ArticlePDF Available

The sociological foundations of organizational learning

Authors:
2The Sociological Foundations
of Organizational Learning
Silvia Gherardi, Davide Nicolini
The purpose of this chapter is to illustrate the
speci®c contribution that general sociology
and the sociology of organizations can make
to the study of organizational learning. The
®rst part provides an overview of the possible
ontological and epistemological choices avail-
able to scholars who undertake one of the
various possible readings of organizational
learning from a sociological standpoint. In the
second part of the chapter, our epistemological
choice is to see organizational learning as a root
metaphor. It is on that basis that we attempt to
determine what contribution a social construc-
tionist approach has made to the study of
organizational learning through two concepts
of participation and re¯exivity. Sociology
The concept of participation highlights the
fact that learning does not take place solely or
principally in the minds of individuals but
rather stems from the participation of indivi-
duals in social activities. Working and organiz-
ing are social practices engaged in through a set
of activities situated in speci®c contexts of
interaction. Organizational learning is learn-
ing-in-organizing, because working, learning,
and organizing are not distinct activities within
a practice. The concept of participation, there-
fore, gives access to the study of organizational
learning that takes place in action and through
action. GherardiandNicolini
The concept of re¯exivity is tied closely to
participation in that re¯exivity occurs when
the ¯ow of experience is interrupted and the
subject re¯ects on knowledge. Re¯exivity refers
to ways of seeing that act back on and re¯ect
existing ways of seeing; re¯exivity gives rise to
the institutionalization of knowledge. The
principal feature of re¯exivity is that re¯ection
produces the setting that contains its object as
well as its expected and unexpected outcomes.
In other words, re¯exivity ensures that the
social production of that area of studies
known as `organizational learning' will pro-
duce the very phenomenon that it studies.
Five Sociological Traditions
Just as is it dif®cult to mark the boundaries
around any discipline in any historical period
Ðthe watchword being `blurring disciplinary
boundaries' (Linstead 1994:3)Ðit is equally dif-
®cult to describe differentiation within them.
Numerous authors have attempted the task,
and we certainly have no intention of propos-
ing a new classi®cation. Aware of the ®ctitious
and arbitrary nature of any endeavor to recount
the history of a discipline, we refer instead to
the scheme proposed by Collins (1994) and sup-
plemented by other contributions in order to
discuss the fact that the insights into organiza-
tional learning yielded by sociology vary
greatly depending on the sociological
approach chosen. Collins identi®ed four socio-
logical traditions: the tradition of con¯ict,
35
This chapter is the result of an entirely collaborative effort by the two authors: If, however, for academic
reasons individual responsibility must be assigned, Silvia Gherardi wrote the second, third, and fourth
sections; Davide Nicolini wrote the ®rst section, the introduction, and the conclusions. The authors
thank Adrian Belton for editing an earlier version of the text.
which he traced back to Marx, Engels, and
Weber; the rational-utilitarian tradition begun
by Homans, Blau, Cook, and Simon; the Dur-
kheimian tradition, in which functionalism
takes the name of its outstanding theoretician;
and the microinteractionist tradition of such
authors as Peirce, Mead, Husserl, Schutz, and
Gar®nkel.
We ¯ank these four traditions with an
approach that, given its youth, cannot properly
be called a tradition but that has nevertheless
been a stimulating re¯ection on knowledge:
postmodernism.
The Tradition of Conflict
This tradition represents a line of thought that
directs attention to the structure of dominant
and subordinate interest groups, to social con-
¯ict, and to power systems. Its principal thesis
is that society is based on con¯ict and that, in
the absence of open con¯ict, a process of dom-
ination prevails. In this tradition the social
order is perceived as the outcome of a struggle
between groups and individuals seeking to
ensure that their own interests predominate
over those of others. Also, organizations are
not innocuous instruments in the hands of
their creators, and political interpretation of
organizational life can be found in Michels
(1911), Selznick (1949), Gouldner (1954), Dalton
(1959), Etzioni (1961), and Crozier (1963). For
Marxism and the Frankfurt school, the econo-
my is what determines politics, law, and
human culture; the materialistic dynamic is
what produces the inevitable contradictions
and transformations identi®ed by Hegel
(1807). Con¯ict is expressed and masked by
ideology. Every social class tends to view the
world in a particular way, and its ideas mirror
its economic interests and the social circum-
stances that de®ne those interests. As ideology,
ideas are exalted by people and are used to
cloak interests in respectable guise.
Weber's (1922/78) thought has exerted its
in¯uence on the sociology of organization
through the model of bureaucracy and its func-
tionalist misinterpretation (Clegg 1995). But the
sociological tradition of con¯ict has continued
to exacerbate the contradiction between sub-
stantial rationality (the capacity of humans to
understand that certain means lead to certain
ends) and formal rationality (obedience to
norms and written rules), a type of behavior
®rst highlighted by Mannheim (1935), then
developed by critical theory, and today theo-
rized by Beck (1992) in the concept `risk society',
a society that escapes human control because
formal rationality has supplanted substantial
rationality.
The theme of control is mirrored by the
theme of power, both within organizations
and among them. Not only has modernization
produced a society of organizations (Perrow
1991; Presthus 1978), but forms of control have
gradually changed from external control
(direct or mediated by technology) to norma-
tive control, which is internalized and based on
the control of decisional and cultural assump-
tions. In postindustrial societies, power-based
social divisions have become more rami®ed,
and, with the increasing use of knowledge for
productive purposes, the linkage between
knowledge and power has given rise to social
con¯icts that are more articulated and complex
than the property-based class con¯icts that
characterized the onset of industrialization
(Clegg 1990; Rothman and Friedman, Ch. 26 in
this volume).
The use of knowledge on a vast scale has
produced a new class of technicoscienti®c
experts, and neologisms such as `knowledge-
®rm' (Starbuck 1992) and `knowledge-workers'
(Zuboff 1988) have appeared in scienti®c as well
as everyday language. The term `organizational
learning' also belongs to this rhetoric, whose
system of persuasion is grounded in knowledge
(Alvesson 1993).
Drawing on both the interpretative tools of
sociology and the tradition of con¯ict, one can
interpret the theme of organizational learning
in three ways.
1.Organizational learning as the ideology of
particular power groups. The ideas subsumed
under the heading `organizational learning'
are extolled. As a consequence, the label `learn-
36 Gherardi and Nicolini
ing organization' has been coined to celebrate
an organizational identity and draw a social
distinction between those organizations con-
forming to a bureaucratic model and those in
which a `new' managerial philosophy is pro-
pounded (Easterby-Smith, Snell, and Gherardi
1998). This philosophy may become ®rst a
methodology, then a technique, as the pre-
scriptiveness of its contents increases, and as
its capacity to discipline members of an organ-
ization grows (Gherardi 1999). Management is
one of the social actors interested in developing
a managerial theory of organizational learning
that will give it legitimacy, but it is not the only
power group that can use this ideology to mask
its interests. Traditional occupational groups of
experts and new occupational groups that
may emerge as experts on organizational learn-
ing will also develop various versions of the
ideology in order to legitimate covert power
struggles against other communities of experts
that possess their own knowledge resources
and compete against them (Snell and Chack
1998).
2.Organizational learning as a policy of mobil-
izing power. In both organizations and society,
knowledge is a resource for social strati®cation
insofar as it gives rise to positions of relative
power that, by virtue of their intrinsic instabil-
ity, must be defended and possibly reinforced.
To create knowledge is to produce a value
resource that can be exchanged. Transmitting
knowledge involves transferring a value; utiliz-
ing knowledge entails exploiting a resource
that is offered for exchange on a political (and
economic) market. Historically, the professions
arose out of the monopolization and institutio-
nalization of sources that had the legitimacy to
produce and transmit knowledge. Within
organizations, that which individuals or
groups learn gives them power over those who
`do not know' or who `know less ef®ciently',
and it is a source of potential con¯ict (Coopey
1995). The circulation of knowledge within
organizations, its exploitation for productive
purposes, and its codi®cation as useful, good,
correct, or prescribed take place within the
micropolitics of quotidian power relationships
(Gherardi, Nicolini, and Odella 1998b). In other
words, power and con¯ict render the circula-
tion of knowledge nontransparent and conceal
the social conditions of its production.
3.Organizational learning as an attempt to
manage the tension between substantial and
formal rationality. Learning conditioned by
substantial rationality is learning acquired
through experience, with logical connections
being established between the means, the ends,
and the consequences of action, and behavior
being modi®ed on the basis of these inferences.
Put differently, substantial rationality is the
learning that people acquire in their work, but
this learning cannot automatically be trans-
ferred to the rules and regulations that govern
organizational behavior. Consequently, obedi-
ence to formal rationality gives rise to unin-
tended effects that fail to take account of
learning from experience. The literature on
how and why organizations do not learn (Hed-
berg 1981) highlights this loss of meaning
caused by the social mechanisms that repro-
duce instrumental rationality. Rationalization
is the enemy of rationality, hence of organiza-
tional learning, a term that can be regarded as
an oxymoron (Merkens, Geppert, and Antal,
Ch. 10 in this volume; Weick and Westley
1996). In fact, learning and organizing can be
de®ned as antithetical processes. The former
focuses on a disorganization and increase of
variety; the latter, on a forgetting and reduction
of variety.
The Rational±Utilitarian Tradition
Utilitarianism has distant origins in British
social philosophy, and later became a discipline
in the ®eld of economics. Collins (1994:85)
argued that the utilitarian tradition is not
sociological in a strict sense, though it has
numerous points of contact with sociology. In
the 1950s a broader intellectual movement
known as `rational choice (or action) theory'
arose, taking the name of `public choice' theory
in political science and `exchange theory' in
sociology.
Rational utilitarianism in sociology has a
great deal in common with con¯ict theory in
the sense that society, from both pointsof view,
Sociology 37
is considered to be a set of groups and indivi-
duals who pursue interests and calculate
advantages. Unlike con¯ict theory, however,
rational utilitarianism is not focused on polit-
ical con¯ict, social strati®cation, or inequality.
Instead, rational utilitarians seek to explain
society in terms of people's rational motiv-
ations and the manner in which they rationally
perform exchanges so that everything func-
tions in the best possible way.
In sociology, utilitarians have provoked a
controversy known as the micro/macro pro-
blem (Collins 1994). They conceive of society
as being held together by the actions of indivi-
duals at the microlevel, and they reject the idea
of society as a macrostructure existing above
and beyond individuals. For example, they dis-
pute the notion that culture is determined by
the actions of people. Utilitarians instead seek
to understand what motivates individuals to
act beyond their own self-interest. Accounting
for sel¯ess behavior by individuals is one of the
paradoxes that has enriched rational utilitar-
ianism, and it well illustrates the method used
in this tradition of thought: On the assumption
that individuals are rational and intent on
maximizing their interests, utilitarians analyze
the limits of rationality, as in the phenomenon
of free riding (Olson 1965), or the prisoner's
dilemma (Luce and Raiffa 1957).
A pioneer of utilitarianism in sociology
was George Homans (1950,1961). Disagreeing
with Parsons's (1951) functionalism, Homans
claimed that not only is the social system a
myth, but so, too, are the standards according
to which individuals act (the role system),
which are inculcated in them by the socializa-
tion process. Homans argued that the more
individuals interact as equals and on the basis
of reciprocity, the more they come to accept,
assimilate, and conform to a common stand-
ard. As individuals interact, cohesive groups
form and develop a shared culture and a nor-
mative system, both at the workplace and in
the neighborhood. According to Homans, the
reason for this emergence of a shared culture
and a normative system is the reward intrinsic
to the interaction, social approval, for the
group will remain united as long as its members
exchange these rewards. Other authors, such
as Blau (1964), have studied the patterns of
exchange and the exchange networks in
which individuals negotiate approval among
themselves (Cook et al.1983).
The tradition in which Homans, Blau, and
Cook et al. stand includes the premise that
power derives from the unequal exchange of
resources and that each of the parties to an
exchange adjusts its manner of negotiating
according to the resources at its disposal. This
conception of exchange has been highly in¯u-
ential in the sociology of organizations, where
the rational-choice paradigm is recognized as
one of the classical theories expounding on the
paradoxes of rationality in organizational deci-
sion theory (March 1988; Simon 1957).
This strand of studies has provided one of
the most coherent accounts of organizational
learning as adaptation (Levitt and March 1988).
The recognition of a performance gap stimul-
ates actors within an organization to search for
knowledge about alternative courses of action
that might reduce the gap between current and
desired performance. Searches may be based on
existing knowledge and existing views of the
world or on the creation of new knowledge
through formal investigations, environmental
scanning, individual experiential learning, or
armchair theorizing.
The contributions of the rational±utilitarian
tradition to organizational learning can be
summarized in three conceptualizations.
