ArticlePDF Available

Automorphisms, Mahlo cardinals and NFU

Authors:

Abstract

This paper shows that there is a surprising connection between Mahlo cardinals of finite order and fixed-points of automorphisms of models of set theory; a connection that also sheds light on the metamathematics of the Quine-Jensen system NFU of set theory.
Automorphisms, Mahlo Cardinals, and NFU
Ali Enayat
Abstract. In what follows, ZF (L) is the natural extension of Zermelo-Fraenkel
set theory ZF in the language L={∈,C}, GW is the axiom “Cis a global
well-ordering”, and Φ := {ϕn:nω}, where ϕnasserts the existence of a
Σn-reflecting n-Mahlo cardinal. Our principal results are Theorem A, and its
“reversal” Theorem B below.
Theorem A. Suppose Tis a consistent completion of ZF C + Φ.There is
a model Mof T+Z F (L) + GW such that Mhas a proper elementary end
extension Nthat possesses an automorphism jwhose fixed point set is M.
Theorem B. There is a weak fragment Wof Zermelo-set theory plus GW
such that if some model N= (N, N,CN)of Whas an automorphism whose
fixed point set Mforms a proper C-initial segment of N,then
MZF (L) + GW + Φ,
where Mis the submodel of Nwhose universe is M.
We also explain how Theorems A and B can be used to fine tune the work
of Solovay and Holmes concerning the relationship between Mahlo cardinals
and the extension N F UA of the Quine-Jensen system NF U.
Department of Mathematics and Statistics, American University, Washington,
DC, 20016-8050
1. INTRODUCTION AND PRELIMINARIES
In this paper we establish an intimate relationship between Mahlo cardinals
and automorphisms of models of set theory. The models of set theory involved
here are not well-founded since a routine argument by transfinite induction reveals
that a well-founded model satisfying the extensionality axiom only admits the triv-
ial automorphism. The source of our inspiration was Solovay’s calibration of the
consistency strength of the unorthodox system of set theory N F U A, but our re-
sults can also be motivated in an orthodox fashion by comparing the behavior of
automorphisms of models of Z F C (Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of
choice), with those of ZF C ’s sister theory P A (Peano Arithmetic). Our point of
departure in this comparative context is Gaifman’s seminal work [G] on the model
theory of P A. Gaifman refined the MacDowell-Specker method [MS] of building
elementary end extensions by introducing the powerful machinery of minimal end
extension types, which can be used to produce a variety of models of P A with spe-
cial properties. In particular, one can use minimal end extension types to establish
that every model M= (M , +,·)of P A has a proper elementary end extension N
1
2 ALI ENAYAT
that possesses an automorphism jwhose fixed point set is precisely M(as observed
by Kossak, this is a corollary of [G, Theorems 4.9, 4.10 and 4.11]). Therefore,
Theorem 1.1. Every consistent completion of P A has a model Nthat possesses
a nontrivial automorphism whose fixed point set is a proper initial segment of N.
A natural question is whether there is an analogue of Theorem 1.1 for ZF C .
We answer this question by showing, in Theorem A (Section 3) and Theorem B
(Section 4), that such an analogue exists precisely for consistent completions of the
theory ZF C + Φ, where
Φ := {∃κ(κis n-Mahlo and Vκis a Σn-elementary submodel of V) : nω}.
(intuitively, Φ says that the class of ordinals behaves like an ω-Mahlo cardinal).
The prehistory of the scheme Φ goes back to the groundbreaking work of Schmerl
and Shelah [SS] on the Hanf-number computation of power-like models in terms of
Mahlo cardinals, but Φ itself was first explicitly introduced and studied by Kauf-
mann [Ka] and the author [E-1, 2] in the context of identifying the right “comple-
tion” of ZF C which resembles P A from the point of view of model theory. For
example, every consistent completion of ZF C + Φ has a κ-like model for any un-
countable cardinal κ([Kau, Theorem 3.10], [E-1, Theorem 3.8]). Moreover, if 2
has the tree property, then every 2-like model of ZF C already satisfies Φ [E-3,
Theorem 4.8]. By [E-1, Remark 1.6] there is no analogue of minimal end exten-
sion types for models of Z F C in any finite alphabet extending {∈},but our work
here shows that, in contrast, there is such an analogue for the enriched theory
ZF C (L) + Φ(L), where Lis an expansion of {∈} by infinitely many predicates.
