ArticlePDF Available

That’-clauses as Existential Quantifiers

Authors:

Abstract

Following Panaccio, 'John believes that p' is analysed as 'For some x such that x is true if and only if p, John believes x'. On this view the complement clause 'that p' acts as a restricted existential quantifier ('For some x such that x is true if and only if p') and it contributes a higher-order property.
HAL Id: ijn_00000493
https://jeannicod.ccsd.cnrs.fr/ijn_00000493
Submitted on 25 Apr 2004
HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access
archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci-
entic research documents, whether they are pub-
lished or not. The documents may come from
teaching and research institutions in France or
abroad, or from public or private research centers.
L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est
destinée au dépôt et à la diusion de documents
scientiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non,
émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de
recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires
publics ou privés.
’That’-clauses as existential quantiers
François Recanati
To cite this version:
François Recanati. ’That’-clauses as existential quantiers. Analysis, Oldenbourg Verlag, 2004, 64
(3), pp.229-235. �ijn_00000493�
7
restriction of the domain of quantification. On this view the overall content of
the belief sentence ‘John believes that Peter is an eye-doctor’ is nothing
other than
[
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff EYE-DOCTOR (Peter)] BELIEVES (John,
p
)
but the variable
‘p’
only ranges over beliefs possessing the contextually
relevant property
F
.3
Institut Jean-Nicod (CNRS/EHESS/ENS)
1
bis
avenue de Lowendal, 75007 Paris, France
recanati@ehess.fr
References
Egré, P. forthcoming. A pragmatic approach to the problem of logical
omniscience.
Panaccio, C. 1996. Belief sentences: outline of a nominalistic approach. In
Québec Studies in the Philosophy of Science II
, eds. M. Marion and R. S.
Cohen, 265-77. Dordrecht : Kluwer.
Recanati, F. 2000.
Oratio Obliqua, Oratio Recta: An Essay on
Metarepresentation
. Cambridge, Mass. : MIT Press/Bradford Books.
3 Many thanks to Paul Egré, Neftali Villanueva Fernandez and Philippe
Schlenker for comments on an earlier version of this paper, and to Claude
Panaccio for inspiring the main idea.
6
is possible, and it might be said that this reading is
‘de re’
with respect to the
property expressed by ‘eye-doctor’:
[ιX : X = EYE-DOCTOR] [
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff X (Peter)] BELIEVES (John,
p
)
But the problem is that the
other
reading — the
de dicto
reading — has been
represented in such a way that it, too, allows substitution. It follows that
nothing, in our framework, captures the feature of belief sentences in virtue
of which substitution fails even for synonymous expressions.
I think that feature can (and should) be handled pragmatically. On a
pragmatic analysis, what the sentence compositionally articulates is only the
truth-conditional content of the ascribed belief. At that level, substitutivity
does
not
fail. But the context and the way the speaker phrases the report
impart extra information regarding the ascribee’s belief, and in particular the
ways she presumably thinks of the various objects and properties which her
belief concerns. Substitutivity fails, when it fails, because the expressions
that are used in giving the truth-conditions of the ascribed belief are
themselves contextual clues which may affect the further suggestions that
are conveyed, but not literally expressed, regarding that belief.
There are two types of pragmatic accounts of opacity in the literature.
One type of account says that the information that is ‘pragmatically
imparted’ rather than compositionally articulated does
not
affect the truth-
conditions of the report. The truth-conditions which such views ascribe to
belief reports are very different from the intuitive truth-conditions which they
seem to have, and this, I take it, is a serious defect of those approaches. The
other type of account says that the pragmatic suggestions in question find
their ways into the truth-conditions of the report. For example, we may argue
that the compositionally articulated content of ‘John believes that grass is
green’ is
freely enriched
through the contextual provision of additional
ingredients (‘unarticulated constituents’) in the restriction of the quantifier
— ingredients which I represent by means of the extra conjunct ‘
F
(
p
)’, in
which
‘F’
is a free variable:
[
p
: (TRUE (
p
) iff EYE-DOCTOR (Peter)) &
F
(
p
)] BELIEVES (John,
p
)
Intuitively, the property
‘F’
that is implicitly ascribed to John’s belief is the
property that its propositional constituents are thought of under such and
such modes of presentation.
