group passed all four false-belief tasks.
The results of the irony comprehension task for the children grouped by
performance on the false belief tests are shown in Figure 1.
Figure 1: Percentage of correct answers to irony items in each ToM group
As Figure 1 shows, the percentage of correct irony responses was similarly low
in each ToM group (25%, 40% and 37%) and a Kruskal-Wallis test comparing
the three groups showed no statistically signicant dierence between them.
One-Sample Wilcoxon Signed Rank tests revealed that while the No-ToM group
performed signicantly below the 33% chance level (p = .023), the other two
groupsperformance did not dier from chance in either direction.
An analysis of incorrect answers in the irony task might shed some light on
the strategies used by the children. Figure 2 displays the distribution of errors in
the irony task.
136 Márta Szücs and Anna Babarczy
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
Figure 2: Distribution of literal and deception answers in the irony task in each ToM group (as a
percentage of the total number of incorrect answers)
As Figure 2 reveals, the most frequent error for children in all groups was by far
the interpretation of the ironic statement as an act of deception, gathering 83%
of errors in the no-ToM group, 69% in the 1st-ToM group and 74% in the 2nd-ToM
group.
2.3.2 Results: The role of language ability
As mentioned above, the Peabody Picture Vocabulary Test scores could be
obtained for only 66 of the 71 children, as ve of the children could not be
reached for testing within the allocated one-week time frame. Statistical tests
involving Peabody Picture Vocabulary Test scores were therefore only run on
these 66 children, while those related to the Test for Reception of Grammar
included all 71 participants. The childrens mean scores and minimum and
maximum values for the two tests are shown in Table 3.
Table 3: Mean scores, ranges and standard
deviations for the TROG and PPTV
Range Mean StDev
TROG 017 11.48 3.83
PPTV 62130 87.36 19.43
The role of Theory of Mind 137
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
In order to explore the relative roles of Theory of Mind and language ability in
irony comprehension, hierarchical linear regression models were built for the 66
children that had completed all tests. In these models, Theory of Mind perfor-
mance was represented by the number of false belief tests passed (0 to 4), while
the Test for Reception of Grammar and Peabody Picture Vocabulary Test scores
represented language ability. Besides these three variables (ToM, TROG and
PPVT), the age of the children (in months) was also included in the model, as a
variable standing for unknown factors of maturity, such as unmeasured
language ability, working memory, cognitive exibility, and so on. As shown in
Table 4, however, the contribution of the variables was very low and barely
approaching statistical signicance.
Table 4: Regression analysis predicting irony comprehension from
language abilities (TROG, PPVT), ToM and age (p value is signicant
if p <0.05)
Model R
2
Standardised ß t p
1
ToM
TROG
PPVT
Age
0.123
0.179
0.247
0.191
0.252
1.337
1.808
1.345
1.691
0.186
0.076
0.184
0.096
2.4 Discussion
Experiment 1 considered the development of irony comprehension in four to
seven-year-old typically-developing Hungarian-speaking children. The two ques-
tions at the heart of this investigation were: (a) What role do the childrens false
belief attribution abilities play in the comprehension of this pragmatic phenom-
enon, and (b) what is the relationship between the general language abilities of
the children and their comprehension of irony?
As regards the rst question, there was no dierence in irony comprehen-
sion between children at dierent stages of Theory of Mind ability as measured
through the false belief attribution tasks. We should note that the irony scores in
the present study were much lower than the indirect speech and metaphor com-
prehension scores (Babarczy and Szücs, in preparation) or the irony scores in
Happés (1993) test, and, notably, around chance level. These results therefore
have nothing to say about whether second-order false belief attribution ability
is a necessary condition for irony comprehension, but they do seem to suggest
that it is certainly not a sucient condition.
138 Márta Szücs and Anna Babarczy
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
One possible explanation for this result could be that the children had to
understand not only the ironic meaning but also the ironic attitude as a whole
in the task. Preschool children may realise that literal/semantic meaning is not
appropriate in a given context, but they may still not be able to recognise the
speakers ironic attitude behind the utterance. This much is also suggested
by the error pattern: children are more prepared to believe that the speaker is
lying than that they themselves have misunderstood the literal meaning of the
utterance or perhaps the story context of the utterance. Notably, this error
pattern is consistent with the results of previous studies. Sullivan et al. (1995,
2003), for example, reported that children who were unable to recognise the
ironic attitude conveyed by ironic utterances all made the same kind of error,
namely, they considered all the ironic jokes lies.
Experiment 1 also looked at the relationship between general receptive lan-
guage development and irony comprehension. Here, we found that the variance
in irony comprehension could not be explained either by the reception of
grammar or by receptive vocabulary. This could of course be due to the low
irony scores observed throughout our sample. As some of the children reached
very high scores on the language tests (17/18 in TROG and 130/150 in PPVT),
however, it is again quite clear that good receptive grammar and vocabulary
skills do not seem to be sucient for irony comprehension.
3 Experiment 2
Building on the results of Experiment 1, Experiment 2 was designed to investi-
gate the role of metapragmatic awareness in irony comprehension over and
above ToM and grammatical ability.