This provides further a posteriori evidence for the maxim:
ZF C + Φ imitates P A, vis-`a-vis model theory.
In Section 5 we use the results obtained about automorphisms of models of Z F C
to gain insight into models of the set theoretical system N F UA (an extension of the
Quine-Jensen system N F U of set theory). In particular, Theorems A and B allow
us to pinpoint the first order theories of the so-called Cantorian initial segments
CZ Aof Zermelian structures ZAarising from models Aof N F U A, which in turn
lead to a new proof of the following result:
Theorem 1.2.1(Solovay, 1995) The following theories are equiconsistent:
T1:= ZF C +{“there is an n-Mahlo cardinal”:nω},
T2:= N F U A.
There is also an arithmetical counterpart to our set theoretical story. Recent
work of Solovay and the author has revealed a close relationship between classical
arithmetical theories (ranging from a fragment of P A to second order arithmetic)
and natural extensions of the theory obtained by adding the negation of the axiom
of infinity to N F U. The picture that emerges from this work shows that N F U
provides a robust framework for the formulation of elegant theories whose consis-
tency strength varies from the tangible territory of the fragment I-∆0+Exp of
P A, all the way up to the heights of systems of set theory with large cardinals. In
light of these developments, the Quine-Jensen paradigm emerges as a fascinating
1This result is announced (without proof ) in Solovay’s online manuscript [So].
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 3
foundational alternative that not only offers a coherent rival account of set theory2,
but also unifies seemingly unrelated systems of classical arithmetic and set theory.
I am grateful to Robert Solovay for pointing the way in [So], enduring my
rough drafts, and providing precious advice. I am also indebted to Randall Holmes
for helpful discussions about N F U , and to the anonymous referee for suggested
improvements.
Preliminaries: Theories and Models
A. Theories
For a relational language L, Σn(L),Πn(L), and ∆n(L) are sets of first
order formulas built up from Lthat (respectively) belong to the Σn-level,
Πn-level, and ∆n-level of the well-known L´evy hierarchy. We use Σ(L)
for S
nω
Σn(L).
For a class Γ of formulas, Γ-Separation consists of formulas of the form
abx(xbxaϕ(x)),
for all formulas ϕΓ in which bdoes not occur free.
For a class Γ of formulas, Γ-Replacement consists of formulas of the form
[xa!(x, y)] [by(yb↔ ∃xaϕ(x, y ))],
for all formulas ϕΓ in which bdoes not occur free.
ZF (L) is Z F augmented by Σ(L)-Replacement, where L ⊇ {∈}.
ES T (L) [Elementary Set Theory] is obtained from the usual axiomati-
zation of ZF C (L) by deleting Power Set and Σ(L)-Replacement, and
adding ∆0(L)-Separation. More explicitly, it consists of Extensional-
ity, Foundation (every nonempty set has an -minimal member), Pairs,
Union, Infinity, Choice, and ∆0(L)-Separation. The theory K P + Infin-
ity (where KP is Kripke-Platek set theory as in [Bar]) is a significantly
stronger theory than ES T {∈} since KP includes Σ-Foundation, and
0-Replacement.
GW [Global Well-ordering] is the axiom in the language L={∈,C},
expressing “Cwell-orders the universe”. More explicitly, GW is the con-
junction of the axioms “Cis a total order” and “every nonempty set has
aC-least element”. A well-known forcing argument shows that every
countable model of ZF C expands to a model of Z F {∈,C}+GW (see,
e.g. [Fe]).
GW is the strengthening of GW obtained by adding the following two
axioms to GW :
(a) xy(xyxCy);
(b) xyz(zyzCx).
It is easy to see that every model of Z F ({∈,C}) + GW (C) can be ex-
panded to a model of Z F ({∈,J}) + GW (J) since the desired ordering
Jsatisfying GW is defined by:
xJy[(xCyand ρ(x) = ρ(y)) or ρ(x)ρ(y)],
2Rosser’s classic text [Ro] offers a development of mathematics within NF . See also Forster’s
[Fo] and Holmes’s [Ho-1] for samples of recent work in this area.