If, for general methodological reasons, one does not like ‘free
enrichment’ or ‘unarticulated constituents’, an alternative analysis is available
which is less controversial but amounts to exactly the same thing. The
alternative analysis appeals to the universally accepted idea of a contextual
5
which would be my rendering of (the
de dicto
interpretation of) ‘John
believes that grass is green’ if ‘iff’ was construed as material equivalence,
‘GREEN (grass)’ can be replaced by any materially equivalent formula (e.g.
‘WHITE (snow)’) without affecting the truth-value of the whole. That is not
acceptable, for we cannot substitute ‘snow is white’ for ‘grass is green’ in
‘John believes that grass is green’.
The belief operator ‘John believes that’ posited by the Hintikka-Prior
analysis is intensional; it operates on the content of the complement
sentence, not on its extension. It follows that only a sentence expressing the
same proposition as the sentence ‘grass is green’ can substitute for it in
‘John believes that grass is green’. In the standard framework, the same
result is achieved by extensional means: the ‘that’-clause ‘that grass is green’
is taken to designate the content of the complement sentence ‘grass is
green’, hence only a sentence with the same content as ‘grass is green’ can
be substituted for it without modifying the reference of the ‘that’-clause. To
achieve that effect in our framework, we have to make the connective ‘iff’
suitably intensional, i.e., sensitive to the content of the sentence on the
right-hand-side, and not merely to its extension (its truth-value). Indeed,
when we say that what the speaker believes is true if and only if grass is
green, we describe a state of affairs, consisting of a certain object (grass)
having a certain colour (green), and we say that the belief is true in all and
only those situations in which
that state of affairs
obtains. The situations in
question may be partial, so even strict equivalence (equivalence in all possible
worlds) will not do. Which of the many proposals available in the logico-
philosophical literature best captures the intuitive content of ‘if and only if’ is
an issue which I will not address in this paper. I use the symbol ‘iff’ as a place-
holder, to record the need for a suitably intensional connective.
IV.
One might object that, even if we had such a connective, we still couldn’t
account for substitutivity failures in belief sentences. The sentence ‘John
believes that Peter is an eye-doctor’ will be rendered as:
[
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff EYE-DOCTOR (Peter)] BELIEVES (John,
p
)
Since ‘EYE-DOCTOR’ has the same content (expresses the same property) as
‘OPHTALMOLOGIST’, substitution is possible. Yet in the natural language
sentence ‘John believes that Peter is an eye-doctor’, substitution is blocked:
John may fail to realize that Peter is an ophtalmologist even if he believes
him to be an eye-doctor.
It will not do to appeal to the
de re/de dicto
distinction here. To be
sure, there is a reading of the natural language sentence in which substitution
4
[
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff GREEN (grass)] BELIEVES (John,
p
)
In this framework, semantic innocence is preserved as much as it is in
Davidson’s paratactic analysis: the sentence ‘grass is green’ makes its
standard contribution and is not recruited as a fragment of a complex name.
The standard view is rejected because (2) is rejected. But no discrepancy is
introduced between grammatical form and logical form. As for the above-
mentioned inferences, they can be accounted for quite easily:
John believes that grass is green,
Sam doubts whatever John believes,
Therefore, Sam doubts that grass is green
is now formalized as
[
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff GREEN (grass)] BELIEVES (John,
p
)
[
p
: BELIEVES (John,
p
)] DOUBTS (Sam,
p
)
[
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff GREEN (grass)] DOUBTS (Sam,
p
)
The
de re/de dicto
distinction also can easily be captured. The two
readings of a belief sentence with an embedded definite description, for
example,
John believes that the winner is African
will be represented respectively as
[de re reading]
[ι
x
: WINNER (
x
)] [
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff AFRICAN (
x
)] BELIEVES (John,
p
)
and as
[de dicto reading]
[
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff [ι
x
: WINNER (
x
)] AFRICAN (
x
)] BELIEVES (John,
p
)
III.