3.1 Participants
Thirty-nine children, whose irony comprehension scores on the non-literal test
in Experiment 1 were around chance level (with at most 2 out of 5 items
answered correctly), were selected as participants for the metapragmatic aware-
ness (MPA) instruction experiment. These children were randomly allocated into
two groups: 20 children in the metapragmatic awareness instruction group and
19 children in the control group, as follows:
The role of Theory of Mind 139
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
Table 5: Number and age (mean and range) of the children in the MPA group and in the
control group
N
(boys, girls)
Mean score on
irony test (%)
Age
(mean)
Age
(range)
MPA instruction group 20 (12, 8) 18 5;9 4;56;11
Control group 19 (9, 10) 15 5;4 4;27;2
Total 39 (21, 18) 16 5;7 4;27;2
3.2 Materials and procedures
The children in the metapragmatic awareness instruction group participated
in three metapragmatic awareness development sessions, where they were
explicitly taught about ironic statements and intentions. Three new irony stories
similar in content and structure to the irony test administered in Experiment 1
were constructed for the programme. Each story represented a natural dialogue
between a child and an adult and included an ironic utterance. The stories were
illustrated by pictures to aid comprehension and memory. As in Experiment 1,
the childrens task was to select the best interpretation of the ironic utterance
from three options: an ironic interpretation, a literal interpretation, and an inter-
pretation of deception.
Again, the children participated in the sessions individually. All sessions
were led by one of the investigators, who gradually reduced the amount of help
given to the child: during the rst session, the three stories were fully explained
and interpreted together with the children, in the second session no explanation
was given but leading questions were asked to help the children, and in the
third one, each child was asked to provide his/her answer without help, but
feedback was given after each answer. The details of the three sessions were as
follows:
3.2.1 Instruction session 1
(2) Sample story in the metapragmatic awareness instruction programme:
Toby and his father went on holiday to Lake Balaton. Before leaving town
they had to pick up Tobys cousin called Pete, who had been waiting for
them at the gate of his house. His father went to help him put his bag into
the car.When he noticed Petes bag, he said:
140 Márta Szücs and Anna Babarczy
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
Father: What a big bag! (Ironic statement with ironic intonation)
Toby: Daddy, why did you say that? His rucksack is so small.
Father: Yes, I know. I was just joking about his small bag.
(explanation of the ironic statement, MPA knowledge)
During the rst session, the interpretation of the ironic statement was assisted
with leading questions that allowed children to follow and understand each
step of the interpretation of the ironic statement. These questions related to (i)
knowledge of the actual state of aairs; (ii) knowledge of the dierence between
the semantic meaning of the utterance and the speakers knowledge of the
actual state of aairs; (iii) the recognition of the inappropriateness of the decep-
tive interpretation; and (iv) the consideration of the ironic use of language:
i) Q: How big do you think the rucksack is in reality?
A: Small.
ii) Q: How big did Tobys father say the luggage was?
A: Big.
Q: How big is the rucksack according to his father in reality?
A: Small.
iii) Q: Why did his father say that the luggage was big? Did his father want to trick
his son?
A: No, he did not want to trick him.
iv) Q: What did Tobys father want to say when he said that?
A: (repeating the fathers response) He wanted to say in a funny way that he
thought the luggage was small.
Apart from the leading questions, the role of ironic intonation and contextual
clues were also mentioned during this session and the childrens answers to
the leading questions were further discussed. For instance, in Hungarian, there
is a special sentence structure (Ez aztán. . .), similar to the English construction
What a...,which can signal the use of irony, even though it does not necessarily
introduce an ironic statement.
3.2.2 Instruction session 2
The second sessions of the metapragmatic awareness instruction programme
were consistently held 45 days after the rst sessions. The children heard the
same three stories as during their rst session, only this time the investigator
played a more passive role. She activated the relevant metapragmatic knowledge
with the leading questions but the children were expected to answer the ques-
The role of Theory of Mind 141
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
tions on their own and were only given help if they had diculty providing the
correct answers.
3.2.3 Instruction session 3
The third session was again held a few days after the second. During this
session the childrens interpretation of the ironic utterances was tested using
the metapragmatic awareness instruction material consisting of the three stories
but no leading questions were asked. After listening to each story, the children
were only asked to answer the interpretation question, i.e., to choose the correct
answer to the question about the intentions of the speaker of the ironic utterance.
The childrens correct irony answers were counted, while their incorrect answers
were also recorded. The children were then given feedback.
3.2.4 Second irony comprehension test
After the instruction programme was concluded, both the metapragmatic aware-
ness instruction group and the control group were tested again, using the irony
comprehension test used in Experiment 1, which contained ve short stories
ending in an ironic utterance and three options to choose from as an answer to
the question about the interpretation of the ironic utterance (ironic, literal,
deception). Again like in Experiment 1, the number of correct answers was noted
and the childrens incorrect answers were also recorded.
3.3 Results
Table 5 below shows the mean percentages of correct answers in the two dierent
irony tests: the results of the rst test administered in Experiment 1, the scores
achieved by the metapragmatic awareness instruction group at the third session
of their programme, and the results of the test administered after the instruction
programme.