1.Organizational learning serves as a problem-
driven search when the organization's perform-
ance does not meet aspiration levels. This kind
of organizational learning is the conscious
learning that takes place within an adaptive
learning system in which a great deal of beha-
vior takes place through standard operating
procedures. The study by Cyert and March
(1963) was the landmark of this neorationalist
approach, although the most strictly sociologi-
cal contribution was made by research into
incomplete learning cycles (March and Olsen
1976; see also Berthoin Antal, Lenhardt, and
Rosenbrock, Ch. 39 in this volume). Cyert and
March (1963) pointed out where the paradoxes
38 Gherardi and Nicolini
of rationality arise, and they highlighted the
impact of ambiguity on interpretation pro-
cesses as well as the emotional and cultural
factors that mould adaptation to experience
(Kieser, Beck, and Tainio, Ch. 27; Pawlowsky,
Forslin, and Reinhardt, Ch. 35 in this volume).
2.Organizational learning serves as the activ-
ation of an exchange network that takes the
form of a market for knowledge and skills.
Knowledge is input into the production pro-
cess, and ®rms acquire it externally in the
form of people in possession of it, patents, and
the technologies that embody and produce it.
The more that knowledge is explicit, codi®ed,
and universal, the more it acquires the transfer-
able nature of a commodity. Conversely, the
more that knowledge is implicit, tacit, and
situated, the more it becomes an asset of the
people and groups that possess it and the more
it is embodied in skills and speci®c practices.
The `invisible assets' of an organization (speci-
®c skills and tacit expertise) are based on idio-
syncratic forms of knowledge (Baumard 1996;
Nonaka and Takeuchi 1995; Spender 1996a).
Workplace control has historically changed
hands in the presence of a different market:
Knowledge work-groups are characterized by
high levels of autonomy and self-management,
trust relations with customers, and uncertain
and ambiguous tasks (Butera, Donati, and
Cesaria 1998). Control becomes concentrated
in the product rather than in the process of
work.
3.Organizational learning as an ecology of
learning located within distributed, multiactor
routines rather than within individual minds
(Arujo 1998). Organizations learn by taking
inferences from past experience and encoding
them into the routines, rules, procedures, con-
ventions, strategies, and technologies that
guide behavior (Levitt and March 1988). This
approach revives Bateson's (1972) work on the
logical levels of learning, but it is also con-
cerned with the speci®c rationality of corporate
actors and the societal consequences of the
power that those actors acquire by monopoliz-
ing knowledge, institutionalizing forms of
systemic myopia, or imitating maladaptive
learning (Levinthal and March 1993). Nelson
(1991) and Tsoukas (1992) viewed ®rms as hier-
archies of routines and argued that most of the
knowledge possessed by ®rms is tacit and
resides not in the heads of individuals but in
teams of individuals with shared experiences
and with only a partial view of what constitutes
a particular routine.
The Durkheimian Tradition
Durkheim's work remains the central tradition
of sociological thought, and both sociology
and social anthropology have developed
within it. Durkheim's followers used the term
`ethnology' for empirical descriptions of tribal
societies and the term `sociology' to denote the
theoretical analysis of society. They believed
that tribal societies were simpler than modern
society and that tribal societies most clearly
evinced the `elementary forms' of social life,
by which was meant, as Collins (1994) put it,
the sentiments, emotions, morality, the sacred,
and the religious that together constitute the
essence of every society as expressed in its
symbolism.
Although Durkheim (1912) forcefully argued
for the in¯uence of `nonrational' elements in
the shaping of society, he is important to the
history of sociology as the founder of sociolo-
gical method and of sociology as the science of
the social order. Paradigmatic of Durkheim's
work is his study of suicide (1897), in which
the circumstances in which a phenomenon
occurs were compared with circumstances in
which it does not. Accordingly, suicideÐor, as
in this handbook, learningÐcan be treated as a
variable. The researcher examines the rates of
incidence of the variable `suicide' (or learning)
as well as its variations in the presence of cer-
tain factors (e.g. age, religion, civil status, and
climate), and sets it in relation to the social
structure. On the basis of empirical indicators,
therefore, alternative explanations can be sys-
tematically tested and theoretical generaliza-
tions or `laws of the social' formulated. In fact
most structuralist studies of organizational
learning follow the Durkheimian model, with
organizations conceived of as social contexts
for learning.
Sociology 39
In the Durkheimian tradition society is con-
ceived of as operating `from outside', so to
speak. Society works externally, on narrow
social groups and society as a whole, exerting
pressure, constraining social action, and shap-
ing sentiments and collective ideas. As regards
suicide, for example, members of groups with
high social density are less likely to kill them-
selves. Social density is not physical density; it
is, rather, moral density, that is, the extent to
which organic solidarity is present in a com-
munity with a `shared life', a life in which indi-
viduals take part in rituals and ceremonies that
focus the emotions of the individual onto the
group. Individuals belong to a broad society
that constrains and moulds them. But they
can also withdraw and meet together to prac-
tice those rituals of everyday life that produce
social density. Society has a nonrational
grounding in ritual, and utilitarian consider-
ations alone cannot hold it together. The Dur-
kheimian tradition therefore incorporates two
currents, one focused on the macroaspects of
society, the other on the microaspects. The for-
mer current developed through an emphasis
on the theory of the social division of labor
and scienti®c method, resulting in the func-
tionalism of Merton (1957) and Parsons (1951).
The second current concentrating on the
microaspects of society has maintained its
links with social anthropology and the analysis
of ritual through the work of Durkheim's
nephew, Mauss (1968), and then through the
work of Goffman (1967,1971) and Bernstein
(1971±1975). Analogously, organizational learn-
ing can be either analyzed as a dependent vari-
able, so that one looks for the (macrostructural)
conditions that favor or impede it, or concep-
tualized as a socialization process to speci®c
cultural codes.
In brief, in the ®rst current of the Durkhei-
mian tradition organizational learning is de®ned
as a dependent variable. Other variables (strat-
egy, structure, or culture) de®ne the conditions
that facilitate or hinder organizational learning
(Duncan and Weiss 1979; Tomassini 1993; War-
glien 1990). Learning is conceived of as one of
the functions of the organizational system,
which engenders change on some occasions
and conservation on others. The theory of
cybernetics is drawn upon both in its simple
feedback version, in which a change of state
occurs when environmental conditions alter,
and in its double-loop version (Argyris and
Scho
Èn1974,1978; Fiol and Lyles 1985), in which
parameters change by virtue of self-organiza-
tion or learning. At bottom, the functions
attributed to organizational learning explain
its dynamics and its position in the organiza-
tion. The manifest function of organizational
learning is to achieve the results that indivi-
duals consciously strive for, including adjust-
ment to changed operational or informational
circumstances and the ability to develop fresh
approaches to situations, to experiment, or to
innovate (Starbuck 1983). The latent function of
organizational learning is generated by the
social system itself, one example, being the
protection of the advantages gained through
the operation of mechanisms requiring modi-
®cation. Organizational learning can be both
explorative and exploitative (March 1996).
The second current, represented by such
scholars as Bernstein (1971±1975), Douglas
(1970), and Collins (1979), has furnished insights
that formulate a structural theory of occupa-
tional or professional cultures and subcultures.
Durkheim's legacy to the analysis of organiza-
tional cultures is immense, as Ouchi and Wilk-
ins (1985) stressed when they examined the
contribution made by sociology to the analysis
of organizational cultures.
This sociological tradition, therefore, con-
ceptualizes organizational learning as socializa-
tion to speci®c cultural codes. Socialization, in
fact, sensitizes subjects to the different orders of
society because it acts selectively on their life-
chances, creating a sense of a given social
order's inevitability and restricting the amount
of change that is permitted. The contexts
of socialization identi®ed by Bernstein (1971±
1975) can be transferred from child to adult
socialization and from an extended social con-
text to a restricted one, such as an organization.
Accordingly, in different contexts of socializa-
tion, speci®c contents of organizational learn-
ing are activated when individuals join speci®c
occupational communities within a particular
40 Gherardi and Nicolini
organization. These contexts of socialization
areÐ
.the regulatory context formed by the author-
ity relationships that sensitize individuals to
the rules of the moral order and their under-
lying structures. The social reproduction of
the hierarchy and the moral order that
regulates relationships among occupational
groups with differing endowments of know-
ledge and power are actuated in this context.
.the educational context, in which indivi-
duals are instructed on the objective nature
of objects and people, and in which they
learn various skills. This context pertains to
the reproduction of expertise.
.the imaginative or innovative context, in
which individuals are encouraged to experi-
ence the world on its own terms. This context
is internal to occupational communities in
which self-images and individual and collect-
ive identities are produced through experi-
mentation and negotiation.
.the interpersonal context, in which people
learn to know their own affective states and
those of others. This context pertains to
socialization in the appropriate social rela-
tionships that grant membership in a com-
munity. In this case, the organization is a
social structure external to the contexts of
socialization, which it structures into one
form rather than another by promoting, or
impeding learning processes.
The Microinteractionist Tradition
The microinteractionist tradition owes a two-
fold debt to philosophy: First, to Peirce's prag-
matism (1931±1935), and second, to Schutz's
phenomenology. Peirce coined the term
`semiotics' (the science of signs) and developed
the theory that individuals cannot perceive
things or think about the world without the
mediation of signs. Consequently, meaning
always exists in a three-way relationship
between the sign, the object, and the internal
referent (the thought). Peirce thus introduced a
social element into theories on the mind of the
individual because, as he explained, thought is
always realized in a community, and what the
community considers to be `true' and `object-
ive' is only what is based on habitus (the
historical product of previous individual
and collective practices). People, Peirce main-
tained, are nothing but the sum of their
thoughts, the historical accumulation of their
social experiences.
The social theory of the mind was re®ned by
Cooley (1964), who maintained that thought
consists of an imaginary conversation with
the self and that society is the mind of all indi-
viduals. Thus, society is a relationship among
ideas, and the ways in which individuals ima-
gine each other are the `concrete facts' exam-
ined by sociology. Much more in¯uential in the
sociology of thought than Cooley, however,
was Mead (1934), who posited that society is
grounded on re¯ectivity, or the ability of the
self to re¯ect upon itself. The self is a point of
view. Every individual possesses a plurality of
selves, and thought is a form of conversation
conducted by individuals with themselves.
Mead's social theory of the mind exerted a
profound in¯uence on Blumer (1969) and the
symbolic interactionist approach, which had
also assimilated insights from Dewey (1922)
and his critique of the doctrine of `rational
man'. Alfred Schutz's social phenomenology
in¯uenced Gar®nkel (1967), Goffman (1967),
and the ethnomethodological movement.
Both in symbolic interactionism and ethno-
methodology society is conceived of not as a
structure but as a process. People do not assume
ready-made roles but rather create and re-create
them according to the given situation. Social
institutions exist only insofar as individuals
come into contact with each other and jointly
construct actions.
Social action comes about because indivi-
duals project various social `me's' onto future
situations; they then assume the role of the
Other, predict the consequences, and model
their actions accordingly. This process of con-
tinuous negotiation yields `de®nitions of the
situation' and the social construction of reality
(Berger and Luckman 1966).
The concept of `de®nition of the situation'
was developed by Thomas and celebrated in his
Sociology 41
aphorism, `If one de®nes a situation as real,
then it is real in its consequences' (Thomas
1928:512). Reality is ¯uid and susceptible to
rapid changes, and if the way in which indivi-
duals de®ne a certain situation changes, then
so, too, does the type of behavior that it
induces. Social life has a peculiar tendency to
become whatever people think it is.
A microinteractionist approach is the cradle
of the concept of organizational learning as the
transmission of knowledge within occupational
communities. The theory starts from the hy-
pothesis that occupations (or professions) are
forms of interaction negotiated by subjects
engaged in work practices. Doctors, janitors,
lawyers, social workers, and so on produce not
only `work' but also social relations, identities,
and self-images. As they work, members of an
occupational community are intent on hiding
the `dirty' aspects of their work and the `dodges'
known only to initiates. They do so in order to
manipulate their public image and to increase
their bargaining power vis-a
Á-vis members of
other occupational communities or the public
in general. Studies of the noncanonical prac-
tices in professions (or occupations) shed a
great deal of light on the purportedly `transpar-
ent' transmission of knowledge (Boland and
Tenkasi 1995; Brown and Duguid 1991; Suchman
1987). This line of inquiry, in fact, is indebted to
the ethnomethodological approach (see Czar-
niawska, Ch. 5in this volume). The term
`ethnomethodology' (Flynn 1991) indicates
that this approach is an examination of social
reality through observation (ethnography) and
that researchers who use it seek to uncover the
methods that individuals employ in order to
give meaning to experience (methodology).
Learning therefore has to do with participating,
with becoming a member of a community,
because social relations are important for the
transmission of knowledge, the mastering of a
situated curriculum (Gherardi, Nicolini, and
Odella 1998a), and the relational development
of identity (Blackler 1995; Wenger 1998). Con-
sequently, learning is always situated in the
sphere of social interaction.