In the above formulas I have used the symbol ‘iff’ without saying which logical
connective it stands for. One thing is sure: the connective in question cannot
be material equivalence. If it were, we would fail to capture an essential
property of belief sentences. In
[
p
: TRUE (
p
) GREEN (grass)] BELIEVES (John,
p
)
3
she has a belief with certain truth-conditions, that is, a belief that is true iff
such and such is the case. We can therefore analyse ‘John believes
that grass
is green’
as ‘John believes
something that is true iff grass is green’
(Panaccio
1996: 266-7). This means that we can treat a ‘that’-clause as, in effect, a
restricted existential quantifier, and paraphrase it as ‘For some
p
such that
p
is true iff S’ (where
‘p’
now is an
objectual
variable ranging over truth-
evaluable entities, and ‘S’ stands for the sentence embedded in the ‘that’-
clause). ‘John believes that grass is green’ is therefore equivalent to
[
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff GREEN (grass)] BELIEVES (John,
p
)
that is, ‘for some
p
such that
p
is true iff grass is green, John believes
p’
.
The semantic contribution of a quantified noun phrase is standardly
treated as a higher-order property, predicated of the property expressed by
the nuclear sentence. Similarly, the semantic contribution of ‘that grass is
green’ in ‘John believes that grass is green’ can be viewed as a higher-order
property, predicated of the property expressed by ‘John believes ξ’. That
higher-order property is the property a property has when it is possessed by
at least one entity true iff grass is green. It can be represented as
λX λ
x
[(
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff GREEN (grass)) X (
x
,
p
)]
This, then, is the semantic content of ‘that grass is green’.2 To get the
content of ‘believes that grass is green’ we apply that higher-order property
to the first-order relation that is the semantic content of ‘believes’:
λX λ
x
[(
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff GREEN (grass)) X (
x
,
p
)] (BELIEVES)
What we thereby get is a property of individuals, namely the property of
believing something that is true iff grass is green:
λ
x
[(
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff GREEN (grass)) BELIEVES (
x
,
p
)]
When this first-order property is applied to John, we get
λ
x
[(
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff GREEN (grass)) BELIEVES (
x
,
p
)] (John)
that is,
2 To get the semantic content of ‘that’, we need only to add another lambda
abstractor and to replace the formula ‘GREEN (grass)’ by a sentential
variable:
λσ λX λ
x
[(
p
: TRUE (
p
) iff σ) X (
x
,
p
)]
2
of inference, I have suggested handling it by appealing to sentential
quantification, along the following lines:
John_believes-that (grass is green)
p
(John_believes-that (
p
) Sam_doubts-that (
p
))
Sam_doubts-that (grass is green)
I still think Davidson’s paratactic analysis and the Prior-Hintikka analysis
fare better than the standard view in certain respects. The standard view
treats ‘that’-clauses as complex names referring to propositions, and that
arguably threatens semantic innocence.1 On both the Davidson and the Prior-
Hintikka view, the embedded sentence is
not
treated as a fragment of such a
name, but it remains a
bona fide
sentence — hence innocence is preserved.
Yet I am worried by the disappearance of ‘that’-clauses, which is a
consequence of their analyses. The disappearance of ‘that’-clauses
introduces an unwelcome discrepancy between grammatical form and logical
form. As far as the
grammar
is concerned, there isn’t much doubt that ‘that’-
clauses exist, and that their behaviour is (to some extent) similar to that of
noun-phrases. This, it seems, argues in favour of the standard view.