Table 6: Mean percentages of correct answers in irony comprehension before, at the end of,
and after MPA instruction
MPA group
Mean % (StDev)
Control group
Mean % (StDev)
Irony comprehension test 1 (Experiment 1) 18 (17) 15 (16)
Irony comprehension in MPA 3rd session 88 (19)
Irony comprehension test 2 (after MPA development
procedure)
71 (35) 18 (20)
142 Márta Szücs and Anna Babarczy
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
The results of the Metapragmatic Awareness 3rd session test (88%) clearly indi-
cate that the children in this group had no diculty choosing the correct ironic
interpretation in a well-known context. This could, however, be the result of
simple associative learning and does not provide evidence that the children
have indeed developed metapragmatic awareness. The children would show
evidence of metapragmatic knowledge, only if they could transfer what they
had learnt to new situations. This is exactly what happened in the irony com-
prehension test following the metapragmatic awareness instruction sessions.
The results of this test reveal an enormous improvement in irony interpretation
in this group when compared to the control group: the metapragmatic aware-
ness instruction group answered correctly to 71% of the questions on average,
which is an improvement of 53 percentage points relative to the pre-instruction
test, while the corresponding gure for the control group is 18%, an improve-
ment of only 3 percentage points relative to the rst irony test. The dierence
between the two groups seems to be reliable as shown by statistical analysis:
independent samples t-tests showed no dierence between the groups prior
to the training sessions (t(37) = .614, n.s.) and a highly signicant dierence
in favour of the metapragmatic awareness instruction group after the training
sessions (t(37) = 5.832; p < 0.001).
The next question we addressed was whether metapragmatic instruction
had an eect independently of the childrens false belief attribution ability. The
20 children who participated in the instruction programme were divided into
three groups based on the their Theory of Mind performance as in Experiment 1.
A One-Way ANOVA with these three groups revealed no dierence between them
(F(2, 19) = 0.24, n.s.) in terms of their performance in the second irony test.
As shown in Table 7, the means of the three groups are almost identical, which
suggests that metapragmatic training improves performance regardless of Theory
of Mind ability.
Table 7: Mean percentage of correct answers in Irony Test 2 in
the MPA instruction group by ToM ability
N
Mean score on
Irony Test 2 (%) StDev
No-ToM 8 72 30
1st ToM 5 68 46
2nd ToM 7 71 36
Similar comparisons were made in relation to receptive grammar and vocabu-
lary skills. After combining their Peabody Picture Vocabulary Test and Test for
Reception of Grammar scores, we divided the children into two groups: those
The role of Theory of Mind 143
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
scoring below average on the combined receptive language tasks and those
scoring at or above average. As one of the children in the metapragmatic aware-
ness instruction group had not completed the PPVT task, the analysis was run
on the remaining 19 children. Table 8 shows the average scores of the two
groups:
Table 8: Mean percentage of correct answers in Irony Test 2 in the
MPA instruction group by receptive grammar and vocabulary ability
N
Mean score on
Irony Test 2 (%) StDev
Below average TROG-PPVT 10 66 27
Above average TROG-PPVT 9 73 43
Although the children with above-average receptive grammar and vocabulary
skills performed slightly better on the second irony test than the children with
below-average language ability, the dierence was again not statistically signi-
cant (t(17) = .447, n.s.).
3.4 Discussion
Experiment 2 considered the eects of enhancing childrens metapragmatic aware-
ness on irony comprehension performance in four to seven-year-old typically-
developing Hungarian-speaking children. The goal of the study was to gain
insight into the role of metapragmatic awareness training in the development
of childrens irony comprehension.
The ndings demonstrated that metapragmatic awareness can indeed play
an important role in the development of irony comprehension in preschool
children and that its benets do not depend on either false belief attribution or
linguistic ability at least to the extent that these abilities are captured through
performance in the tasks undertaken by our participants. All in all, our results
clearly show that, if given explicit instruction, preschool children have the
ability to integrate their knowledge of linguistic (linguistic and speaker meaning
of ironic utterances) with metalinguistic rules (contextual and intonation clues)
and use this knowledge to recognise irony.
4 Conclusion
Summing up, the ndings of Experiment 1 reported here have shown a loose
relationship between Theory of Mind ability and irony comprehension in
typically developing children, since a developed second-order Theory of Mind
144 Márta Szücs and Anna Babarczy
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
ability did not appear to be sucient to ensure better irony comprehension.
Grammar reception and receptive vocabulary were also found to be relatively
unrelated to irony comprehension in our group. Yet, metapragmatic training
involving drawing childrens attention to the fact that a literally false statement
may be uttered with an intention other than deception, made a dramatic dier-
ence to our groups irony comprehension performance regardless of their ToM or
general language ability. Our Experiment 2 showed the relationship between
metapragmatic awareness and irony comprehension to be clearly causal.
It could thus be the case that the puzzlingly slow development of irony
comprehension relative to lexical and syntactic development is simply a matter
of insucient experience with ironic language use. Given our results, it is
further possible that the direction of the relationship between false belief under-
standing and irony comprehension is not quite as simple as we had assumed;
while having a Theory of Mind may aid irony comprehension, another explana-
tion for the previously observed co-appearance of the two is that metapragmatic
knowledge of the kind needed for irony comprehension, for instance, also aids
the development of a Theory of Mind.
We therefore suggest that ironic interpretation is a social-pragmatic phenom-
enon and under non-laboratory circumstances children learn to comprehend
ironic statements from natural discourses, in which they meet them in a context
where the ironic interpretation is either explained or is the only cognitively plau-
sible interpretation.