4 ALI ENAYAT
where ρis the usual ordinal-valued rank function. However, over weaker
set theories GW might be stronger than GW . Also, note that if αis an
admissible ordinal, or a limit of admissible ordinals, and Lαis the α-th
level of the constructible hierarchy, then by Σ1-reflection [Bar, Theorem
4.3],
(Lα,, <Lα)ES T ({∈,C}) + GW ,
where <Lαis G¨odel’s canonical well-ordering of Lα.
For a finite relational language L, Φ(L) is the scheme {ϕn(L) : nω},
where ϕn(L) is the formula expressing:
κ(κ is n-Mahlo and (Vκ,,···)Σn(L)(V,,···).
GBC is the G¨odel-Bernays theory3of classes GB with the class form of
the axiom of choice.
B. Models
Models of set theory are of the form M= (M, E, ···) and N= (N , F, ···),
where E=M, and F=N.
Mis a submodel of N, written MN,if MNand E=FM2.
For M= (M, E , ···), and aM, aE={bM:bEa}.
Nend extends M(equivalently: Mis an initial submodel of N), written
MeN,if Mis a submodel of Nand for every aM, aE=aF.
We abbreviate “elementary end extension” by “e.e.e.”. It is well-known
that if Nis an e.e.e. of a model Mof Z F , then Nis a rank extension of
M, i.e., whenever aMand bN\M, then Nρ(a)ρ(b).
Nis said to be a conservative extension of M, if MNand for all
parametrically definable subsets Xof N,XMis definable in M. For
MeNZF, this is equivalent to saying that for all cN\M, cFM
is parametrically definable in M.
Suppose L ⊇ {∈} is a relational language. Given structures Mand Nof
the same language L,MΣn(L)Nmeans that Mis a Σn(L)-elementary
submodel of N,i.e., every formula of Σn(L) is absolute in the passage
between Mand N.For finite L, Σn(L)-truth is Σn(L)-definable within
ZF (L) for n1 [J, Section 14]. Therefore, for every finite language
L, and every natural number nthere is a single L-formula ϕn(x) such
that for all models Mof Z F (L), and all αOrdM,Mϕ(α) iff
(Vα,,···)MΣn(L)M.
Models of GB can be written in the two-sorted form (M,A), where Mis a
model of Z F , and Ais a family of subsets of M. Since coding of sequences
is available in GB, we shall use expressions such as “f∈ A”, where fis
a function, as a substitute for the precise but lengthier expression “the
canonical code of fis in A”. S∈ A is said to form a proper class if there
is no cMsuch that cE=S, else Sis said to form a set. It is well-known
that for A⊆P(M),and MZF , (M,A)GB iff (M, S )S∈A ZF (L),
where L={∈} ∪ {S:S∈ A}.
3We have followed Mostowski’s lead in our adoption of the appellation GB, but Jech’s text
[Jec] dubs this theory BG. To make matters more confusing, the same theory is also known in
the literature as V NB (von Neumann-Bernays) and N B G (von Neumann-Bernays-G¨odel).
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 5
2. THE STRENGTH OF “ORD IS WEAKLY COMPACT”
In this section we probe the strength of the assertion “Ord is weakly compact”
within GBC. Here “Ord is weakly compact” is the statement in class theory as-
serting that every Ord-tree has a branch4.Ord-trees are defined in analogy with
the familiar notion of κ-trees in infinite combinatorics: (τ , <τ) is an Ord-tree, if
(τ, <τ) is a well-founded tree of height Ord such that the collection of nodes of
any prescribed ordinal rank form a set. The principal results of this section are
Theorems 2.1 and 2.2. Theorem 2.1 reveals an unexpected equivalence between the
class theory GBC+ “Ord is weakly compact” and the set theory Z F C + Φ, which
can be paraphrased as:
Φ/ZF C Ord is weakly compact”/GBC.
Theorem 2.2, on the other hand, establishes a combinatorial theorem that plays a
vital role in the proof of Theorem A.