Or does it? An intermediate position may be available. One can
acknowledge the grammatical status of ‘that’-clauses as noun-phrases (or,
more accurately, as complementizer phrases similar in many respect to NPs),
while resisting the innocence-damaging claim that they are referential
expressions. To give a trivial example, quantified noun-phrases such as ‘most
children in the park’ are noun-phrases, but they are not referential
expressions. Therefore it is worth considering what would result if we decided
to treat ‘that’-clauses on the same pattern. In this way we could
acknowledge the grammatical reality of ‘that’-clauses, without accepting the
standard view and its unwelcome consequences.
II.
Can ‘that’-clauses be considered as quantified phrases? Why not? To say that
someone believes something is to say that she has a belief with a certain
content. To ascribe a content to a belief is to ascribe it certain truth-
conditions. Therefore, to say that someone believes something is to say that
1 For me ‘semantic innocence’ covers not only the requirement of semantic
constancy, but also a requirement of syntactico-semantic correspondence :
expressions of distinct grammatical categories should make semantic
contributions of different types. I am indebted to Paul Egré for discussion of
this point, both in conversation and in writing (Egré forthcoming). Thanks
also to Neftali Villanueva.
1
‘That’-clauses as existential quantifiers
FRANÇOIS RECANATI
I.
The following assumptions jointly constitute the
standard view
regarding the
logical form of belief reports:
(1) ‘believe’ and other propositional attitude verbs denote relations
between an agent and a truth-bearing entity (a ‘proposition’);
(2) ‘that’-clauses are referential expressions which denote propositions.
On this view ‘John believes that grass is green’ has the form
aRb
. The name
‘John’ and the ‘that’-clause ‘that grass is green’ are both referential
expressions, whose respective denotata fill the two argument-places in the
relation denoted by the verb. In this way we can account for the validity of
inferences such as
John believes that grass is green,
Sam doubts whatever John believes,
Therefore, Sam doubts that grass is green.
This is formalized as
BELIEVES (John, that_grass_is_green)
x
(BELIEVES (John,
x
) DOUBTS (Sam,
x
))
DOUBTS (Sam, that_grass_is_green)
Several philosophers have expressed dissatisfaction with the standard
view, on various grounds. Two alternatives have been put forward. One is
Davidson’s paratactic theory, which rejects (2). Davidson analyses attitude
reports like ‘John believes that grass is green’ as consisting of two
juxtaposed sentences: ‘John believes that’ (where ‘that’ is a demonstrative),
and ‘grass is green’. The second alternative, advocated by Prior and Hintikka,
treats ‘John believes that’ as a sentential operator analogous to modal
operators both syntactically and semantically. On this view, not only are
‘that’-clauses deprived of any linguistic reality (as on Davidson’s analysis),
but the verb ‘believes’ itself is no longer treated as denoting a first-order
relation. Hence both (1) and (2) are rejected.
I am among those who have expressed dissatisfaction with the
standard view, and in my book
Oratio Obliqua, Oratio Recta
I have argued in
favour of the Prior-Hintikka sort of view. Regarding the above-mentioned type
... Making the real logical structure or form of a sentence explicit in this way is often called a 'logical analysis'. Another example is Recanati's (2004) analysis of 'that'-clauses as restricted existential quantifiers. Following Panaccio (1996, 266-7), Recanati analyses (3) as (4), i.e. '[∃p: TRUE (p) iff WHITE (show)] BELIEVES (Nixon, p)', where p ranges over truth-bearing entities. ...
Article
Full-text available
In this paper, I will present a puzzle for logical analyses, such as Russell’s analysis of definite descriptions and Recanati’s analysis of ‘that’-clauses. I will argue that together with Kripke’s disquotational principles connecting sincere assent and belief such non-trivial logical analyses lead to contradictions. Following this, I will compare the puzzle about logical analysis with Frege’s puzzle about belief ascriptions. We will see that although the two puzzles do have similarities, the solutions to Frege’s puzzle cannot be applied mutatis mutandis to the puzzle about logical analysis. Hence, to say it with Kripke, the main thesis of this paper is that the puzzle is a puzzle. A complete solution to the puzzle promises a better understanding of both logical analyses and belief ascriptions.