References
Angeleri, Romina & Gabriella Airenti. 2014. The development of joke and irony understanding:
A study with 3- to 6-year-old children. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology/Revue
canadienne de psychologie expérimentale 68. 133146.
Babarczy, Anna and Márta Szücs. In preparation. The comprehension of hint and metaphor in
preschool children: The contribution of metarepresentational abilities and language skills.
Baron-Cohen, Simon, Alan M. Leslie & Uta Frith. 1985. Does the autistic child have a theory of
mind?Cognition 21. 3746.
Baron-Cohen, Simon, Alan M. Leslie & Uta Frith. 1986. Mechanical, behavioral and intentional
understanding of picture stories in autistic children. British Journal of Developmental
Psychology 4. 113125.
Bernicot, Josie and Virginie Laval. 2004. Speech acts in children: The example of promises. In
Ira A. Noveck & Dan Sperber (eds.), Experimental pragmatics, 207228. London: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Bernicot, Josie, Virginie Laval & Stephanie Chaminaud. 2007. Nonliteral language forms in
children: In what order are they acquired in pragmatics and metapragmatics? Journal of
Pragmatics 39. 21152132.
The role of Theory of Mind 145
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
Bishop, Dorothy. 1983. Test for the Reception of Grammar (TROG). Age and Cognitive Performance
Research Centre: University of Manchester.
Ca, Claudia. 1994. Metapragmatics. In Ronald E. Asher & James M.Y. Simpson (eds.), Encyclo-
pedia of Language and Linguistics, 24612466. Oxford: Pergamon Press.
Collins, Anna. 2013. Metapragmatic awareness in children with typical language development,
pragmatic language impairment and specic language impairment. Manchester: Univer-
sity of Manchester PhD thesis.
Coull, Greig J., Susan R. Leekam & Mark Bennett. 2006. Simplifying second-order belief attribu-
tion: What facilitates childrens performance on measures of conceptual understanding?
Social Development 15. 548563.
Csányi, F. Ivonne. 1974. Peabody Szókincs-Teszt [Peabody Vocabulary Test]. Budapest: Bárczi
Gusztáv Gyógypedagógiai Fõiskola.
Cutica, Ilaria, Monica Bucciarelli & Bruno G. Bara. 2006. Neuropragmatics: Extralinguistic
pragmatic ability is better preserved in left-hemisphere-damaged patients than in right-
hemisphere-damaged patients. Brain and Language 98. 1225.
De Mulder, Hanna L.N.M. 2011. Putting the pieces together: The development of theory of mind
and (mental) language. Utrecht: Utrecht University PhD dissertation.
Dunn, Lloyd M. & Leota M. Dunn. 1959. Peabody picture vocabulary test. Circle Pines, MN:
American Guidance Service.
Filippova, Eva & Janet W. Astington. 2008. Further development in social reasoning revealed in
discourse irony understanding. Child Development 79. 126138.
Frith, Uta & Chris Frith. 2010. The social brain: Allowing humans to boldly go where no other
species has been. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences
365.1537. 165176.
Grice, H. Paul. 1989. Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Happé, Francesca G.E. 1993. Communicative competence and theory of mind in autism: A test
of relevance theory. Cognition 48. 101119.
Herold, Róbert. 2005. Mentalizációs decit szkizofréniában [Mentalising decit in schizophre-
nia] Pécs: University of Pécs PhD dissertation.
Hogrefe, Juergen G., Heinz Wimmer & Josef Perner. 1986. Ignorance versus false belief: A
developmental lag in attribution of epistemic states. Child Development 57. 567582.
Leinonen, Eeva, Nuala Ryder, Margaret Ellis & Claire Hammon. 2003. Use of context in pragmatic
comprehension by specically language-impaired and control children. Linguistics 41.
407423.
Lukács Á., Győri M. and Rózsa S. 2013. TROG-H: új sztenderdizált módszer a nyelvtani megértés
fejlődésének vizsgálatára [TROG-H: A new standardised method of testing the develop-
ment of receptive grammar]. Gyógypedagógiai Szemle 2013/1.
Miller, Scott A. 2009. Childrens understanding of second-order mental states. Psychological
Bulletin 135. 74973.
Milligant, Karen, Janet Wilde Astington & Lisa Ain Dack. 2007. Language and theory of mind:
Metaanalysis of the relation between language ability and false-belief understanding.
Child Development 78. 622646.
Norbury, Courtenay Fraser. 2005. The relationship between theory of mind and metaphor: Evi-
dence from children with language impairment and autistic spectrum disorder. British
Journal of Developmental Psychology 23. 383399.
Noveck, Ira A. 2004. Pragmatic inferences related to logical terms. In Ira Noveck & Dan
Sperber (eds.), Experimental pragmatics, 301322. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
146 Márta Szücs and Anna Babarczy
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
Papafragou, Anna & Julien Musolino. 2003. Scalar implicatures: Experiments at the semantics-
pragmatics interface. Cognition 86. 253282.
Perner, Josef & Heinz Wimmer. 1985. John thinks that Mary thinks that. ..Attribution of
second-order beliefs by 510 years old children. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology
39. 437471.
Robinson, Elizabeth J. & Peter W. Robinson. 1981. Ways of reacting to communication failure in
relation to the development of the childs understanding about verbal communication.