It is a classical theorem of ZF C set theory that if κis a weakly compact
cardinal, then κis κ-Mahlo. In contrast, Corollary 2.1.1 of Theorem 2.1 implies
that the set theoretical consequences of GBC + “Ord is weakly compact” are
precisely the same as those of ZF C + Φ. Consequently, even though the theory
GBC + “Ord is weakly compact” can prove the family of statements of the form
Ord is n-Mahlo” for standard natural numbers n, it is unable to prove “Ord is
ω-Mahlo”. To see this, note that
GBC + “Ord is ω-M ahlo`Z F C + Φ is finitely satisfiable”.
Therefore, since Corollary 2.1.1 is a theorem of P A,
GBC + “Ord is ω-M ahlo`Con(GBC + “Ord is weakly compact”).
So, by G¨odel’s second incompleteness theorem,
GBC + “Ord is weakly compact” 0Ord is ω-Mahlo”.
Theorem 2.1.
1. If (M,A)GBC + “Ord is weakly compact”, then MZF C + Φ.
2. Every consistent completion of Z F C + Φ has a countable model that has an
expansion to a model of GBC + “Ord is weakly compact”.
Before proceeding with the proof of Theorem 2.1, let us derive two corollaries.
Corollary 2.1.1. The following are equivalent for a sentence ψin the language of
set theory:
1. ZF C + Φ `ϕ.
2. GBC + “Ord is weakly compact `ψV.
Proof .This is an immediate consequence of coupling Theorem 2.1 with the
completeness theorem for first order logic.
4The discriminating reader might prefer “Ord has the tree property” to express this property.
But all is well, since one can use the methods of this section to show that within GBC the statement
“Every Ord-tree has a branch” is equivalent to the statement “If Tis a proper class of sentences
in the infinitary logic L,(allowing less than Ord-many conjunctions and strings of quantifiers)
every subset of which has a model, then Thas a model”.
6 ALI ENAYAT
Corollary 2.1.2. Suppose GBC + “Ord is weakly compact is consistent. If ψis
a sentence in the language of set theory satisfying either
1. ZF `ψholds in L”, or
2. ZF C `for some poset P, 1Pψ,
then there is a model of GBC + “Ord is weakly compact ” + ψV.
Proof .This follows from Corollary 2.1.1 and the observation that if Msatisfies
ZF C + Φ,then (1) Φ holds in the constructible universe LMof M, and (2) Φ holds
in every P-generic extension of M, where PM. (1) is easy to verify. (2) is a
consequence of the preservation of both (a) the n-Mahlo property of a cardinal κ,
and (b) the property “VκΣnV”, in P-generic extensions satisfying PVκ. (a)
is established along the lines of the proof of [Kan, Proposition 10.13]; (b) follows
from a standard forcing argument.
The proof of part (1) of Theorem 2.1 is based on the methods introduced in [E-
2, E-3]. Notice that the proof would have been routine if GBC were to be replaced
by the stronger theory KM C (Kelley-Morse theory of classes with global choice),
since the usual ZF C -proof establishing the κ-Mahlo property of a weakly compact
cardinal κcan be conveniently implemented within KM C. We need the following
refinement of the KM C-proof, tailor made for GBC .
Lemma 2.1.2. Suppose (M,A)is a model of GBC + “Ord is weakly compact
and S∈ A.For every natural number n,there is a Σn-e.e.e. (N, S)of (M, S)
such that OrdN\Mhas a minimum element, and {cFM:cN} ⊆ A, where
F=N.
Proof .By global choice, there is some C∈ A such that (M , C)GW. Given
any S∈ A, (M, f, S)Z F ({∈,C, S}),and therefore, as shown in [E-3, Section 3],
for every natural number nthere is a tree τnsuch that (i) through (iii) below hold:
(i) τnis definable in (M,C, S);
(ii) (M,C, S)τnis an Ord-tree”;
(iii) If τnhas a branch B, then there is a model (N, S), and an embedding
j: (M, S)(N, S ),
where both (N, S) and jare definable within (M,C, S, B),such that
(M,C, S, B)j(M, S ) is a Σn-elementary initial segment of (N, S)”.