... 1 For these labels and the defense of the thesis that this is the face-value theory, see Bach 1997;Braun 2015;Fara 2013;Moltmann 2003;Recanati 2004;Richard 2013, p. 146;Rosefeldt 2008;Schiffer 2003, pp. 12-14;Trueman 2018;Wettstein 2004, pp. ...
Article
For sentences such as (1) Columbus knows that the sea is unpredictable there is a face‐value theory, according to which ‘that’‐clauses are singular terms denoting propositions. Famously, Prior raised an objection to the theory, but defenders of the face‐value theory such as Forbes, King, Künne, Pietroski and Stanley urged that the objection could be met by maintaining that in (1) ‘to know’ designates a complex relation along the lines of being in a state of knowledge having as content. Is the theory safe, then? The aim of this paper is to show that a new problem for the theory arises if we consider some clauses other than ‘that’‐clauses.
... Clearly, also Russell's account is at odds with Syntactic Unity. 12 More recently, accounts of this kind were suggested by Bach (1997) and Recanati (2004). According to Scheffler, Arthur fears that natural language is messy should then be taken as saying that Arthur fears some rephrase of the concrete inscription "Natural language is messy" occurring above. ...
Article
Full-text available
In English, in order to speak about Arthur’s attitudes, we use sentences like “Arthur believes that natural language is messy”. For sentences of this kind we have a standard theory, according to which the ‘that’-clause ‘that natural language is messy’ denotes a proposition. As Prior showed for the first time, the standard theory appears to be at odds with some linguistic data. Geach and Prior both assumed that linguistic data are to be taken as reliable guides to a correct semantic account and I will start by raising some worries concerning their methodology. Because of these data, Prior and Geach suggested some non-standard accounts. I will then show that if we take linguistic data seriously, their non-standard accounts do not fare any better than the standard theory. My general conclusion will thus not only be that Prior’s and Geach’s methodology is disputable, but also that their conclusions do not seem to follow even if we grant the reliability of their methodology.
Article
Full-text available
Recently, in a series of papers, Joshua Spencer has introduced, defended, and developed a modified version of Neo-Russellianism (NR), namely Plenitudinous Russellianism (PR), according to which there are structurally identical but numerically distinct singular Russellian propositions (SRPs). PR claims to provide novel semantic solutions to all the major problems that NR faces with no radical revision in NR. In this paper, I introduce a semantic puzzle for PR: the view leads to the violation of the principle of substitutivity of co-referential proper names within simple (predicative) ‘that’-clauses (PS1). I consider different responses to my argument, and show that none of them is fully satisfactory for the Russellian. I conclude that PR needs to depart from NR more radically.
Chapter
In cases where one sentence embeds another, sometimes it is natural to see the embedding context as effecting a shift in the index of evaluation. A problem for this view comes from sentences where embedded predicates do not make the semantic contribution we would thereby expect them to. We review different ideas as to how these sentences arrive compositionally at their interpretation. According to one, the structure that gets interpreted is one where the troublemaking predicate is actually outside the syntactic scope of the expression that serves to shift indices. All the approaches have an important difficulty to face. That one also has to deal with a German football team.
Article
Thomas Hofweber has written a very rich book. In line with the conviction that ontology should be informed by linguistic considerations, he develops a systematic approach to central ontological questions as they arise in different regions of discourse. More generally, the book seeks to cast light upon the nature of ontology and its proper place in enquiry. His preferred methodology is not without consequence: it promises, for example, to solve what otherwise look like intractable philosophical puzzles raised by arithmetical practice and numerical discourse, and, likewise, his treatment of propositional discourse has ramifications for larger questions to do with the prospects of metaphysical enquiry generally. In what follows, I would like to comment on the general approach to ontology and to look at the special case of propositional discourse and its ramifications for metaphysics. 1. Quantification and ontology At the heart of the book is the thesis that quantifiers are semantically underspecified. There is at least a distinction between an external and an internal reading of a quantifier. The external reading is tied to the representational role of the quantifier whereby the world is portrayed to come with a domain of objects over which the quantifier ranges. On the external reading, the truth conditions of a quantified sentence are given in terms of a condition on an external domain of individual objects: a sentence of the form ‘something is A’ is true if, and only if, some member of the external domain is in the extension of A. Other quantifiers are associated with different conditions on the external domain.