European Journal of Social Psychology 11. 189208.
Robinson, Elizabeth J. & Peter W. Robinson. 1982. The advancement of childrens verbal refer-
ential communication skills: The role of metacognitive guidance. International Journal of
Behavioural Development 5. 329355.
Sperber, Dan & Deirdre Wilson. 1995. Relevance: Communication and cognition. 2nd edn.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Sullivan, Kate, Ellen Winner & Natalie Hopeld. 1995. How children tell a lie from a joke: The role
of second-order mental state attributions. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 13.
191204.
Sullivan, Kate, Ellen Winner & Helen Tager-Flusberg. 2003. Can adolescents with Williams Syn-
drome tell the dierence between lies and jokes? Developmental Neuropsychology 23.
85103.
Váradi, Tamás. 2002. The Hungarian National Corpus. In Proceedings of the 3rd LREC Con-
ference, 385389. Las Palmas: University of Las Palmas de Gran Canaria. http://www.
lrec-conf.org/proceedings/lrec2002/pdf/217.pdf (accessed 20 May 2016)
Verschueren, Jef. 2000. Notes on the role of metapragmatic awareness in language use. Prag-
matics 10. 439456.
Wilkinson, Louise Cherry & Linda M. Milosky. 1987. School-aged childrens metapragmatic
knowledge of requests and responses in the classroom. Topics in language disorders 7.
6170.
Wilson, Deirdre. 2013. Irony comprehension: A developmental perspective. Journal of Prag-
matics 59. 4056.
Wilson, Deirdre & Dan Sperber. 2004. Relevance theory. In Laurence R. Horn & Gregory Ward
(eds.), The handbook of pragmatics, 607632. Oxford: Blackwell.
The role of Theory of Mind 147
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS
Authenticated
Download Date | 3/7/17 9:02 PM
... The majority have involved participants with a diagnosis of autism spectrum disorder (Persicke et al., 2013;Saban-Bezalel & Mashal, 2015) or second language speakers (Bouton, 1999;Kim & Lantolf 2018). Most relevant for the current study, two studies explored the effect of irony training with typically developing children (Lee et al., 2021;Szücs & Babarczy, 2017). ...
... First, Szücs and Babarczy (2017) investigated how three one-on-one training sessions teaching metapragmatic knowledge affected 4-to 7-year-old children's irony comprehension (n = 20) as compared to passive controls (n = 19). In the task, children listened to ageappropriate stories containing an ironic statement, for example, father saying "What soft cookies!" after seeing burned cookies in the kitchen. ...
... The results showed that, as hypothesized, teaching irony in the classroom effectively improved children's irony comprehension. This is consistent with the previous training studies (Lee et al., 2021;Szücs & Babarczy, 2017), but extends the training effect to a group learning context. The results suggest that irony-specific metapragmatic knowledge is crucial for the development of irony comprehension. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Irony comprehension requires going beyond literal meaning of words, and is challenging for children. In this pre-registered study we investigated how teaching metapragmatic knowledge in classrooms impacts 10-year-olds’ written irony comprehension (n = 41, 21 girls) compared to a control group (n = 34, 13 girls). At pre-test, participants read ironic and literal sentences embedded in stories while their eye movements were recorded. Next, the training group was taught about irony, and the control group was taught about reading comprehension. At post-test, the reading task and eye tracking were repeated. Irony comprehension improved after training, suggesting that metapragmatic knowledge serves an important role in irony development. However, the eye movement data suggested that training did not change the strategy children used to resolve the ironic meaning. The results highlight the potential of metapragmatic training and have implications for theories of irony comprehension.
... They identified five studies that have remedied irony comprehension in various study fields, including children, second-language learners, and people with autism. These studies (Bouton, 1999;Kim & Lantolf, 2018;Persicke et al., 2013;Saban-Bezalel & Mashal, 2015;Szücs & Babarczy, 2017) demonstrated that explicit metapragmatic training led to a significant improvement in irony comprehension. This training consisted of defining irony and its contextual cues and then putting them into practice in the context of written stories, comic strips, or videos. ...
... Irony comprehension is linked to metapragmatic abilities (Szücs & Babarczy, 2017), also known as the ability to explicitly reflect on pragmatic rules (Collins et al., 2014). According to Gombert (1992: 186), there are four phases of metalinguistic development. ...
Article
This study investigated links between the development of children's understanding of ironic comments and their metapragmatic knowledge. Forty-six 8-year-olds completed the short version of the Irony Comprehension Task, during which they were presented with ironic comments in three stories and asked to provide reasons for why the speaker in a story uttered an ironic comment. We coded their responses and compared the results to similar data collected previously with 5-year-olds. Results showed that compared to younger children, 8-year-olds frequently refer to interlocutors' emotions, intentions, and to metapragmatics. These results support the view that comprehension of verbal irony is an emerging skill in children.
... Thus, the current literature is quite heterogeneous: some studies reported a significant effect of ToM on metaphor understanding, also when controlling for linguistic skills (Del Sette et al., 2020;Edwards, Figueras, Mellanby, & Langdon, 2011;Whyte & Nelson, 2015). Other studies failed to observe a link between ToM and figurative meaning comprehension over and above the contribution of the language processing system (Szücs & Babarczy, 2017;Whyte, Nelson, & Scherf, 2014). These divergent findings have fueled a debate about the role of ToM in pragmatic development, which is still ongoing (Bosco, Tirassa, & Gabbatore, 2018;Katsos & Andrés-Roqueta, 2021;Kissine, 2021;Matthews, Biney, & Abbot-Smith, 2018). ...