(i) through (iii) together imply that for every natural number n,
(iv) (M,A)“(M, S) has a Σn-e.e.e. (N, S )”.
It remains to show that (N, S) can be arranged to have a least new ordinal.
This is a consequence of the following result, which can be established by adapting
the proof of [Kau-2, Lemma 3.2] or [E-2, Theorem 3.3] to the present setting.
Proposition 2.1.3. Suppose Mis a model of ZF C (L)for a finite relational
language Lsuch that for some nω,there is a model Nsuch that
(1) Me,Σn+2(L)N,and
(2) for every parametrically N-definable subset Xof N,
(M, X M)ZF (L∪{S}),
where Sis a unary predicate interpreted by XM.There is a submodel N0of N
such that Me,Σn(L)N0and OrdN0\Mhas a least element.
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 7
Proof of part 1 of Theorem 2.1. We are now in a position to verify that if
(M,A) is a model of GBC + “Ord is weakly compact”, then Msatisfies Φ. We
shall use an external induction to show that for each standard natural number n,
if Nis a Σ1-e.e.e. of Msatisfying
(z){cFM:cN}⊆A,where F=N,
and γ= min(OrdN\M), then γis n-Mahlo in N.Coupled with Lemma 2.1.2, this
shows that Φ holds in M. Suppose Nis a Σ1-e.e.e. of Msatisfying (z) with a
least new ordinal γ. The case n= 0 follows from the simple observation that γ
cannot be singular in Nbecause any potential singularizing map in Nis already in
Aby (z), and GB rules out such an entity. Moreover, γmust be a strong limit
cardinal because if λ < γ then (2λ)M= (2λ)Nsince “xis the power set of y” is a
Π1-predicate and, of course, (2λ)Mis a member of Mand therefore is less than γ.
Now assume the inductive hypothesis for some nω, and assume on the contrary
that γis not (n+ 1)-Mahlo in N. Let Cbe a closed unbounded subset of γall of
whose members fail to be n-Mahlo. Since C∈ A by (z), we can use Lemma 2.1.2
to get hold of a Σ1-e.e.e. (M, C) of (M, C ) with a least new ordinal γ.Since
(M, C) satisfies the Σ0-statement
Cis closed and no member of Cis an n-Mahlo cardinal”,
(M, C) satisfies the same sentence. But then we have a contradiction because
on one hand γCsince Cis closed, thus implying that γis not n-Mahlo
in the eyes of M, and on the other hand γis n-Mahlo in Mby our inductive
hypothesis. Therefore γmust be (n+ 1)-Mahlo in N.
Proof of part 2 of Theorem 2.1. We use the strategy of Schmerl and Shelah
[SS] of building models with “built-in” e.e.e.’s using Mahlo cardinals of finite order.
Let Tbe a consistent completion of ZF C + Φ.We wish to describe a theory T
extending Tin a new language L ⊇ {∈,C}with the following two key properties:
()ZF (L) + GW T.
(∗∗) Every model Mof Thas a conservative e.e.e..
Note that if Mis a model of Tand Ais the family of M-definable subsets of M, then
by () (M,A) is a model of GBC. Moreover, it is easy to see5that (∗∗) implies that
(M,A) satisfies “Ord is weakly compact”. Therefore, to prove part (2) of Theorem
2.1 it is sufficient to construct a consistent extension Tof Tsatisfying properties
()and (∗∗)above. This will be accomplished in Lemmas 2.1.4 and 2.1.5.
The language Lis obtained by enriching {∈} with a binary relation symbol C,
and two sets {Sn:nω}and {Un:nω}of unary predicates.
Let L0:= {∈,C}, and Ln+1 := L0∪ {Si:in+ 1}∪{Ui:in+ 1}.
The desired theory Tis Taugmented with 4 sets of axioms A1through A4in the
extended language L, as described below:
• A1:= ZF (L) + GW (C).
5See the proof of (3) (1) of Lemma 3.3 for more detail.