The social dimension of learning suggests the
existence of a `group mind' that takes the form
of cognitive interdependence centered on
memory processes. People working together
give life to a single transactive memory system,
complete with differentiated responsibility for
remembering their experiences. The behaviors
of people in organizations, like to the neuron
connections in the brain, may be spontan-
eously and tacitly activated and then intercon-
nect so that they coordinate an intelligent
action. Social learning is thus a network of col-
lective behaviors based on distributed know-
ledge (Tsoukas 1996).
The microinteractionist account of learning
as social and cultural process has also devel-
oped through studies on communities of prac-
tice (Brown and Duguid 1991; Lave and Wenger
1991; Orr 1993; Stopford, Ch. 11 in this volume;
Stucky 1995; Zucchermaglio 1995). Lave and
Wenger (1991) are taken to be the represent-
atives of the so-called situated learning theory.
They de®ne a community of practice as `a set of
relations among persons, activity, and world,
over time and in relation with other tangential
and overlapping communities of practice. A
community of practice is an intrinsic condition
for the existence of knowledge, not least
because it provides the interpretative support
necessary for making sense of its heritage'
(p. 98). Working, learning, and innovating are
not distinct activities; they are, rather, closely
bound up with each other in a local practice
and in the culture of that practice.
A similar concept, that of the occupational
community, has been developed in studies of
organizational cultures (Barley 1991; Gherardi
1990; Kunda 1986; Strati 1986; Van Maanen and
Barley 1984). It focuses on the growth of local
cultures, the socialization of their members,
and the `organization' that results from nego-
tiation within communities and between the
communities external and internal to a given
organization. Both concepts share the Weber-
ian idea of the dynamic between Gemeinschaft
and Gesellschaft, which is inherent in the con-
cept of community, but they differ in the
emphasis that they place on either practice or
occupation.
The distinctive features of the microinter-
actionist tradition are its constructionist epis-
42 Gherardi and Nicolini
temology (the idea that society is constituted
in and by the interpretative practices of its
members) and its stress on the role of language
as the medium of such social construction.
Speech acts are units of language and action;
they are part of practice. They are not descrip-
tions but, rather, types of action like any other
action in a given practice. Language is not only
the expression of social relations; it is also the
medium for their creation (Czarniawska-
Joerges 1991). The previous point implicitly
highlights the impact of the `linguistic turn'
(Alvesson and Deetz 1996:205) in organization
studies. The turning point came with the
notion that language does not describe or
represent reality (language is not tied to mean-
ing or perception); rather, it constructs the
`objects' and `subjects' of reality.
The contribution of this sociological tradi-
tion is the study of organizational learning as
a label that both produces a socially constructed
reality and is produced by that reality. The label
`organizational learning' gives identity to a
scienti®c community whose social practices
are grounded in such pursuits as writing and
talking about organizational learning, organiz-
ing conferences, and founding new journals
(Nicolini and Meznar 1995; Spender 1996b).
Indeed, a wholly sociological phenomenon is
the social process by which a term, organiza-
tional learning, is coined for managerial prac-
tices; a new subjectivity is socially created;
®rms that de®ne themselves as `learning organ-
izations' appear; and social researchers pro-
liferate and, equipped with survey tools, set
off in quest of `learning organizations', deter-
mined to measure the properties of this new
`object' in the physical world (Gherardi 1999).
Words, labels, metaphors, and platitudes pro-
duce the reality that people experience as `out
there'.
The characteristic features of construction-
ism are contingency, negotiation, breakdown,
discontinuity, heterogeneity, and fragment-
ation. Accordingly, in a social constructionist
approach organizational learning is seen as
situated; knowledge is seen to stem from nego-
tiations, breakdowns, and discontinuities; and
knowing is seen as heterogeneous and frag-
mented. The process of learning can therefore
be better understood when it is located in the
domains of knowledge, language, and interpre-
tation rather than in action and its outcomes.
These features are at odds with the traditional
psychological models of learning (based on sti-
mulus±response theory), which are acritically
transferred to the study of organizational learn-
ing (Maier, Prange, and Rosenstiel, Ch. 1in this
volume; Weick 1991). Within the microinterac-
tionist tradition an antithesis to modernist
thought has thus begun to appear. In the next
section we examine the insights that such post-
modernist thought can offer.
The Postmodern Tradition?
It is only with a certain amount of irony that
one can talk of a postmodern tradition in
sociology, given that systematic criticism of
modernist thought dates back only to the late
1980s. Although postmodernism originated in
aesthetics and philosophy (Lyotard 1984; Vatti-
mo 1985), sociologists soon declared themselves
for or against this silent cultural revolution
(Clegg 1990; Giddens 1990). Preeminent in the
postmodern approach to organizations is the
in¯uence of French poststructuralism, decon-
structionism (Derrida 1971), and Foucault's the-
ory of discourses (1980) as contingent systems
of thought that inform both linguistic and
material practices through speci®c technolo-
gies of power producing speci®c forms of sub-
jectivity.
The central theme of the debate on the post-
modern, or on postmodernisms, is the critique
of that modernism which is characterized by
grand narratives, the concepts of totality and
development, and essentialism. Although post-
modernism is generally de®ned by default in
the literature, the topics on the postmodern
agenda can be summarized as
the constructed nature of people and reality,
emphasizing language as a system of distinctions
which are central to the construction process,
arguing against grand narratives and large-scale the-
oretical systems, such as Marxism, or functionalism,
emphasizing the power±knowledge connection
and the role of claims of expertise in systems of
Sociology 43
domination, emphasizing the ¯uid and hyperreal
nature of the contemporary world and the role of
mass-media and information technologies, and
stressing narrative/®ction/rhetoric as central to the
research process. (Alvesson and Deetz 1996:192)
The role of research in postmodern thought is
not that of `discovering the truth' but of chal-
lenging the conventional wisdom, routines,
static meanings, and axioms of `normal'
science, thereby exposing knowledge to non-
dogmatic forms of thought (Astley 1985; Gergen
1992).
In discussing how the topic of organizational
learning is addressed in the postmodern tradi-
tion, we consider here those issues on the post-
modern agenda that are relevant to learning:
the relationship between knowledge and
power, the central importance of language
and discourse, and fragmented identity.
The relationship between knowledge and
power is crucial, both because it challenges
the existence of any universalistic foundation
to knowledge and because learning is intim-
ately bound up with the production of know-
ledge. Every attempt to label something as
`knowledge' is made by a speci®c social com-
munity belonging to a network of power rela-
tions, and not by a world consisting purely of
ideas. Hence, no knowledge is universal or
supreme; instead, all knowledge is produced
within social, historical, and linguistic rela-
tions grounded in speci®c forms of con¯ict
and the division of labor. Power is implicit in
the language that draws distinctions, hier-
archizes terms, permits modes of reasoning
and discursive practices that, in turn, organize
the social institutions and produce one type of
subject rather than another. Therefore, in the
sense of the `narrative turn' (Bruner 1990:1),
stories told and retold in organizations become
important because memory is retained not so
much in propositions as in stories. Stories are
vehicles of organizational memory, and the
development of stories constitutes organiza-
tional learning (Sims 1999).
The obvious implication for the study of
organizational learning is that the concept
and its adoption should be situated within the
network of knowledge/power relations that
produces it. Take, for example, managerial
knowledge. It shapes the identity of a group of
people; creates a bond of solidarity, shared
interests, and a profession; establishes criteria
for selection, remuneration, membership, and
exclusion; and allocates power and resources
with which to discipline the behavior of mem-
bers and nonmembers. Townley (1993) dis-
cussed Foucault's (1977) concept of discipline,
applying it to human resource management in
order to show that this form of expert know-
ledge is used to exert control over another
social group.
As Foucault (1977) argued, a discipline can be
conceived of as a speci®c technology of power:
`Disciplinary power is exercised through its
invisibility; at the same time it imposes on
those it subjects a compulsory visibility. In dis-
cipline, it is the subjects who have to be seen. It
is the fact of being constantly seen that main-
tains the disciplined individual in his subjec-
tion' (p. 187). Foucault (1988) de®ned four major
technologies of self-understanding that enter
into the power game of truth:
1) technologies of production, which permit us to
produce, transform, or manipulate things; 2) tech-
nologies of sign systems, which permit us to use
signs, meanings symbols, or signi®cation; 3) tech-
nologies of power, which determine the conduct of
individuals and submit them to certain ends or
domination, an objectivizing of the subject; and 4)
technologies of the self, which permit individuals to
effect by their own means or with the help of others
a certain number of operations on their own bodies
and souls, thoughts, conduct, and the way of being,
as to transform themselves in order to attain a cer-
tain state of happiness, purity, wisdom, perfection,
or immortality. (p. 18)
A Foucauldian reading of the managerial use of
the concept of organizational learning is there-
fore the interpretation of the use of this con-
cept as a technology of power used to discipline
organizational members.
Although postmodern analysis in organiza-
tion studies is only in its beginnings, it has
provided signi®cant insights, as in accounting,
where terms are meaningless if isolated from
the speci®c accounting practices that sustain
them (Hopwood 1987; Munro and Mouritsen
44 Gherardi and Nicolini
1996; Power and Laughlin 1992). Other interest-
ing proposals relate to knowledge-®rms and the
production of speci®c technologies of power
that are used to control knowledge-workers
(Deetz 1996). Although there is no direct linkage
between those who produce the social object
`knowledge-®rm' by studying it and those who
investigate organizational learning and the
`learning organization', the two communities
of scholars closely resemble each other in the
social effects of their practices, effects that
deconstructionism can reveal.
In the postmodern approach the task of the
researcher is to deconstruct (Cooper 1989; Lin-
stead 1993) the so-called objects that are taken
to be objective and self-evident in organiza-
tional life. Organizational discourses do not
use language as the mirror of reality or of
mental states. Instead, language is ®gurative,
metaphorical, and fraught with contradictions,
opacities, and incoherencies (Cooper and
Burrell 1988). It is not universal but local; it is
precarious and fragmented (Linstead and
Grafton-Small 1990). Consequently, postmo-
dernism takes social constructionism one step
further: Language constitutes identity, that is,
the subject's position within a discursive prac-
tice. Rather than being focused on persons with
a unitary identity (the locus of will and self-
determination), postmodernism is a considera-
tion of the narratives of identity. Identity as a
human property and the foundation of subject-
ivity is one of the great narratives of modern-
ism. Its critique by postmodernism has
generated the concept of `identities' con-
structed by means of unstable and multiple
discourses (Czarniawska-Joerges 1995).
Whereas modernism views knowledge as a
collection of real entities located in people's
minds, with learning as the process of internal-
izing them and context as the container of
decontextualized knowledge, postmodernism
asserts that the boundary between culture and
the world has dissolved. The problem of decon-
textual and contextual knowledge is bound up
with the arguments between modernism and
postmodernism and with traditional cognitive
learning theory on the one hand and emergent
situated learning theory on the other (Fox
1997). Decontextualized knowledge is valued
because it is taken to represent the hidden
unity of the world. In cognitive theory the con-
text is conceived of as the container of decon-
textualized knowledge, and the interpretation
process is ultimately impersonal, detached,
and ahistorical. But if it is assumed that science,
too, is a cultural phenomenon and that inter-
pretation itself is a textually mediated process,
then one has to agree with Fox (1997), who
stated that `modernism, like science, hides or
represses the socially skilled craft work which
goes into producing the ``real'' with textual
materials and accounts' (p. 741).
Postmodernism is consistent with situated
learning theory's valorization of emergent
social contexts. Theory therefore becomes a
contextualized practice in which communities
of practitioners work to construct a `scienti®c
theory' or a body of knowledge out of textual
materials.
Within the postmodern tradition one may
say that organizational learning is viewed as a
discursive practice. Every discourse on organiza-
tional learning unfolds within a network of
knowledge/power relations that shapes the
subjectivity of those who participate as speak-
ers and those who are excluded and that sus-
tains concrete practices based on speci®c
technologies of power (Boje 1994). A subject
position incorporates both a conceptual reper-
toire and a location for persons within the
structure of the rights pertaining to those who
use this repertoire. A position is created in and
through conversations as speakers and listeners
construct themselves as persons: It creates a
location in which social relations and actions
are mediated by symbolic forms and modes of
being. Through practices of mutual account-
ability, speaking subjects not only make the
world more intelligible but also choose a dis-
cursive position for themselves and for others.
Because organizational learning is thus lo-
cated within the discursive practices of a scient-
i®c community, the researcher's concern is to
examine how this social object is formed and to
render this object of knowledge unstable,
incomplete, and always open to fresh inter-
pretations.
Sociology 45
The Metaphorical Nature of the
Concept `Organizational
Learning'
Accepting a postmodern stance, we ®nd that
the sociological contribution to the ®eld of
organizational learning is socially constructed
by eleven discursive positionings (or in Reed's
[1996:34] terminology, analytical narratives)
that stem from ®ve sociological traditions.
Researchers in this ®eld can choose different
ontological and epistemological positions and
thereby give different accounts of their object
of knowledge. Each account presupposes a nar-
rative capacity, an ability to narrate their
experience and that of others when making
sense of the world. Therefore, we resume our
analysis of the sociological contribution to the
study of organizational learning by examining
several narratives (see Table 2.1) that stem from
as many theoretical discourses and merge into
one conversation.