Article
Theoretical pragmatics in the post-Gricean tradition argued that metaphor requires understanding of how another person sees the world. Yet, it is unclear what role mindreading plays in developing metaphor skills. Here we examined the relationship between metaphor and Theory of Mind (ToM) in middle childhood by using two different tasks. In addition to the Physical and Mental Metaphors task (PMM), based on the verbal explanation of physical and mental metaphors, we revived the Referential Metaphors task for children (Noveck, Bianco, & Castry, 2001), where metaphorical and literal referents are presented in a narrative context. The sample included 169 8-, 9-, and 10-year-old children, assessed also for ToM (via the Strange Stories) and other linguistic and cognitive skills as control variables. In the PMM, ToM supported the understanding of mental (but not physical) metaphors in 9-year-olds only, whereas in the Referential Metaphors task ToM supported accuracy of understanding metaphors (but not literal items) in younger children as well. At age 10, ToM effects were negligible in both tasks. These findings suggest that ToM has a task-specific role in metaphor, linked to the characteristics of the items in the task at stake, being for instance greater for metaphors with mental (compared to physical) content and for non-literal (compared to literal) referents. The findings also suggest that the relationship between ToM and metaphor skills is developmental sensitive, as children start to capitalize on ToM earlier in development when the metaphor context is richer, and these effects fade with age. Theoretically, these data argue in favor of the relevance-theoretic account of metaphor, spelling out different ways in which ToM might support metaphor resolution across tasks, for instance by providing better access to the psychological lexicon (i.e., terms referring to mental states) and better context processing, serving as a springboard to achieve sophisticated pragmatic skills in middle childhood.
... Estos tipos de reflexiones son parte de la habilidad metalingüística del individuo, es decir, de la capacidad para reflexionar de manera consciente sobre el uso del lenguaje incluyendo tanto los aspectos lingüísticos como los extralingüísticos que involucra dicho uso (al respecto véase Baroni, & Axia, 1989;Berko & Bernstein, 2010;Collins, 2013;Crespo--Allende, 2009;Crespo--Allende & Alfaro--Faccio, 2010;Dos Santos, 2016;Gombert, 1987Gombert, , 1992Verschueren, 2000). Relacionado con esto, otras investigaciones han señalado que en la adecuada interpretación de la función comunicativa de la ironía verbal interviene la capacidad para atribuir, a uno mismo y a los demás, estados mentales, tales como pensamientos, conocimientos, emociones, creencias e intenciones, con el fin de predecir y explicar el comportamiento propio y ajeno (Banasik--Jemielniak et al., 2020;Bosco et al., 2013;Bosco & Gabbatore, 2017;Dews et al., 1995;Filippova, 2014a;Filippova & Astington, 2008Mewhort--Buist & Nilsen, 2013;Szücs & Babarczy, 2017;Winner & Leekam, 1991;Yus, 2016;Zajaczkowska et al., 2020). Con base en lo anterior, el presente estudio tuvo como objetivo analizar la manera en que adolescentes de 12 y 15 años reflexionan sobre las funciones de la ironía verbal en dos tipos de enunciados irónicos: agradecimiento y ofrecimiento. ...
Article
Full-text available
Para establecer las razones por las que un hablante elige un enunciado irónico por encima de uno literal es necesario evaluar la mente del hablante y su intención al emplear la ironía verbal en un contexto comunicativo específico. Con base en lo anterior, el objetivo de este estudio es analizar la manera en que adolescentes de 12 y 15 años reflexionan sobre las funciones de la ironía verbal en dos tipos de enunciados irónicos: agradecimiento y ofrecimiento. Treinta y dos adolescentes se enfrentaron a diferentes situaciones comunicativas que finalizaban con un enunciado irónico, y mediante un guion de preguntas se indagó sobre las funciones que los participantes atribuían a cada enunciado irónico y sobre el tipo de conocimientos en los que basaban sus reflexiones. Los resultados muestran diferencias debidas a la edad en la cantidad y calidad de las reflexiones presentadas por los participantes.
... Específicamente se ha señalado que para comprender y producir un enunciado irónico es necesario contar con capacidades pragmáticas evolucionadas, puesto que el significado de una expresión irónica requiere del reconocimiento del significado intencional de las palabras, significado que solo es reconocible a través del significado pragmático (dependiente del contexto) (Ruiz Gurillo y Alvarado Ortega 2013; Schnell y Varga 2012). De manera adicional, se ha evidenciado que para interpretar adecuadamente la ironía verbal resulta esencial ser capaz de tomar en cuenta el estado mental del ironista, es decir, sus conocimientos, pensamientos, creencias, deseos, entre otros, con la finalidad de poder determinar qué es lo que realmente quiso expresar con sus palabras (Bosco et al. 2013;Filippova y Astington 2008Hess Zimmermann et al. 2021;Pexman 2008;Szücs y Babarczy 2017;Winner 1988;Winner y Leekam 1991). A su vez, el oyente debe poder considerar que entre los interlocutores existen elementos compartidos, tales como el conocimiento lingüístico, de contexto o situacional e incluso personal de cada participante, además de poder hacer una relación y juicio de la actitud del otro con base en el contexto social donde ocurre la expresión irónica (Kalbermatten 2010;Yus 2009). ...