Article
Reductionist realist accounts of certain entities, such as the natural numbers and propositions, have been taken to be fatally undermined by what we may call the problem of arbitrary identification. The problem is that there are multiple and equally adequate reductions of the natural numbers to sets (see Benacerraf, 1965), as well as of propositions to unstructured or structured entities (see, e.g., Bealer, 1998; King, Soames, & Speaks, 2014; Melia, 1992). This paper sets out to solve the problem by canvassing what we may call the arbitrary reference strategy. The main claims of such strategy are 2. First, we do not know which objects are the referents of proposition and numerical terms since their reference is fixed arbitrarily. Second, our ignorance of which object is picked out as the referent does not entail that no object is referred to by the relevant expression. Different articulations of the strategy are assessed, and a new one is defended.
Chapter
I am proud of being able to say that Jan Woleński was my first friend in Poland and that he still is my best Polish friend. So I am glad that I can contribute a paper to his Festschrift. ‘Künne likes to remain very close to natural language and its parlance’, Jan wrote in his contribution to a symposium on a book on truth in Dialectica 62 (2008). Since I want to elucidate our workaday concept of truth, I do indeed like to stay close to natural language: after all, that’s where this concept gets expressed in the first place. ‘Sooner or later’, Jan wrote in the same article, ‘we encounter problems which require a clear decision concerning the metalogical properties of “is true.” Is it a predicate or a modality? […]’ This is the main question that I want to clarify and to answer in this paper. Tackling this problem requires close attention to the syntactical and semantical status of that-clauses. The questions such clauses evoke when we brood on truth ascriptions (‘It is true that p’) reappear when we consider reports of propositional attitudes (‘A φs that p’) and ascriptions of sentential meaning (‘S means that p’), That’s why I shall also discuss the second and the third issue which the verbose title of this paper alludes to. Arthur N. Prior saw the connection, and in each of these fields he opted for the same treatment of that-clauses. I shall argue that it is a mistreatment.
Chapter
What I call a nominalistic analysis of belief-sentences is an explication of the meaning of sentences of the form ‘A believes that p’ that does not commit the analyst to the existence of special abstract entities such as sets, Fregean senses and propositions, or universal properties and relations. I take it, without discussing the point here, that if it is feasible, such an analysis is prima facie philosophically preferable to a realistic one for general reasons of clarity and ontological economy. But the question, of course, is: is it, in some reasonable way, feasible? Standard nominalistic approaches to belief-sentences all face well-known and crucial difficulties. The quotational theory, according to which the object-sentence ‘p’ is quoted or mentioned within the belief- sentence ‘A believes that p’, fails the Langford-Church translation test.1 The metalinguistic analysis, on the other hand, according to which the ‘that’-clause within the belief-sentence is, in every case, a primitive metalinguistic predicate fails to satisfy Davidson’s learnability requirement.2 And Davidson’s own approach, the so-called paratactic theory, according to which ‘A believes that p’ means simply ‘A believes this, p’ fails, for all its virtues, to accommodate some important illocutionary and logical characteristics of belief- sentences.3 These negative results from the last four or five decades of debates led more than one phi-losopher to conclude drastically that nominalism just can’t cope with belief-sentences in any satisfactory way. What I would like to show here is that there is still at least one more line of investigation for nominalism in this endeavour. Space being severely limited, I will be content to sketch the general features of this hitherto unexplored approach and to list some of the motivations for it as well as some of its theoretical advantages.
Article
A summary of my book *Oratio Obliqua, Oratio Recta*, published by MIT Press in 2000 ('Representation and Mind' series).
Article
Postcripts to "A pragmatic approach to the problem of logical omniscience"