8 ALI ENAYAT
• A2:= {σn:nω},where σnasserts that Sn+1 is a satisfaction predicate
over (V,,C, Si, Ui)in. More specifically, σnsays that Sn+1 contains the
Σ0(Ln)-theory of (V,,C, Si, Ui)in, and Sn+1 satisfies Tarski’s inductive
truth clauses.
• A3:= {ψn:nω},where ψnasserts that Un+1 is a class of ordinal codes
of unary formulas that describe a nonprincipal Ord-complete ultrafilter
over subsets of Ord that are definable in
(V,,C, Si, Ui)in.
Note that by GW (C) there is a definable bijection between the universe
and the class of ordinals, and therefore, every object can be canonically
coded by an ordinal. Also note that to formulate ψnwe need to use the
predicate Sn+1 to express definability within (V,, Si, Ui)in.Finally, we
point out that the Ord-complete condition of Un+1 can be expressed in
one sentence asserting
pτ(x, c)κqUn+1 ⇒ ∃α < κ pτ(x, c) = αqUn+1 ,
where τis a definable term of Ln, c is a parameter in V,κis a cardinal,
and ϕ7→ pϕqis a canonical coding of formulas by ordinals.
• A4:= {UnUn+1 :nω}.
The following proposition is essentially due to Schmerl and Shelah [SS] and is
our main tool in the construction of a model of T . First we need a definition:
Suppose A= (A, ···) and B= (B , · · ·) are models in common language,
and AB.Ais relatively saturated in B, written ARS B,if for every
XAwith |X|<|A|, every 1-type over Xrealized in Bis already
realized in A, i.e., for every bB, there is some aAsuch that
(A, x, a)xX(B, x, b)xX.
Proposition .Suppose θis an (n+ 1)-Mahlo cardinal for some nω, and for
some kω,PiVθfor i < k. There is an n-Mahlo cardinal γ < θ such that
(Vγ,, PiVγ)i<k RS (Vθ,, Pi)i<k.
Proof .Let C1:= {α < θ : (Vα,, PiVα)i<k (Vθ,, Pi)i<k }.C1is a closed
subset of θby Tarski’s elementary chain theorem, and it is unbounded in θby a
Skolem hull argument. Since (Vθ,)Z F ,
()αC1|Vα|=iα=α.
Let C2be the subset of C1consisting of elements αC1satisfying:
γ < α aVθbVα(Vθ, x, a)xVγ(Vθ, x, b)xVγ.
Note that if γC2is an inaccessible cardinal, then
(Vγ,, PiVγ)i<k RS (Vθ,, Pi)i<k.
So the proof would be complete once we verify that C2is a closed unbounded subset
of θ. It is clear that C2is a closed subset of θ. To see that it is also unbounded,
suppose α < θ. Using the inaccessibility of θwe can define a sequence hαn:nωi
of elements of C1such that the following two conditions are satisfied for every
nω:
(1) α < αn< αn+1 < θ;
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 9
(2) Every 1-type realized in (Vθ,, Pi, x)i<k,xVαnis realized already by an element
in Vαn+1 .
Let δ:= S
nω
αn.Clearly δ > α and δC2because of (1), (2) and ().
Lemma 2.1.4. Thas a model.
Proof .Since Φ T , by the compactness theorem there is a model Mof T
containing a nonstandard element HωM, and some θ0OrdMsuch that
VM
θ0Mand Mθ0is (H+ 1)-Mahlo”.
Fix rMsuch that Mrwell-orders Vθ0”. Since θis an inaccessible cardinal
of M,
(Vθ0,, r)MZ F (L0) + GW (C).
Reasoning within M, we plan to construct a strictly decreasing sequence hθj:j < Hi
of elements of OrdM, and two sequences of elements hsj:j < Hiand huj:j < Hi
of Mto construct the sequence of models hAj:j < H isuch that j < H P (j)
holds in M,where
P(j) := “For all Lj-sentences ϕT , Ajϕ”, and
Aj:= (Vθj,, rj, si, ui)ij, where uiand sirespectively interpreteUiand
Si,and rj:= rVθjinterprets C.
Note that Tis a recursive theory and therefore we can meaningfully speak about T
in M(with the proviso that TMcontains formulas of infinite length and properly
extends T). The following recursive construction of length Hshould be understood
to take place within M.