The conversation metaphor has been used
(Clegg and Hardy 1996b) to map the debate in
organization theory as `nothing less, nothing
more, nothing other than its practices of repre-
sentation' (p. 676). In conversations between
researcher and researched, both parties may
learn, and the aim of such conversations is to
open up multiple narratives with multiple
meanings, resist conventional narratives, and
avoid marginalizing narratives that do not con-
form to accepted wisdom. These conversations
are socially organized (in professions, academic
disciplines, and specialized journals), and they
organize a social process. No conversation is
more valid than any other, but all conversa-
tions offer opportunities for understanding
and action within different discursive prac-
tices, whether theoretical, practical, profes-
sional, or daily.
One discursive practice predominant in the
conversation about organization theory is the
narrative of organizational learning as learning
by an organization that, according to a more or
less cybernetic model, produces change, real or
potential, after a shift in the relationship
between thought, organizational action, and
environmental response (Tsang 1997). From
Table 2.1. Narratives of organizational learning according to five sociological traditions
Sociological traditions Narratives of organizational learning
The tradition of conflict .Organizational learning as the ideology of particular power groups
.Organizational learning as a policy of mobilizing resources of power
and conflict
.Organizational learning as an attempt to manage the tension
between substantial and formal rationality
The rational±utilitarian tradition .Organizational learning as a problem-driven search
.Organizational learning as the activation of an exchange network
.Organizational learning as an ecology of learning
The Durkheimian tradition .Organizational learning as a dependent variable
.Organizational learning as socialization to specific cultural codes
The microinteractionist tradition .Organizational learning as the transmission of knowledge within
occupational communities
.Organizational learning as a label producing and produced by a
socially constructed reality
The postmodern `tradition' .Organizational learning as a discursive practice
46 Gherardi and Nicolini
functionalism, which, according to Burrell and
Morgan (1979), is the dominant paradigm in the
sociology of the organization, organization
scholars have inherited a realistic postulate
(and a positivistic methodology) that concerns
both learning and the organization: Learning is
a `real' event that takes place in those `real'
places that are called organizations (and one
can measure learning). Both organizations
and learning are considered to be empirical
objects, and the organization came to be an-
thropomorphized as the subject of learning,
or, in order to avoid this dilemma, came to be
the container of individual and collective
learning.
By contrast, we argue that this `reality' results
from discursive practices based on the meta-
phorical use of a term, organizational learning,
which yields a particular account of organiza-
tions. Organizational learning is a metaphor
that encompasses two concepts, learning and
organization, and enables the exploration of
an organization as though it were a subject
that learns, processes information, re¯ects on
experiences, and possesses a stock of know-
ledge, skills, and expertise. This metaphor
opens the way for critical examination of the
relationship between organization and know-
ledge, between organization and the social
and cognitive processing of knowledge, and
between organizational action and organiza-
tional thought; it activates a `conversation'
that recognizes some aspects of the organiza-
tion and not others (Gherardi 1994,1996).
Metaphors can be a medium of important
elements of culture that `persuade us to see,
understand, and imagine situations in partial
ways' (Morgan 1997:348). Moreover, `metaphor
encourages us to think and act in new ways. It
extends horizons of insight and creates new
possibilities' (Morgan 1997:351). The assump-
tion that the concept organizational learning
is a metaphor implicitly allows one to start a
conversation about knowledge, knowing, and
learning in organizational processes.
The epistemological premises that allow this
transition from a realistic to a metaphorical
conception reside in the semantic shift from
the term `organization' to the term `organiz-
ing'. Organizing refers `to the embeddedness
of organizing within distinct local practices of
language, of culture, of ethnicity, of gender'
(Clegg and Hardy 1996a:4). Accordingly, we,
too, propose a semantic change. Instead of
`organizational learning', we explore the con-
cept of `learning-in-organizing'. This expres-
sion denotes a representational system, a way
of organizing a theoretical discourse on organ-
izing and organizations that eschews the
concept of organization as a uni®ed (and rei-
®ed) entity. The term, therefore, refers to a
social process inherent in the social construc-
tion of society and signi®es no recognition
of boundaries between one organization and
another or between an organization and its
environment. In the following sections we
argue that sociology has contributed two con-
cepts to learning-in-organizing: participation
and re¯exivity.
Learning-in-organizing and
Participation in a Practice
Sociologists approach learning not as some-
thing that takes place in the mind but as
something produced and reproduced in the
social relations of individuals when they parti-
cipate in society. `Learning is unhampered
participation in a meaningful situation', wrote
Illich (1971:65). Consequently, the various
forms assumed by individuals engaged in
goal-oriented activities are important for
understanding how people become members
of a community of practice and how they
come to master the speci®c knowledge
embedded in the various activities. Learning
and knowing may therefore be understood `as
competent participation in a practice' (Wenger
1998:137). The study of situated learning reveals
the intended uses of knowledge in situations
(Brown, Collins, and Duguid 1989).
The concept of learning through participa-
tion in a practice requires exploration of
practice as a concept because it is laden with
diverse traditions of thought: phenomeno-
logical, Marxist, and linguistic. These three
Sociology 47
traditions have been described (Ehn 1988)in
terms of practice-as-work (the transformation
of a given work process), practice-as-morality
(the politics and power of the different groups
or social classes involved in a given work pro-
cess), and practice-as-language (professional
language and interaction within a given work
process). We brie¯y recall them in this context
in order to illustrate how practice-based theor-
izing reshapes the concept of knowledge and
helps dissolve the arti®cial separation of levels
of learning based on the learning subject (the
individual, group, organization, and net-
works).
Heidegger (1962) and the phenomenological
school used the term Dasein to denote this
`being-in-the-world', whereby subject and ob-
ject are indistinguishable. Both subject and
object are part of a situation and exist in a social
and historical setting. An illuminating example
of the relationship between subject, object,
environment, and knowledge is found in
Winograd and Flores (1986), who used hammer-
ing as a paradigmatic instance of prere¯exive
learning, of comprehension that takes place in
situations of involvement in a practice when
subject and object are not separated. Consider a
carpenter hammering a nail into a piece of
wood. In terms of the carpenter's practical
activity, the hammer does not exist as an object
with given properties. It is as much a part of his
world as the arm with which he wields it. The
hammer belongs to the environment and can
be unthinkingly used by the carpenter. The
carpenter does not need to `think a hammer'
in order to drive in a nail. His capacity to act
depends on his familiarity with the act of ham-
mering. His use of the practical item `hammer'
constitutes its signi®cance to him in the setting
`hammering' and `carpentry'. When the car-
penter's hammering is unimpeded, the ham-
mer with its properties does not exist as an
entity. Only when some breakdown or situa-
tion of nonusability occurs will the carpenter's
activity of hammering become problematic.
The hammer exists as an entity when it no
longer works or is missing. That is to say,
when it becomes unusable. In the usable envir-
onment, the understanding of situations is a
prere¯exive activity. Re¯exive, investigative,
theoretical knowledge requires that something
that was previously usable now becomes un-
usable. The world of objects thus becomes `sim-
ply present' (vorhanden), no longer understood.
This breakdown occurs only when the carpen-
ter has already understood the hammer in
practice.
The concept of tacit knowledge is very close
to the phenomenological tradition. This af®n-
ity is what Polanyi (1962:105±6) meant when he
said that we know much more than we know
we know. He asked whether an analytical
description of how to keep one's balance on a
bicycle suf®ces as instruction to someone want-
ing to learn how to ride a bicycle? His answer:
`Rules of art can be useful, but they do not
determine the practice of an art; they are max-
ims, which can serve as a guide to an art only if
they can be integrated into the practical know-
ledge of the art. They cannot replace this
knowledge' (p. 50).
In order to convey what he meant by `tacit
knowledge' in the practice of skills, Polanyi
(1962) distinguished between two types of
awareness: focal and subsidiary:
When we use a hammer to drive in a nail, we attend
to both nail and hammer, but in a different way.We
watch the effect of our strokes on the nail and try to
wield the hammer so as to hit the nail most effect-
ively. When we bring down the hammer we do not
feel that its handle has struck our palm but that its
head has struck the nail. (p. 55; emphasis in the
original)
The focal awareness is on driving in the nail,
the subsidiary awareness is on what is felt on
the palm of the hand. The phenomenological
thinker pays close attention to these feelings
not because they are the object of one's atten-
tion but because they are the instruments of
that attention. The conclusion is that, in gen-
eral, people do not have focal awareness of the
instruments over which they have achieved
mastery. The implication for studying a prac-
tice is not how to make explicit what is tacit
knowledge but how to deal with what von Hip-
pel (1994) called `sticky information': all that is
unsayable and kept within the usable environ-
ment and the docile instruments in it.
48 Gherardi and Nicolini
To participate in a practice is to learn the
logic of that practice (what Bourdieu [1990]
called sens pratique as opposed to the logic of
discourse). Sens pratique is prere¯exive, unlike
the logic of discourse, which functions by mak-
ing the work of thought explicit in a linear
series of signs that the mind perceives as sim-
ultaneous instead. The logic of practice is
necessary for the order and continuity of an
organization because practical knowledge is
kept within the habitus, which produces his-
torical `anchors' and ensures the correctness of
practices and their constancy over time more
reliably than formal and explicit rules do (Bour-
dieu 1990).
In the phenomenological tradition, there-
fore, the concept of practice shows how com-
prehension in situations where one is `thrown
headlong into use' (Heidegger 1962:57) is prere-
¯exive and does not draw distinctions between
subject, object, thing, or environment. The
concept of practice also shows how re¯exive
understanding arises at moments of break-
down. It signi®es that organizations as systems
of practices exist in the world of tacit know-
ledge that is simply usable and that becomes
the object of re¯ection when a breakdown
occurs.
The phenomenological concept of practice
is, however, less well known than the Marxist
use of the term, which assigns to it an emancip-
ating force. Practice is a notion central to Marx-
ist epistemology, where it contrasts with the
Cartesian notion of detached re¯ection and
separation of mind and body and is at odds
with rationalism, positivism, and scientism.
Practice is an epistemological principle, and
activity theory (Engestrom 1987) draws on the
work of Vygotsky (1962,1978), Luria (1976), and
Leontyev (1981) from the Russian school of
social psychology in order to show how the
analysis of human activity must begin with
the study of material actions and contexts of
action. Human activity systems are distin-
guished from animal activity by the presence
of (a) manufactured objects and concepts that
mediate the interaction between individuals
and concepts; (b) traditions, rituals, and rules
that mediate the interaction between indi-
viduals and the community; and (c) the divi-
sion of labor that mediates the interaction
between the community and the actions of
its members. In rede®ning the study of work,
psychologists, sociologists, and cognitive
scientists are increasingly turning to an inter-
disciplinary approach to work as mindful pract-
ice (Engestrom and Middleton 1996). Analyzing
work as culturally mediated practice requires a
consideration of both the `mindfulness' of
human action (remembering, reasoning, see-
ing, learning, and inventing) and the social
relations and artifacts in which cognition and
communication are embedded.
In other words, the activity in which know-
ledge is developed and applied is not separable
from or ancillary to learning, and conceptual
knowledge shares signi®cant features with
tools. As Brown, Collins, and Duguid (1989)
explained: `they [tools] can only be fully under-
stood through use, and using them entails both
changing the user's view of the world and
adopting the belief system of the culture in
which they are used' (p. 33). This analogy
between knowledge and tools stresses the
materiality of knowledge and is also expressed
by Law's (1994) concept of relational material-
ism: `ordering has to do both with humans and
non-humans' (p. 24; emphasis in the original).
Practice is a system of activities in which
knowing is not separate from doing and situa-
tions might be said to coproduce knowledge
through activity (Blackler 1993; Hutchins 1993;
Resnik 1993; Rogoff and Lave 1984; Zuccherma-
glio 1996). If the old vocabulary of technology
as `designed', `implemented', and `impact pro-
ducing' is abandoned in favor of seeing techno-
logical systems as malleable artifacts, that is,
cultural objects leading to new routines despite
their initial purpose and design, then an inno-
vative arena for negotiating the materiality
of knowledge opens up. Take, for example,
computer-based information systems, which,
despite the characteristics usually attributed
to information technologies (standardization,
routinization of tasks, and centralization), are
open and dynamic artifacts (Ciborra and Lan-
zara 1990). Computer-based information sys-
tems are embodiments not just of data ¯ows
Sociology 49
and work routines but also of organizational
cultures and archetypes: `Computers are able
to interact with both the structural and institu-
tional arrangements associated with a given
division of labor and the assumptions, frames,
and mental images people have while enacting
and practicing routinely that division of labor'
(Ciborra and Lanzara 1990:149; emphasis in the
original). Technology, argued Latour (1991), is
society made durable.