Article
Full-text available
Verbal irony is the type of non-literal language of latest acquisition, as it requires a profound knowledge of social relationships between those who ironize, such as those imposed by gender. Therefore, the purpose of this study was to analyze children and adolescents’ metalinguistic reflections on verbal irony in situations where the gender of the speakers was a variable. The participants were 18 children aged 9 and 19 adolescents aged 15, who were presented with four ironic stories in which the speakers were of different genders; they were questioned on the meaning of the ironic sentence and whether the gender of the speaker was important. The results show significant differences by age but not by gender of participants. Also, they show that the interpretation of irony is favored or obstructed by the gender of the ironist or the victim. The conclusion is that social and cultural environment is an essential factor for the development of verbal irony in individuals.
Chapter
Research on the development of irony comprehension shows a rather inconsistent acquisition pattern, with some studies pointing to its relatively late emergence and others suggesting its presence from an early age. The heterogeneity of methodological approaches used across studies is an issue that has been greatly overlooked in the literature. However, such heterogeneity may contribute to explaining this developmental puzzle. The main purpose of this chapter is to provide an exhaustive overview of relevant methodological approaches used to study irony comprehension and discuss their cognitive demands on young participants. The chapter includes an outline of the most frequently employed task formats to study the understanding of other figurative or non-literal uses of language as well as the ensuing discussion on whether and how they could be implemented to irony. It addresses other relevant methodological aspects, such as the effects of contextual circumstances and utterance types, and assesses their importance in the design of less cognitively challenging tasks. The chapter makes a plea for the harmonization of testing measures and experimental materials, as well as for a deeper reflection on the challenges related to testing a full-fledged understanding of irony.
Article
Full-text available
Children’s ability to understand irony is believed to be acquired late compared to other pragmatic skills. To explore this assertion, this article presents a review of four decades of research, to determine the age at which children actually do become capable of understanding ironic utterances, and what the crucial influencing factors are. As this systematic examination of the state of research shows, children do indeed seem to gain an understanding of irony later than other forms of non-literal language. In seeking an explanation for this finding, this article discusses the methodological orientation of previous research. It might be that the predominant use of offline methods, especially metalinguistic judgment tasks, paints a somewhat distorted picture of children’s irony comprehension. The article therefore argues for the use of eye-tracking, and a re-examination of the thesis of late acquisition of irony comprehension in children in the near future.
Article
Full-text available
Dentro de las habilidades lingüísticas que se desarrollan durante los años escolares destaca la interpretación de la ironía verbal. Estudios previos han señalado que la adecuada interpretación de la ironía conlleva habilidades de teoría de la mente (ToM) y que cuando los niños y adolescentes reflexionan sobre los enunciados irónicos tienden a proporcionar razonamientos morales. Por lo anterior este estudio se propuso describir el nivel de ToM y el nivel de desarrollo moral en función de la edad, así como determinar si ambas variables son factores que se relacionan con el nivel de interpretación de la ironía verbal durante los años escolares. Formaron parte del estudio 37 niños y adolescentes nativohablantes de español de 9 y 15 años que se enfrentaron a tres instrumentos: nivel de interpretación de la ironía, nivel de ToM y nivel de desarrollo moral. Los resultados muestran diferencias significativas debidas a la edad en las tres medidas. A su vez señalan correlaciones entre ironía, ToM y desarrollo moral para toda la muestra. Por último, ToM resultó ser variable predictora de ironía y desarrollo moral, pero desarrollo moral no fue variable predictora de ironía.
Thesis
Full-text available
This dissertation is about the nature of the relationship between language and Theory of Mind (ToM, the ability to understand other people’s mental states). Does the development of language influence the child’s ToM development or is the child’s understanding of other people’s mental states crucial in the development of language? Each of the chapters in this dissertation attempts to address this question by focussing on children’s ToM development in relation not only to their linguistic capacities in a general sense (e.g. general vocabulary and understanding of syntax), but also to their understanding of language that relates to mental states more directly: “mental” language (e.g. understanding of mental state verbs and indirect requests). This dissertation investigates this relationship in three- to six-year-old children, in typically and atypically developing populations, in correlational and longitudinal studies using not only traditional or standardised assessment materials, but novel methods of testing as well. The main finding of this thesis is that there is a complex developmental relationship between language and ToM, with bi-directional relations between some domains of language and ToM, but unidirectional relationships from other domains of language to ToM. More specifically, this dissertation demonstrates that although ToM and both general and mental vocabulary are bi-directionally related (ToM influences vocabulary development and vocabulary influences ToM development), the child needs a certain level of general language ability at the sentential level to develop ToM. However, a post-hoc finding suggests that understanding of locative prepositions may be an important prerequisite for ToM development as well.