To begin with, let s0=u0=.Note that P(0) holds. By Proposition we can
choose an H-Mahlo cardinal θ1< θ0,such that:
(1) (Vθ1,, r1)(Vθ0,, r).
(note: for this step, we do not require relative saturation). Let s1θ1code the
satisfaction predicate for (Vθ1,, r1), and let U1be the ultrafilter on the paramet-
rically (Vθ1,, r1)-definable subsets of θ1that is generated by α0:= θ1θ0,i.e., if
Yθ1is definable in (Vθ1,, r1) by a formula ϕ(x),then
Y∈ U1iff (Vθ0,, r)ϕ(α0).
Let u1θ1code U1. Note that P(1) holds. The next step of the construction is
more subtle. By Proposition , there is some (H1)-Mahlo cardinal θ2< θ1such
that:
(2) (Vθ2,, r2, s1θ2, u1θ2)RS A1:= (Vθ1,, r1, s1, u1).
Let s2θ2code the satisfaction predicate for (Vθ2,, r2, s1θ2, u1θ2). We wish
to extend the ultrafilter coded by u1θ2to an ultrafilter U2on the family of all
subsets Yof θ2that are definable in the model (Vθ2,, r2, s1θ2, u1θ2) such
that P(2) holds. By (2) there is some α1θ1such that α0and α1have the same
L1-type in A1over Vθ2.Therefore, we can use α1to define the desired U2extending
U θj+1 via
Y∈ U2iff (Vθ1,, r1, s1, u1)ϕ(α1),
where ϕdefines Yin (Vθ2,, r2, s1θ2, u1θ2). It is clear that if u2θ2codes U2,
then P(2) holds. Since θ0was chosen to be (H+ 1)-Mahlo, thanks to Proposition
10 ALI ENAYAT
this process can be continued a total of Hsteps to produce sequences hθj:j < H i,
hαj:j < H i,hsj:j < Hiand huj:j < H isuch that for all j < H the following
hold in M:
(a) θj+1 is (Hj)-Mahlo and αj+1 θj+1;
(b) αjand αj+1 have the same Lj+1-type in Aj+1 over Vθj+2;
(c) uj+1 θj+1 codes the ultrafilter generated by αj;
(d) sj+1 θj+1 codes the satisfaction predicate for (Vθj+1 ,, rj+1, si, ui)ij+1.
This makes it evident that Mj < H P (j). The desired model of Tis
(VθK,)M, rK, si, uii<ω ,
where K < H is any nonstandard element of ωM.
Lemma 2.1.5. Every model Mof Thas a conservative e.e.e. .
Proof .Suppose M= (M, E , ···) is a model of T. Let
U:= [
nω
(Un)E.
By design, Ucodes an OrdM-complete nonprincipal ultrafilter Uover the Boolean
algebra of subsets of OrdMthat are parametrically definable in M. Let Nbe the
definable ultrapower6of Mmodulo U. Usual arguments show that Nis an e.e.e.
of M. Moreover Nis a conservative extension of Msince any cNis of the form
[τ]Ufor some Ln-term τ, and therefore
cFM={mM:M{αOrd :mτ(α)} ∈ Un}.
A Canonical Partition Relation
We close this section by discussing an important combinatorial principle that
will be used in the proof of Theorem A.
For a natural number n1, let Ord (Ord)nbe the statement in class
theory asserting that for every f: [Ord]n→ {0,1}there is a proper class
HOrd such that fis constant on [H]n.
Given f: [Ord]nOrd, and HOrd, H is f-canonical if there is some
S⊆ {1,···, n}such that for all sequences α1<·· · < αn, and β1<·· · < βn
of elements of H,
f(α1,···, αn) = f(β1,···, βn)⇔ ∀iS(αi=βi).
Note that if S=, then fis constant on [H]n, and if S={1,···, n},then
fis injective on [H]n.
Ord → ∗(Ord)nis the statement in class theory asserting that for every
f: [Ord]nOrd there is some proper class HOrd such that His
f-canonical.