Finally, language is a distinctive feature of
human activity systems, an observation that
brings us to Wittgenstein's notion of practice
as a linguistic game. Language is a social, not a
private, fact: Linguistic terms arise within a
social practice of constructing meaning. Parti-
cipation in a practice entails taking part in a
professional language game and mastering
and being able to use its rules. To have grasped
a concept means that one has learned to obey
the rules within a given practice. Those who
participate in the practice of a linguistic game
must share in the `life form' that makes that
practice possible: Intersubjective consensus is
more a matter of shared environment and lan-
guage than a lack of opinions (Wittgenstein
1953).
Sharing in a life form is the prerequisite for
understanding and transmitting so-called
procedural knowledge, the type of knowledge
acquired through the practical understanding
of an operation. For example, carpenters parti-
cipate in a professional language game, and
they are able to `articulate' the procedures that
they follow in making a chair. But this `know-
what' kind of knowledge that can be acquired
in this way is different from the practical under-
standing, the real operation, of making a chair.
The practical knowledge of how to make a chair
and how to describe this process is qualitatively
different from knowing how to use a carpen-
ter's plane or knowing when its blade needs
changing.
Some knowledge is transmitted through the
senses and stored in sensory maps (Gagliardi
1990) by virtue of one's familiarity with previous
situations and the re®nement of one's sensitiv-
ity. This type is the connoisseur's knowledge
(Turner 1988) and is possessed by individuals,
professional communities, and industries. The
manufacture of ¯utes is an example (Cook and
Yanow 1993). Knowing how to describe the
sound of a ¯ute is part of the practice of know-
ing how to identify a ¯ute from other ¯utes and
how to manufacture it. Practical understanding
(Strati 1986) is often inarticulate, aesthetic, and
tacit. In cases where this description of practi-
cal understanding applies to ¯ute-makers, its
pertinence does not stem from an inability to
talk about the range of sounds but to the ¯ute-
makers' capacity to talk about participating in
that language game and to the fact that this
knowledge requires the presence of the per-
son(s) possessing it. Whereas `objective' knowl-
edge is accessible through tangible artifacts
(e.g. books, ®lms), subjective knowledge is pos-
sessed by those who participate in a practice. It
is impossible to learn how to recognize the
sound of a ¯ute from other instruments solely
through books. It can only be learned by inter-
acting with other people who are skilled in the
activity.
In other words, learning-in-organizing is not
only a way to acquire knowledge in practice but
also a way to change or perpetuate such knowl-
edge and to produce and reproduce society. A
practice can be the hammering of a carpenter or
more complex practices such as organ trans-
plantation, bridge-building, or the execution
of a safety plan. If learning is understood as
participation in such practices, the arti®cial
separation of learning into levels (e.g. indivi-
dual, collective, organizational, interorganiza-
tional, institutional) dissolves because a
practice may cross all levels and link all relevant
knowing and knowledge. The empirical start-
ing point for practice as a framework is the
`logic of action' formulated and pursued by
social actors, and to accept this view of practice
is to reject the concept of organization as a
uni®ed entity (Reed 1992:115). The notion of
practice includes both the mental and the
material, the verbal and the nonverbal, the tex-
tual and the nontextual, and the human and
nonhuman as the instruments surrounding
everyone in everyday organizational life, as
the `missing masses' (Latour 1992) that are
meant whenever social actions are described.
50 Gherardi and Nicolini
Amid the diverse schools of thought about
organizational learning, the speci®c contribu-
tion that practice-based theory has made to the
analysis of the knowledge intrinsic in practice
can be summarized as follows:
1. Learning is acquired through particip-
ation in communities of practice (Brown and
Duguid 1991; Lave and Wenger 1991; Wenger
1998).
2. Organizing can be seen as an activity sys-
tem that reveals the tentative nature of know-
ledge and action (Blackler 1993,1995; Blackler,
Crump, and McDonald 1998). Incoherencies,
inconsistencies, paradoxes, and tensions are
integral to activity systems.
3. Knowledge and action are located in eco-
logies of sociomaterial relations (Fujimura 1995;
Star 1995).
4. Knowing is enacted (Weick 1979), situated
(Billett 1994; Suchman 1987), resilient but provi-
sional (Unger 1987), and public and rhetorical
(Vattimo 1985).
5. Practice involves the establishment of
alignments across human and nonhuman ele-
ments (Latour 1986; Law 1994) at particular posi-
tionings at a particular time within a network
of relations (Suchman 1998).
An emphasis on practice focuses the research
on organizational learning on the `doing' and
the materiality of social relations, detaching
it from idealist tradition and cognitive
approaches.
Learning-in-organizing and
Reflexivity
Learning-in-organizing can be de®ned as the
enactment of a practice-based knowledge and
its unfolding over time. Whereas in the pre-
vious section we stated that practice is both
the production of the world and the result of
this process, in this section we illustrate how
re¯exivity is the link between knowing in prac-
tice and knowing apractice. Learning a practice
means participating competently in the know-
ledge embedded in that practice (i.e. knowing
in practice); knowing a practice entails disem-
bedding knowledge through an act of re¯exive
logic. Re¯exivity betrays the logic of practice
because it inserts distance, re¯ection, and
separation of subject and object where there
had been no distinction between the subject
and the world because both were totally pre-
sent and caught up by the `matter at hand'. The
previous example of the carpenter hammering
a nail is an illustration of his `being in the
world' while absorbed by carpentry. And it is
also an illustration of what is meant by prere-
¯exivity in the phenomenological tradition.
Situated practices are both prere¯exive (i.e.
they depend on unstated assumptions and
shared knowledge for the mutual comprehen-
sibility of the participants) and re¯exively con-
stitutive of the situated members' contexts
from which they arise. Re¯exivity results from
the separation of or breakdown between sub-
ject and object and, for ethnomethodologists,
from the need for accountability, by which is
meant making the world comprehensible to
oneself and to the other members of a collec-
tivity: `Re¯exivity refers to the dynamic self-
organizational tendency of social interaction
to provide for its own constitution through
practices of accountability and scenic display'
(Flynn 1991:28).
Re¯exivity, therefore, is a characteristic of all
order-producing social activities. Moreover,
`the essential re¯exivity of accounts' (Gar®nkel
1967:67) is used to create a sense of orderliness
for action, but it re¯exively creates that self-
same context. The term `organizational learn-
ing' not only acquires meaning from the con-
text in which it appears but also re¯exively
creates that context.
Re¯exivity, individual and systemic, is there-
fore the process whereby the carpenter in the
previous section translates his or her practical
knowledge of hammering and carpentry into
explicit knowledge that can, for example, be
transmitted to an apprentice; codi®ed as stand-
ard operating routines, books, models, or
instruments; and used as a knowledge base for
innovation.
The concept of re¯exivity therefore com-
prises three elements: (a) self-monitoring as its
Sociology 51
cognitive element, which produces knowledge;
(b) accountability as its social element, which
creates a discursive order; and (c) institution-
alization as its normative element, which pro-
duces and reproduces the social institutions.
The term `institutional re¯exivity' (Giddens
1976:6,1990:12) refers to the fact that the insti-
tutional work of society reproduces the social
order that has produced its institutions. It does
so by means of a twofold hermeneutics, that is,
the constant reinterpretation of previous inter-
pretations.
Learning-in-organizing can only occur in
relation to re¯exivity, for re¯exivity enables
both cybernetic self-monitoring, the institutio-
nalization of knowledge, and hence change as
the result of a learning process. Both positions
are continuations of the Enlightenment tradi-
tion of modernity (Bauman 1992), and in Ger-
man sociology they are taken up, albeit with
different emphases, by Luhmann (1984), Haber-
mas (1975), and Beck (1992): Social change is a
learning process.
This conceptualization of re¯exivity in main-
ly cognitive terms differs from the notion of
aesthetic re¯exivity (Lash 1993,1994; Strati
1999), according to which re¯exivity does not
occur solely by virtue of cognitive categories
(self-monitoring) but involves hermeneutic
categories as well. That is to say, it is a process
of self-interpretation and aesthetic judgment
that involves the imagination and intuition
speci®cally.
Re¯exivity as a phenomenon typically tied to
modernity has given rise to an interesting
sociological debate (Beck, Giddens, and Lash
1994) that has engendered something akin to a
`third way' between modernism and postmo-
dernism: `re¯exive modernization'. Whether
modernity is over and done with or whether it
has entered a new phase, proponents of re¯ex-
ive modernization have asserted that `the more
societies are modernized, the more agents
acquire the ability to re¯ect on the social con-
ditions of their existence and to change them
in that way' (Beck 1994:174). Of course, what is
meant by re¯exivity, and what the subjects, the
medium, and the consequences of re¯exive
modernization are, change from one author to
the next. Be that as it may, the social construc-
tion of organizational learning by organiza-
tional scholars also contributes to the process
of re¯exive modernization and exempli®es
institutional re¯exivity.
In Giddens's terms (1994), institutional
re¯exivity means the dis-embedding and re-
embedding of industrial society's ways of life
by new ones under the general conditions of
the welfare state in a developed society based
on industrial labor. The subjects of re¯exive
modernization are organizations, institutions,
and individuals, and the medium is know-
ledge in its various forms: scienti®c knowledge,
expert knowledge, everyday knowledge. Re¯ex-
ive modernization is a theory of the ever-grow-
ing powers of social actors (agency) to shape
structure (Lash 1994). The re¯exive modernity
of the organizational learning approach lies in
its progressive liberation of the practice and
theory of organizing from the `cage' of order-
producing structure and contingency. The pur-
pose of that liberation is to create more space
for the organizational agency and its activity
of self-monitoring or self-interpreting uncer-
tainty and ambiguity.
We therefore conclude that the concept of
re¯exivity can make a twofold contribution to
the social foundation of learning. First, re¯ex-
ivity is a methodological guide for analyzing
how practical knowledge is communicated to
and institutionalized at all levels of society.
This knowledge is communicated and institu-
tionalized throughÐ
.the community of practice based upon it;
.the organizational subsystem where this
community interacts with other commu-
nities;
.the organization as a corporate actor that
possesses the power to legitimate some
forms of expert knowledge and discredit
others;
.the interorganizational network created by a
system of practices and within which they
circulate, by imitation, diffusion, or transla-
tion;
.varyingly institutionalized forms of know-
ledge reproduced by knowledge-brokering
52 Gherardi and Nicolini
organizations, such as training agencies, con-
sortia for certi®cation, and organizational
consultants; and
.the institutional environment that creates
the conditions for the reproduction (or
change) of knowledge institutionalized into
rules and regulations or granted to universi-
ties, national research institutes, and similar
institutions authorized to manage know-
ledge.
In this sense, institutional re¯exivity constitu-
tes the grounds for a rather different view of
learning than the one that underpins most of
the views of organizational learning shown in
Table 2.1. As Star (1995) argued, an alternative
view of cognition emphasizes the situated and
shared character of learning, the uncertain
and ¯uid boundaries of knowledge in formal
organizations, and the social and material prac-
tices that make up learning, knowledge, and
skills.
Second, the concept of re¯exivity enables a
community of practice (the organizational
learning scholars) to exert re¯exive control
over both the knowledge that it produces and
the social effects that arise from this production
in all their ambiguity. Learning, in fact, is a
term that is often part of a ®nal vocabulary, an
axiomatic value. The positive connotations
associated with the word induces the a priori
assumption of what needs to be empirically
demonstrated. Learning, as the founding
myth of the scienti®c community of scholars,
obscures the social construction of organiza-
tional practices that, inasmuch as they are
called `learning', produce learning (Nicolini
and Meznar 1995) in the form of discourses
that normalize and discipline the thought of
individuals. The exploitative ethos of many
discourses on organizational learning is part
of the theoretical construction of the ®eld as a
discourse of disciplining when such discourse is
preselected as a managerial technique biased
speci®cally toward systematic and purposeful
learning, improvement, and particular norms
(Gherardi 1999). These biases and othersÐ
toward individual action, environmental adap-
tation, or planned learning, for example (Huys-
man 1999)Ðconstitute a speci®c structuring of
power/knowledge that sustains and perpetu-
ates them as a discourse of power even though
other discursive positions are possible.
Conclusions
The speci®c disciplinary contribution of socio-
logy to the study of organizational learning lies
in its depiction of learning as a social process
involving social relations (shaped by social
institutions) and learning itself (a `cultural
object' created by artful practices of cultural
work). However, sociology is not a body of
incremental knowledge. Consequently, var-
ious sociological traditions have produced
many sociological discourses on learning (see
Table 2.1), which can be discerned in the
specialist and multidisciplinary ®eld of organ-
izational studies.
We have used an analytical approach that
ideally draws on a constructionist ontology.
Accordingly, we have argued that the notion
of organizational learning is like an open con-
versation and that we can contribute to this
conversation through two sociological con-
cepts: participation and re¯exivity.
The concept of participation directs the
attention of the scholar of organizational learn-
ing to the fact that learning is not an activity
distinct from other activities, organizational or
otherwise, but rather a part of becoming a
member of an organization and that it is intrin-
sic to the practices that sustain an organization.