Chapter
Full-text available
Paul Grice was concerned with the way logical terms such as some, or and and take on extralogical meanings in conversational contexts. To take one example, Grice (1989) described or as having a weak word meaning identical to formal logic’s inclusive disjunction (which is false only in the case where both disjuncts are) but as conveying in conversation a speaker’s stronger meaning corresponding to the exclusive disjunction (which is false in the case where both disjuncts are false and where both are true). Grice used the term implicature to describe the pragmatic inference linking word meanings to speaker’s meanings and laid the foundations for nearly all of the linguistic-pragmatic studies found in this volume.1
Article
Full-text available
This paper considers what light experimental work on the development of irony comprehension can shed on the relation between echoic and pretence accounts of irony, and how theoretical debates about the nature of irony might suggest fruitful directions for future developmental research. After surveying the results of developmental studies of three distinctive features of verbal irony – the expression of a characteristic attitude, the normative bias in the uses of irony and the ‘ironical tone of voice’ – it considers how echoic and pretence accounts of irony might explain these results. On the theoretical side, it argues that echoing and pretence are distinct mechanisms which can be used independently of each other, and that verbal irony necessarily involves echoic use, but does not necessarily involve pretence. On the experimental side, it argues that a range of disparate phenomena including hyperbole, jocularity, understatement and rhetorical questions, which are generally treated as forms of irony in the developmental literature, display none of the distinctive features of irony in most of their uses, and are not inherently ironical. However, these phenomena are worth investigating in their own right, and new theoretical accounts and experimental paradigms are needed to prise them apart.
Article
Full-text available
Previous research suggests that comprehending ironic utterances is a relatively late-developing skill, emerging around 5-6 years of age. This study investigated whether younger children might show an earlier understanding when ironic utterances are performed in familiar communicative situations, and investigated the relationships among irony comprehension, language, and theory of mind (ToM) abilities. A group of 100 children aged 3.0-6.5 years was presented with 4 types of puppet scenarios depicting different communicative interactions: control, joke, contingent irony and background irony stories. Results suggested that (a) even younger children easily understand jokes, and may sometimes understand ironies; (b) children's comprehension of irony continues to develop across early childhood; and (c) receptive vocabulary scores had simultaneous effects on irony comprehension and ToM performance. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2013 APA, all rights reserved).
Chapter
Promises are central to human exchanges, especially in adult-child interactions. They consist of a commitment on the part of the speaker to perform a future act, as in ‘je promets de ranger ma chambre’ (‘I promise to clean my room’). For the past ten years, we have been investigating promise comprehension among children from the point of view that language is a communication system and that language competence is the acquisition and use of that system. The emphasis is therefore placed on the functional aspects of language (Bates, 1976; Bruner, 1983; Ervin-Tripp and Mitchell-Kernan, 1977; Halliday, 1985 ; Ninio and Snow, 1996; Tomasello, 2000). It has been shown in this perspective that interaction formats or routines (prototypical exemplars of social relations) are very important for young children (Bernicot, 1994; Marcos and Bernicot, 1994, 1997).
Article
There are at least three senses in which it is possible to speak of metapragmatics. The first sense is that of metatheoretical reflection on the basic assumptions, the relevance criteria, and the epistemological commitments of pragmatics. The second sense refers to the conditions that make speakers' use of language possible and effective. The task of metapragmatics in this sense is, above all, to make those conditions explicit. This kind of metapragmatics, which can be related to the problem of the universals of human communication, is transcendental in a Kantian sense, inasmuch it deals with the constitutive elements of human knowledge. The third sense is concerned with the investigation of that area of the speakers' competence that reflects judgments of appropriateness on one's own and other people's communicative behavior. In this sense, metapragmatics deals with the 'know-how' regarding the control and planning of, as well as feedback on, the ongoing interaction. Two are features of this kind of metapragmatics, namely, reflexivity and common knowledge.
Article
High-ability autistic children were compared with low-ability Down's syndrome children and clinically normal preschool children on a picture sequencing task. When the sequences could be understood in terms of causal-mechanical or simply descriptive-behavioural criteria, the autistic children were at least as good as the controls and often showed superior performance. However, on sequences that evoked understanding in terms of psychological-Intentional criteria, the autistic children performed much worse than the others. This pattern was also seen in the language used by the children in narrating the stories afterwards. In contrast to the controls, the autistic children used causal and behavioural language, but hardly ever mental state language. This experiment confirms and extends a previous study of ours which also tested the hypothesis of a specific cognitive deficit which apparently prevents the development of a ‘theory of mind’ in the autistic child.
Article
36 children aged between 4-4 and 5-4 were assessed for both their understanding about the role of message ambiguity as a cause of communication failure, and their level of performance in verbal referential communication tasks. All children then took part in six half-hour sessions during which they practised listening and speaking in small groups, with the experimenter modelling appropriate behaviour on her turns. In addition, half the children received information about when and why listeners understood or failed to understand (metacognitive guidance) during the course of the sessions. Both groups improved in both performance and understanding in the immediate post-test and in a delayed post-test seven weeks later there was no sign of regression in understanding. The guidance group advanced more than the practice group in both performance and understanding (with the exception of those at the highest levels of understanding originally). Performance and understanding measures were significantly related to each other in the pre-test, and the relationship remained unchanged following intervention, with the exception of question-asking, which increased even among children who made no advances in understanding. The results were interpreted as suggesting that we can advance children's verbal communication skills not only by giving them information about communication, but also by treating them as though they understand that messages can be ambiguous and can cause communication failure.