The logic of practice does not draw a distinc-
tion between subject and object; instead, it
involves `knowing how to be competent' in a
usable environment. This concept therefore
invites the study of prere¯exive knowledge,
tacit knowledge, aesthetic understanding,
knowledge in actionÐin short, of what we
have called learning-in-organizing. By con-
trast, the concept of re¯exivity relates to a par-
ticular moment of separation between the
knowing subject and the object of its know-
ledge: the moment that produces the con-
ditions of the context. Re¯exivity directs
Sociology 53
organizational analysis to the processes of
knowledge institutionalization. It invites
investigation of the organizational network
engaged in the social process of extracting the-
oretical knowledge from practical knowledge
and then transforming it into the normative
knowledge that produces the operating condi-
tions of practical knowledge.
References
Alvesson, M. (1993). `Organization as Rhetoric: Knowledge-intensive Firms and the Struggle with
Ambiguity'. Journal of Management Studies, 30: 997±1016.
ÐÐ and Deetz, S. (1996). `Critical Theory and Postmodernism Approaches to Organizational
Studies', in S. R. Clegg, C. Hardy, and W. R. Nord (eds.), Handbook of Organization Studies.
London: Sage, 191±217.
Argyris, C. and SchoÈn, D. A. (1974). Theory in Practice: Increasing Professional Effectiveness. San
Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
ÐÐ ÐÐ (1978). Organizational Learning: A Theory of Action Perspective. Reading, Mass.: Addison-
Wesley.
Arujo, L. (1998). `Knowing and Learning as Networking'. Management Learning, 29: 317±36.
Astley, G. (1985). `Administrative Science as Socially Constructed Truth'. Administrative Science
Quarterly, 30: 497±513.
Barley, S. (1991). `Semiotics and the Study of Occupational and Organizational Cultures', in P. J.
Frost, L. F. Moore, M. R. Louis, C. C. Lundberg, and J. Martin (eds.), Reframing Organizational
Culture. Newbury Park, Calif.: Sage, 39±54.
Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an Ecology of Mind: A Revolutionary Approach to Man's Understanding of
Himself. New York: Ballantine Books.
Bauman, Z. (1992). Intimations of Postmodernity. London: Routledge.
Baumard, P. (1996). `Organizations in the Fog: An Investigation into the Dynamics of Knowledge',
in B. Moingeon and A. Edmondson (eds.), Organizational Learning and Competitive Advantage.
London: Sage, 74±91.
Beck, U. (1992). The Risk Society:Towards a New Modernity (M. Ritter, trans.). London: Sage.
(Original work published 1986)
ÐÐ (1994). `Self-dissolution and Self-endangerment of Industrial Society: What Does This Mean?'
in U. Beck, A. Giddens, and S. Lash (eds.), Reflexive Modernization. Cambridge: Polity Press,
174±83.
ÐÐ Giddens, A., and Lash, S. (1994). Reflexive Modernization. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Berger, P. L. and Luckmann, T. (1966). The Social Construction of Reality: ATreatise in the Sociology of
Knowledge. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
Bernstein, B. (1971±1975). Class, Codes, and Control (Vols. 1±3). London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Billett, S. (1994). `Situated Learning: A Workplace Experience'. Australian Journal of Adult and
Community Education, 34/2: 112±30.
Blackler, F. (1993). `Knowledge and the Theory of Organizations: Organizations as Activity Systems
and the Reframing of Management'. Journal of Management Studies, 30: 863±84.
ÐÐ (1995). `Knowledge, Knowledge Work and Organizations: An Overview and Interpretation'.
Organization Studies, 16: 1021±46.
ÐÐ Crump, N., and McDonald, S. (1998). `Managing Experts and Competing through Collabora-
tion: An Activity Theoretical Analysis'. Organization, 6: 5±31.
Blau, P. M. (1964). Exchange and Power in Social Life. New York: Wiley.
Blumer, H. (1969). Symbolic Interactionism. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Boje, D. M. (1994). `Organizational StorytellingÐThe Struggles of Premodern, Modern and Post-
modern Organizational Learning Discourses'. Management Learning, 25: 433±61.
Boland, R. and Tenkasi, R. (1995). `Perspective Making and Perspective Taking in Communities of
Knowing'. Organization Science, 6: 350±72.
54 Gherardi and Nicolini
Bourdieu, P. (1990). The Logic of Practice. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
Brown, J. S., Collins, A., and Duguid, P. (1989). `Situated Cognition and the Culture of Learning'.
Educational Researcher, 18/1: 32±42.
ÐÐ and Duguid, P. (1991). `Organizational Learning and Communities-of-Practice: Toward a
Unified View of Working, Learning, and Innovation'. Organization Science, 2: 40±57.
Bruner, J. (1990). Acts of Meaning. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Burrell, G. and Morgan, G. (1979). Sociological Paradigms and Organizational Analysis. Aldershot:
Gower.
Butera, F., Donati, E., and Cesaria, R. (1998). I lavoratori della conoscenza (Knowledge Workers).
Milan: Angeli.
Ciborra, C. U. and Lanzara, G. F. (1990). `Designing Dynamic Artifacts: Computer Systems as
Formative Contexts', in P. Gagliardi (ed.), Symbols and Artifacts: Views of the Corporate Landscape.
Berlin: de Gruyter, 147±65.
Clegg, S. R. (1990). Modern Organization: Organization Studies in the Postmodern World. London:
Sage.
ÐÐ (1995). `Of Values and Occasional Irony: Max Weber in the Context of the Sociology of
Organizations', in S. B. Bacharach, P. Gagliardi, and B. Mundell (eds.), Studies of Organizations
in the European Tradition. Greenwich, Conn.: JAI Press, 1±46.
ÐÐ and Hardy, C. (1996a). `Organizations, Organization and Organizing', in S. R. Clegg, C. Hardy,
and W. R. Nord (eds.), Handbook of Organization Studies. London: Sage, 1±28.
ÐÐ ÐÐ (1996b). `Representations', in S. R. Clegg, C. Hardy, and W. R. Nord (eds.), Handbook of
Organization Studies. London: Sage, 676±708.
Collins, R. (1979). The Credential Society: A Historical Sociology of Education and Stratification. New
York: Academic Press.
ÐÐ (1994). Four Sociological Traditions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cook, K. S., Emerson, R. M., Gillmore, M., and Yamagishi, I. (1983). `The Distribution of Power in
Exchange Networks'. American Journal of Sociology, 89: 275±305.
Cook, S. D. N. and Yanow, D. (1993). `Culture and Organizational Learning'. Journal of Manage-
ment Inquiry, 2: 373±90.
Cooley, C. H. (1964). Human Nature and the Social Order. New York: Shocken.
Cooper, R. (1989). `Modernism, Postmodernism and Organizational Analysis 3: The Contribution
of Jacques Derrida'. Organization Studies, 10: 479±502.
ÐÐ and Burrell, G. (1988). `Modernism, Postmodernism and Organizational Analysis: An Intro-
duction'. Organization Studies, 9: 91±112.
Coopey, J. (1995). `The Learning Organization: Power, Politics and Ideology'. Management Learn-
ing, 26: 193±214.
Crozier, M. (1963). Le Phe
Ânome
Áne bureaucratique. Paris: de Seuil.
Cyert, R. M. and March, J. G. (1963). A Behavioral Theory of the Firm. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice
Hall.
Czarniawska-Joerges, B. (1991). `Culture Is the Medium of Life', in P. J. Frost, L. F. Moore, M. R. Louis,
C. C. Lundberg, and J. Martin (eds.), Reframing Organizational Culture. Newbury Park, Calif.:
Sage, 285±97.
ÐÐ (1995). `Autobiographical Acts and Organizational Identities', in S. Linstead, B. Grafton-Small,
and P. Jefcutt (eds.), Understanding Managements. London: Sage, 157±71.
Dalton, M. (1959). Men Who Manage: Fusions of Feeling and Theory in Administration. New York:
Wiley.
Deetz, S. (1996). `Discursive Formations, Strategized Subordination, and Self-surveillance: An
Empirical Case', in A. McKinlay and K. Starkey (eds.), Managing Foucault: A Reader. London:
Sage, 157±71.
Derrida, J. (1971). L'E
Âcriture et la diffe
Ârence. Paris: de Seuil.
Dewey, J. (1922). Human Nature and Conduct. New York: Holt.
Douglas, M. (1970). Natural Symbols. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Duncan, R. and Weiss, A. (1979). `Organizational Learning: Implications for Organizational
Design', in B. M. Staw (ed.), Research in Organizational Behavior: An Annual Series of Analytical
Sociology 55
Essays and Critical Reviews (Vol. 1). Greenwich, Conn.: JAI Press, 75±123.
Durkheim, E. (1897). Le Suicide: E
Âtude de sociologie. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
ÐÐ (1912). Les Formes e
Âle
Âmentaires de la vie religieuse: Le Syste
Áme totemique en Australie. Paris:
Alcan.
Easterby-Smith, M., Snell, R., and Gherardi, S. (1998). `Organizational Learning and Learning
Organization: Diverging Communities of Practice?' Management Learning, 29: 259±72.
Ehn, P. (1988). Work-oriented Design of Computer Artifacts. Stockholm: Arbetlivscentrum.
Engestrom, Y. (1987). Learning by Expanding: An Activity Theoretical Approach to Developmental
Research. Helsinki: Orienta Konsultit.
ÐÐ and Middleton, D. (1996). Cognition and Communication at Work. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Etzioni, A. (1961). A Comparative Analysis of Complex Organizations. New York: Free Press of
Glencoe.
Fiol, C. M. and Lyles, M. A. (1985). `Organizational Learning'. Academy of Management Review, 10:
803±13.
Flynn, P. (1991). The Ethnomethodological Movement. New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Foucault, M. (1977). Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (A. Sheridan, trans.). New York:
Pantheon. (Original work published 1975)
ÐÐ (1980). Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972±1977 (C. Gordon,
trans.). New York: Pantheon.
ÐÐ (1988). `Technologies of the Self', in L. Martin, H. Gutman, P. Hutton (eds.), Technologies of the
Self: A Seminar with Michel Foucault. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 16±49.
Fox, S. (1997). `Situated Learning Theory versus Traditional Cognitive Learning Theory: Why
Management Education Should Not Ignore Management Learning'. Systems Practice, 10:
727±47.
Fujimura, J. (1995). `Ecologies of Action: Recombining Genes, Molecularizing Cancer, and Trans-
forming Biology', in S. L. Star (ed.), Ecologies of Knowledge. Albany: State University of New York
Press, 302±46.
Gagliardi, P. (1990). `Artifacts as Pathways and Remains of Organizational Life', in P. Gagliardi (ed.),
Symbols and Artifacts: Views of the Corporate Landscape. Berlin: de Gruyter, 3±37.
Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Gergen, K. (1992). `Organization Theory in the Postmodern Era', in M. Reed and M. Hughes (eds.),
Rethinking Organizations. London: Sage, 207±26.
Gherardi, S. (1990). Le microdecisioni nelle organizzazioni (Microdecisions in Organizations). Bolog-
na: Il Mulino.
ÐÐ (1994). `Imparare a decidere' (Learning for Decision-making), in D. Demetrio, D. Fabbri, and
S. Gherardi (eds.), Apprendere nelle organizzazioni. Rome: Nuova Italia Scientifica, 161±208.
ÐÐ (1996). `Organizational Learning', in M. Warner (ed.), International Encyclopedia of Business
and Management. London: Routledge, 3934±42.
ÐÐ (1999). `Learning as Problem-driven or Learning in the Face of Mystery?' Organization Studies,
20: 101±24.
ÐÐ Nicolini, D., and Odella, F. (1998a). `Toward a Social Understanding of How People Learn in
Organizations: The Notion of Situated Curriculum'. Management Learning, 29: 273±98.
ÐÐ ÐÐ ÐÐ (1998b). `What Do You Mean by Safety? Conflicting Perspectives on Accident
Causation and Safety Management Inside a Construction Firm'. Journal of Contingencies and
Crisis Management, 7/4: 202±13.
Giddens, A. (1976). New Rules of Sociological Method. London: Hutchinson.
ÐÐ (1990). The Consequences of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press.
ÐÐ (1994). `Living in a Post-traditional Society', in U. Beck, A. Giddens, and S. Lash (eds.), Reflexive
Modernization. Cambridge: Polity Press, 68±109.
Goffman, E. (1967). Interaction Ritual. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
ÐÐ (1971). Relations in Public. New York: Harper & Row.
Gouldner, A. W. (1954). Patterns of Industrial Bureaucracy: AStudy of Modern Factory Administration.
Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
56 Gherardi and Nicolini
Habermas, J. (1975). Legitimation Crisis (T. McCarthy, trans.). Boston: Beacon. (Original work
published 1973)
Hedberg, B. L. T. (1981). `How Organizations Learn and Unlearn', in P. C. Nystrom and
W. H. Starbuck (eds.), Handbook of Organizational Design: Vol. 1. Adapting Organizations to
Their Environments. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3±27.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1807). Die PhaÈnomenologie des Geistes. Bamberg: Goebhardt.
Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and Time (J. Macquire, trans.). New York: Harper & Row. (Original
work published 1927)
Homans, G. C. (1950). The Human Group. New York: Harcourt Brace.
ÐÐ (1961). Social Behavior: Its Elementary Forms. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Hopwood, A. (1987). `The Archeology of Accounting Systems'. Accounting, Organizations and
Society, 12: 207±34.
Hutchins, E. (1993). `Learning to Navigate', in S. Chaiklin and J. Lave (eds.), Understanding Practice:
Perspectives on Activity and Context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 35±63.
Huysman, M. (1999). `Balancing Biases: A Critical Review of the Literature on Organizational
Learning', in M. Easterby-Smith, L. Araujo, and J. Burgoyne (eds.), Organizational Learning and
the Learning Organization: Developments in Theory and Practice. London: Sage, 59±74.
Illich, I. (1971). Deschooling Society. London: Calder and Boyars.
Kunda, G. (1986). Engineering Culture: Control and Commitment in a High-tech Organization.
Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Lash, S. (1993). `Reflexive Modernization: The Aesthetic Dimension'. Theory, Culture and Society,
10: 1±23.
ÐÐ (1994). `Reflexivity and Its Doubles: Structure, Aesthetics, Community', in U. Beck, A. Gid-
dens, and S. Lash (eds.), Reflexive Modernization. Cambridge: Polity Press, 110±73.
Latour, B. (1986). `The Powers of Association', in J. Law (ed.), Power, Action and Belief: A New
Sociology of Knowledge? London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 264±80.
ÐÐ (1991). `Technology Is Society Made Durable', in J. Law (ed.), A Sociology of Monsters:Essays on
Power, Technology and Domination. London: Routledge, 103±31.
ÐÐ (1992). `Where Are the Missing Masses? The Sociology of a Few Mundane Artifacts', in
W. E. Bijker and J. Law (eds.), Shaping Technology/Building Society: Studies in Sociotechnical
Change. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 225±58.
Lave, J. and Wenger, E. (1991). Situated Learning: Legitimate Peripheral Participation. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Law, J. (1994). Organizing Modernity. Oxford: Blackwell.
Leontyev, A. N. (1981). Problems of the Development of the Mind. Moscow: Progress. (Original work
published 1959)
Levinthal, D. A. and March, J. G. (1993). `The Myopia of Learning'. Strategic Management Journal,
14 (Winter special issue): 95±112.
Levitt, B. and March, J. G. (1988). `Organizational Learning'. Annual Review of Sociology, 14:
319±40.
Linstead, S. (1993). `Deconstruction in the Study of Organizations', in J. Hassard and M. Parker
(eds.), Postmodernism and Organizations. London: Sage, 49±70.
ÐÐ (1994). `The Responsibilities of Betrayal: Deconstruction and Ethnographic Praxis'. Blurring
Genres, 6: 1±27.
ÐÐ and Grafton-Small, R. (1990). `Theory as Artifact: Artifact as Theory', in P. Gagliardi (ed.),
Symbols as Artifacts: Views of the Corporate Landscape. Berlin: de Gruyter, 387±420.
Luce, R. and Raiffa, H. (1957). Games and Decisions. New York: Wiley.
Luhmann, N. (1984). Soziale Systeme: Grundriû einer allgemeinen Theorie. Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp.
Luria, A. R. (1976). Cognitive Development: Its Cultural and Social Foundations. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
Lyotard, J. (1984). The Postmodern Condition. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Mannheim, K. (1935). Mensch und Gesellschaft im Zeiltalter des Umbaus. Leiden: Sijthoff's Vitge-
versmaatschappij.
Sociology 57
March, J. G. (1988). Decisions and Organizations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
ÐÐ (1996). `Exploration and Exploitation in Organizational Learning', in M. D. Cohen and
L. S. Sproull (eds.), Organizational Learning. Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage, 101±23.
ÐÐ and Olsen, J. P. (1976). `Organizational Choice Under Ambiguity', in J. G. March and J. P. Olsen,
Ambiguity and Choice in Organizations. Bergen: Universitetsforlaget, 10±23.
Mauss, M. (1968). êuvres. Paris: edition de Minuit.
Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, Self, and Society: From the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Merton, R. K. (1957). Social Theory and Social Structure. New York: Free Press.
Michels, R. (1911). Zur Soziologie des Parteiwesens in der modernen Demokratie: Untersuchungen
u
Èber die oligarchischen Tendenzen des Gruppenlebens. Leipzig: Werner Klinkhardt.
Morgan, G. (1997). Images of Organization (2nd edn). Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage.
Munro, R. and Mouritsen, J. (1996). Accountability: Power, Ethos and the Technologies of Managing.
London: Thomson Business Press.
Nelson, R. R. (1991). `Why Do Firms Differ, and How Does It Matter?' Strategic Management Journal,
12 (Winter special issue): 61±74.
Nicolini, D. and Meznar, M. B. (1995). `The Social Construction of Organizational Learning'.
Human Relations, 48: 727±46.
Nonaka, I. and Takeuchi, H. (1995). The Knowledge-creating Company: How Japanese Companies
Create the Dynamics of Innovation. New York: Oxford University Press.
Olson, M. (1965). The Logic of Collective Action. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Orr, J. (1993). `Sharing Knowledge, Celebrating Identity: War Stories and Community Memory
among Service Technicians', in D. S. Middleton and D. Edwards (eds.), Collective Remembering:
Memory in Society. Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage, 169±89.
Ouchi, W. and Wilkins, A. (1985). `Organizational Culture'. Annual Review of Sociology, 11: 457±83.
Parsons, T. (1951). Toward a General Theory of Action. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, C. (1931±1935). Collected Papers. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Perrow, C. (1991). `A Society of Organizations'. Theory and Society, 20: 725±62.
Polanyi, M. (1962). Personal Knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. (Original work
published 1958)
Power, M. and Laughlin, R. (1992). `Critical Theory and Accounting', in M. Alvesson and H. Willmott
(eds.), Critical Management Studies. London: Sage, 113±35.
Presthus, R. (1978). The Organizational Society. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Reed, M. (1992). The Sociology of Organizations. Hemel Hempstead: Harvester.
ÐÐ (1996). `Organizational Theorizing: A Historically Contested Terrain', in S. R. Clegg, C. Hardy,
and W. R. Nord (eds.), Handbook of Organization Studies. London: Sage, 31±56.
Resnick, L. B. (1993). `Shared Cognition: Thinking as a Social Practice', in L. Resnick, J. Levine, and
S. D. Teasley (eds.), Perspectives on Socially Shared Cognition. Washington, DC: American Psy-
chological Association, 57±73.
Rogoff, B. and Lave, J. (eds.) (1984). Everyday Cognition: Its Development in Social Context. Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Schutz, A. (1971). Collected Papers. The Hague: Nijhoff.
Selznick, P. (1949). TVA and the Grass Roots: A Study in the Sociology of Formal Organization.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Simon, H. A. (1957). Administrative Behavior: A Study of Decision-making Processes in Administrative
Organization (2nd edn). New York: Free Press.
Sims, D. (1999). `Learning as the Development of Stories', in M. Easterby-Smith, L. Araujo, and
J. Burgoyne (eds.), Organizational Learning and the Learning Organization: Developments in
Theory and Practice. London: Sage, 44±58.
Snell, R. and Chak, A. M. (1998). `The Learning Organization: Learning and Empowerment for
Whom?' Management Learning, 29: 337±64.
Spender, J. C. (1996a). `Competitive Advantage from Tacit Knowledge? Unpacking the Concept
and Its Strategic Implications', in B. Moingeon and A. Edmondson (eds.), Organizational Learning
and Competitive Advantage. London: Sage, 56±73.
58 Gherardi and Nicolini
ÐÐ (1996b). `Organizational Knowledge, Learning, and Memory: Three Concepts in Search of a
Theory'. Journal of Organizational Change Management, 9/1: 63±78.
Star, S. L. (1995). Ecologies of Knowledge. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Starbuck, W. H. (1983). `Organizations as Action Generators'. American Sociological Review, 48:
91±102.
ÐÐ (1992). `Learning by Knowledge-intensive Firms'. Journal of Management Studies, 29: 713±40.
Strati, A. (1986). `Lavoro e Simbolismo Organizzativo' (Work and Organizational Symbolism). Studi
Organizzativi, 17/2±3: 65±85.
ÐÐ (1999). Organization and Aesthetics. London: Sage.
Stucky, S. (1995). `Technology in Support of Organizational Learning', in C. Zucchermaglio,
S. Bagnara, and S. Stucky (eds.), Organizational Learning and Technological Change. New York:
Springer, 4±15.
Suchman, L. (1987). Plans and Situated Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
ÐÐ (1998). Organizing Alignment: A Case of Bridge-building. Paper presented at The Academy of
Management Annual Meeting, San Diego, Calif., Symposium on `Situated Learning, Local
Knowledge, and Action: Social Approaches to the Study of Knowing in Organizations', 10±12
August.
Thomas, W. (1928). The Child in America. New York: Knopf.
Tomassini, M. (1993). Alla ricerca dell'organizzazione che apprende (In Search of the Learning
Organization). Rome: Edizioni Lavoro.
Townley, B. (1993). `Foucault, Power/Knowledge, and Its Relevance for Human Resource Manage-
ment'. Academy of Management Review, 18: 518±45.
Tsang, E. W. K. (1997). `Organizational Learning and the Learning Organization: A Dichotomy
between Descriptive and Prescriptive Research'. Human Relations, 50: 73±89.
Tsoukas, H. (1992). `Ways of SeeingÐTopographic and Network Representations in Organization
Theory'. Systems Practice, 5: 441±56.
ÐÐ (1996). `The Firm as a Distributed Knowledge System: A Constructionist Approach'. Strategic
Management Journal, 17 (Winter special issue): 11±25.
Turner, B. (1988). `Connoisseurship in the Study of Organizational Cultures', in A. Bryman (ed.),
Doing Research in Organization. London: Routledge and Kegal Paul, 108±22.
Unger, R. (1987). False Necessity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
van Maanen, J. and Barley, S. R. (1984). `Occupational Communities: Culture and Control in
Organizations', in B. M. Staw and L. L. Cummings (eds.), Research in Organizational Behavior:
An Annual Series of Analytical Essays and Critical Reviews (Vol. 6). Greenwich, Conn.: JAI Press,
287±366.
Vattimo, G. (1985). Fine della modernita
Á(The End of Modernity). Milan: Garzanti.
von Hippel, E. (1994). ` ``Sticky Information'' and the Locus of Problem Solving: Implications for
Innovation'. Management Science, 40: 429±39.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1962). Thought and Language. New York: Wiley.
ÐÐ (1978). Mind in Society. London: Harvard.
Warglien, M. (1990). Innovazione e impresa evolutiva: Processi di scoperta e apprendimento in un
sistema di routines (Innovation and the Evolutionary Firm: Discovery and Learning in a Routine
System). Venice: Cedam.
Weber, M. (1978). Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology (2 vols., E. Fischoff,
H. Gerth, A. M. Henderson, F. Kolegar, C. W. Mills, T. Parsons, M. Rheinstein, G. Roth, E. Shils, and
C. Wittich, trans.). G. Roth and C. Wittich (eds.). Berkeley: University of California Press. (Original
work published 1922)
Weick, K. E. (1979). The Social Psychology of Organizing (2nd edn). Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley.
ÐÐ (1991). `The Nontraditional Quality of Organizational Learning'. Organization Science,2:
116±24.
ÐÐ and Westley, F. (1996). `Organizational Learning: Affirming An Oxymoron', in S. R. Clegg,
C. Hardy, and W. R. Nord (eds.), Handbook of Organization Studies. London: Sage, 440±58.
Wenger, E. (1998). Communities of Practice: Learning, Meaning and Identity.Cambrid ge: Cambridge
University Press.
Sociology 59
Winograd, T. and Flores, F. (1986). Understanding Computers and Cognition: A New Foundation for
Design. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.
Zuboff, S. (1988). In the Age of the Smart Machine: The Future of Work and Power. New York: Basic
Books.
Zucchermaglio, C. (1995). `Organization and Cognitive Design of (Technological) Learning Envir-
onment', in C. Zucchermaglio, S. Bagnara, and S. Stucky (eds.), Organizational Learning and
Technological Change. New York: Springer, 61±74.
ÐÐ (1996). Vygotskij in Azienda (Vygotskij in the Workplace). Rome: La Nuova Italia Scientifica.
60 Gherardi and Nicolini
... Organizational learning advances ingenious and enterprising efforts and leads to exceptional service improvements, transforming cognitive resources into an asset for sustaining existing practices (Garvin et al., 2008). Intraorganizational knowledge exchange and the transfer of tacit knowledge, such as skills and expertise, increase innovative capacity and enable the accumulation, learning, processing, and stocking of key information (Gherardi and Nicolini, 2017). ...
... Organizational learning advances ingenious and enterprising efforts and leads to exceptional service improvements, transforming cognitive resources into an asset for sustaining existing practices (Garvin et al., 2008). Intraorganizational knowledge exchange and the transfer of tacit knowledge, such as skills and expertise, increase innovative capacity and enable the accumulation, learning, processing, and stocking of key information (Gherardi and Nicolini, 2017). Treasuring cognitive capital is fundamental for achieving sustainable economic performance, as valuable expertise and know-how build up enterprise resilience and act as a buffer in case of adversity (Bratianu, 2015). ...
Article
Full-text available
In today's rapidly evolving business landscape, organizational change has emerged as a crucial aspect of contemporary business strategies. The capacity to adapt is vital for organizations to maintain their competitive edge and stay relevant. However, executing change can be challenging, and the success of change initiatives largely hinges on an organization's readiness to change and learn. Organizational readiness to change has been extensively researched in management and organizational studies. This research paper delves into organizational readiness to change and learn, scrutinizing its influence on change initiatives and emphasizing the key trends and developments in this area between 2012 and 2021. The paper presents an in-depth SciVal analysis of the growth and scholarly output in the domains of learning organizations, organizational performance, and personnel over this period. The study identifies the most pertinent keyphrases, leading institutions, countries/regions, and Scopus sources contributing to the field.
... A sociedade transformou-se e o contexto educativo tem testemunhado as alterações e a divergência sobre a temática de entender a aprendizagem por observação ou imitação no cotidiano escolar é pouco discutida e até mesmo naturalizada no processo de ensino e aprendizagem. Na Teoria da Aprendizagem Social, desenvolvimento e aprendizagem são processos inseparáveis (Gherardi;Nicolini, 2003, p.35). ...
Article
O artigo salienta que muitos são os desafios na área educacional que o professor enfrenta, referente a alunos com dificuldade de aprendizagem e que a aprendizagem por observação pode emergir como uma estratégia para ajudar na aprendizagem. Segundo Bandura (1969), o conhecimento de processo por modelação proporciona que os indivíduos efetuem mudanças pessoais, organizacionais e sociais. É notório, que o número de alunos que sentem dificuldades em aprender tem aumentado consideravelmente, o que leva a muitos deles, a perderem o interesse pela escola, criando um clima de insegurança e a perda da autoestima. O fracasso escolar afeta o aprender do sujeito em suas manifestações sem chegar a aprisionar a inteligência: muitas vezes surge do choque entre o aprendente e a instituição educativa que funciona de forma segregadora. Segundo Fernández (1990), as dificuldades de aprendizagem são “fraturas” no processo de aprendizagem, onde estão em jogo o organismo, o corpo, a inteligência e o desejo.
... Enquanto uma vertente de aprendizagem sociológica, os EBPs desenvolvem um olhar reflexivo sobre o organizar e aprender, enquanto estes acontecem com/nas práticas (Gherardi & Nicolini, 2001;Pagani, 2021). O aprendizado reside na participação e interação dos indivíduos em seu meio social (Avila & Aantonello, 2016;Gherardi, 2012), ou seja, o saber na prática revela-se no campo das práticas, cujo "contexto no qual a atividade concreta de produção e uso do conhecimento torna-se visível e observável, assim como descritível" (Gherardi, 2006, p. XVI). ...
Article
Full-text available
Este estudo propõe o uso da lente teórico-metodológica das práticas como uma maneira (alternativa) de aprofundar e explorar as compreensões sobre os processos de aprendizagem em Novas Formas Organizacionais (NFO). A lente da prática amplia o entendimento da aprendizagem em NFO através de um olhar processual e relacional, explorado neste ensaio a partir da perspectiva de Gherardi, Nicolini, Strati e Latour. Trata-se de entender o conhecimento como um constante acontecendo, onde o saber éinerente à ação e, portanto, temporário, produzido, reproduzido e transformado a cada prática. A prática oferece uma alternativa ontoepistemológica que permite explorar o saber-fazer na tecitura de práticas produzidas pelos atores, fruto do nexo de relações e ações em fluxo. O uso da prática para compreender a aprendizagem em formas organizacionais que fogem do mainstream dos negócios, mostra-se possível através da compreensão de organização enquanto organizing, entendendo que estruturas surgem das relações, e como tal, e à medida que surge, também se desmantelam, trazendo assim a ideia de fluxo e ponto para dentro dos estudos organizacionais. Diferente das lentes teóricas marcadas pela ortodoxia sistêmica, a perspectiva da prática permite acessar nuances impulsionadoras dos processos de aprendizagem em coletivos constituídos pelas NFOs, deslocando o foco do ‘‘por quê’’ para o ‘‘como’’ as relações se agregam e produzem conhecimento. Os Estudos Baseados em Prática fornecem um olhar às subjetividades da vida organizacional, apoiando a gestão de NFO a partir do entendimento que a estrutura surge das relações e se molda pelas que nelas se estabelecem.
... While psychological approaches are better known and have founded, for better or worse, the interpretative model of organizational learning (see the critique of Weick, 1991; and Chapter 1 in this Handbook) sociological perspectives have been slower to establish themselves. The sociological contribution to the study of organizational learning (Gherardi and Nicolini, 2001) can be summarized in the terms of an invitation to view organizational learning from a cultural perspective as a metaphor (derived from the juxtaposition of the two terms 'learning' and 'organization') that makes it possible to develop a system of representation (a theory) with which to interpret organizing as if it were a learning process. Therefore, identifi able within studies on organizational learning are various narratives concerning what constitutes that relationship and how it can be understood. ...
Chapter
Full-text available
In an era of far-reaching changes, issues of Organizational Learning are high on the agenda of social scientists, managers and consultants worldwide as they seek to adapt to new environments. The Handbook of Organizational Learning and Knowledge provides a comprehensive overview of how the concept of Organizational Learning emerged, how it has been used and debated, and where it may be going. It summarizes the state of the art and provides a full account of the diverse approaches, themes, issues, and debates of the field. The handbook unites a distinguished team of international authors, who examine both the central themes and emerging issues. The coverage extends beyond the American tradition to include the experiences of Europe, Asia and the Middle East. The book opens with chapters drawing insights from various social science approaches. The following Sections examine fundamental issues concerning the external triggers, factors and conditions, agents, and processes of Organizational Learning. Subsequent chapters review the subject within a global context, looking in particular at inter-organizational collaboration. The next sections examine the development of learning practices and provides case studies to illustrate Organizational Learning and knowledge creation. The book concludes with an analysis of the state of the art and an agenda for the future. This handbook will be an invaluable reference tool for scholars and students in the social sciences, as well as for professionals involved in organizational development, learning, and change.
... This material world is also part of creating solidifying and reifying memories helpful for making sense of who and where we are in the world (Latour, 2007). In situated learning theory, reification is essential for knowing and being (Gherardi & Nicolini, 2001;Jørgensen & Keller, 2008;Lave & Wenger, 1991;Wenger, 1998). Technologies are therefore more durable than living stories. ...
Book
Organizational storytelling has been taught for many years in many different places as part of organizational development, organizational change, organizational learning, and business ethics. There has not been any comprehensive framework that addresses sustainability in organizations and so this book develops a new ethics of sustainability for management and organizations. A terrestrial ethics of storymaking is proposed, which responds to Latour’s claim that the Terrestrial has become a new decisive political actor in politics. The Terrestrial is born from Gaia, a metaphor for a new look on life on Earth. Gaia situates life in the thin layer of matter that is the surface of the Earth. It entails the view that nature is a process that humans are part of. Storymaking is constructed from Arendt’s political philosophy, which is rooted ontologically in the principle of natality: rebirth of life. The term ‘storymaking’ is developed from Arendt’s understanding of storytelling as political action to emphasize not only that stories are spatial, embodied and material practices that are tied to a specific time and space but also that technology is an important dimension in making stories. Stories are thus human practices that apart from meaning making and politics involve the use and manipulation of material and objects, and which are crucial for how a human world is shaped. This human world is furthermore shaped by the rhythms of life embedded in the complex landscapes that humans move through. Storymaking is developed through rethinking the links between the central categories of labor, work, action, and thinking in Arendt’s writings. Implications for business ethics are drawn out and a comprehensive ethics framework is constructed that connects the biological and physical with the social, economic, and political regarding how organizations work. Finally, a storymaking philosophy of management is constructed, making this book especially relevant to researchers, academics, managers, and students in the fields of business ethics, management studies, leadership, organizational studies, and international business.
... Sob este ponto de vista, o conhecimento pode ser entendido como a manifestação dos sistemas de linguagem, tecnologias, colaboração e conflito, localizados no espaço e no tempo, em um contexto particular que é socialmente construído (FLACH et al., 2010). O conhecimento ocorre por processos de negociação de identidades e relações de poder, abrangendo a transmissão de artefatos físicos, comportamentais e verbais (GHERARDI et al., 2001). ...
Article
Full-text available
A aprendizagem organizacional vem se consolidando como fundamental para responder as mudanças vivenciadas pelas organizações. Esta pesquisa, de natureza teórico-empírica, discute o processo de aprendizagem organizacional em momentos de crise. O estudo tem como base as principais teorias sobre o processo de aprendizagem individual e organizacional. Os resultados apontam a aprendizagem organizacional como um fenômeno complexo e demonstra que para a superação das crises organizacionais não há um caminho exclusivamente traçado. É necessária uma sólida formação técnica e teórica e ações que depreendem da empiria e da compreensão do ambiente, associada à aprendizagem contínua, a inovação e a capacidade prototipar, experimentar, realizar correções rápidas, improvisar e melhorar continuamente o sistema para que se torne cada vez mais adaptável e flexível.
... Learning improves the integration process of the interaction between the individual and his environment (Doornbos et al., 2004). Work place is considered as a social field (Gherardi & Nicolini, 2001) and a place for learning (Ashton, 2004). ...
Article
Full-text available
Learning is a new paradigm that is introduced in today's organizations. The purpose of this study is to determine learning contingency model from the mistakes using TOPSIS. Variables were identified using the Delphi technique. The samples of this study were consisted 30 public administrators in Iran. The results show which factors have the greatest impact and which causes the least impact on learning from mistakes in public sector of Iran.
... A racionalidade da prática é guiada pelo entrelaçamento entre seres humanos e objetos, reforçando um estar-no-mundo, ou seja, a sociomaterialidade do mundo (Pimentel & Nogueira, 2018), ao explorar o processo por meio do qual identidades, artefatos, ideologias, regras, linguagem, moralidade e interesses são tecidos juntos e afetam uns aos outros no processo de aprendizagem coletiva (Gherardi & Nicolini, 2001). A prática aciona as faculdades sensoriais de modo diferente de uma pessoa para outra, produzindo uma compreensão da experiência sensível (Strati, 2007), cujo conhecimento reside na participação e na interação dos indivíduos, em seu meio social, como seres organizacionais (Gherardi, 2012b). ...
Article
Full-text available
Este estudo tem como objetivo compreender como a prática do trabalho coletivo da reciclagem é apreendida, produzida e reproduzida, a partir de um estudo de caso em uma associação de reciclagem. A elaboração dos dados empíricos tomou por base o método de zoom in e zoom out, operacionalizado por meio de técnicas etnográficas. A análise foi desenvolvida por meio de análise textual e uso de templates. Os dados revelam que os praticantes ressignificam a prática do trabalho coletivo da reciclagem mediante negociação e reflexividade, suspendendo o fluxo da ação anterior e legitimando um novo repertório de construções normativas, reconhecidas conjuntamente. Concluiu-se que o modo de organização e aprendizagem dos recicladores propicia, ao longo do tempo, a construção e a reconstrução de práticas produzidas nas interações entre sujeitos, conhecimento e materialidade, fazendo com que a prática do trabalho coletivo da reciclagem mantenha-se em refinamento constante. Estes achados, especialmente no tocante ao trabalho coletivo, revelam nuances sobre o processo de organizing e learning, incentivando gestores a superar, por meio da aprendizagem pela prática, desafios advindos de projetos sociais.
Article
Full-text available
O ensaio discute a relevância crítica da alfabetização financeira nas organizações, salientando como a carência de aptidão financeira tem consequências como endividamento e stress, que repercutem na produtividade laboral. Palavras Chave Alfabetização financeira , Bem-estar financeiro, Organização que Aprende
Chapter
This chapter offers the key theoretical concepts that provide the basis of this book. I start by providing the conceptualization of legitimacy and organizational legitimacy and offering an excursus of the theoretical contributions of recent decades. I then link legitimacy with organizational sustainability and organizational change. Subsequently, I explain the concept of organizational learning and illustrate the transition from organizational learning to learning organizations. The chapter then focuses on value co-creation theory and its evolution in the academic debate, and introduces some models of value co-creation processes as well as the emerging “circular co-creation processes”. In each paragraph, I advance the main research gaps emerging from the extant literature, while in the last paragraph, I specifically highlight those gaps addressed in this book.