It is a theorem of ZF C [Bau, Theorem 2] that if κis a weakly compact cardinal
then κ→ ∗(κ)nholds for all n<ω. This is based on Baumgartner’s observation
that the proof of the Erd¨os-Rado canonical partition theorem [ER] for 0 (0)n
shows that κ→ ∗(κ)nfollows from κ(κ)2n.
6See the proof of part of Lemma 3.3 for more detail on the construction of such ultrapowers.
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 11
Theorem 2.2.
1. nω,GBC + “Ord is weakly compact” `Ord (Ord)n.
2. nω,GBC + “Ord is weakly compact” `Ord → ∗(Ord)n.
Proof .The usual ramification tree proof from Z F C establishing the partition
properties of weakly compact cardinals (as in [Kan, Theorem 7.8]) works in the
GBC context to prove (1) as well, by an external induction on n. (2) is a corollary
of (1), and the fact that the aforementioned Erd¨os-Rado ZF C proof of κ→ ∗(κ)n
from κ(κ)2ncan be conveniently implemented in the GBC context to establish
GBC +Ord (Ord)2n`Ord (Ord)n.
Remark 2.2.1. If GBC is replaced by KM C (Kelley-Morse theory of classes with
global choice), then in both parts of Theorem 2.2 “nω” can be moved to the
right hand side of the provability symbol `.
3. AUTOMORPHISMS FROM MAHLO CARDINALS
The main result of this section is Theorem A, which is the analogue of Theorem
1.1 for ZF C + Φ.In the next section we shall prove a “reversal” of Theorem A by
showing that over the weak fragment EST ({∈,C}) + GW the assumption that T
contains ZF C + Φ is indeed necessary.
Theorem A. Suppose Tis a consistent completion of Z F C+ Φ.There is a model
Mof T+ZF (C) + GW such that Mhas a proper e.e.e. Nthat possesses an
automorphism whose fixed point set is M.
The proof of Theorem A is presented at the end of the present section, once
the machinery of generic ultrafilters and iterated ultrapowers are put into place.
However, we can describe the high-level strategy of the proof here: Mis the {∈
,C}-reduct of the model of GBC + “Ord is weakly compact” whose existence is
certified by part (2) of Theorem 2.1; Nis the Z-iterated ultrapower of Mmodulo a
“generic ultrafilter” (where Zis the linearly ordered set of integers); and the desired
automorphism of Nis induced by the automorphism n7→ n+ 1 of Z.
For a countable model (M,A) of GBC, let Bbe the Boolean algebra
{S∈ A :SOrdM}.
Our first goal is to construct ultrafilters Uover Bwith certain combinatorial prop-
erties that yield desirable structural properties of U-based ultrapowers. We shall
employ the conceptual framework of forcing in order to efficiently present the nec-
essary bookkeeping arguments. Our notion of forcing is the poset P, where
P:= {SB:Sis unbounded in OrdM},
ordered under inclusion.
A subset Dof Pis dense if for every XPthere is some Y∈ D with
YX.
U Pis a filter if it satisfies (1) /U; (2) Uis closed under intersections;
and (3) Uis upward closed.
A filter U Pis P-generic over (M,A) if U ∩ D 6=whenever Dis a
dense subset of Pthat is parametrically definable in (M,A).
12 ALI ENAYAT
A filter U Pis (M,A)-complete if for every f:OrdMκ, where
κOrdMand f∈ A,there is some H∈ U such that fis constant on U.
Note that if a filter U Pis (M,A)-complete, then Uis a nonprincipal ultrafilter
on Bsince for each YB,the characteristic function of Yis constant on some
member of U. We therefore refer to (M,A)-complete filters as ultrafilters.
Let Γ be a canonical bijection between OrdM×OrdMand OrdM. Every
g:OrdM→ {0,1}codes a sequence DSg
α:αOrdMEof subsets of
OrdM, where Sg
α:= {βOrdM:g(Γ(α, β)) = 1}.
A filter U Pis (M,A)-iterable7if Uis (M,A)-complete, and for every
g∈ A and g:OrdM→ {0,1},{αOrd :Sg
α∈U}∈A.
A filter U Pis (M,A)-canonically Ramsey if for every
f: [OrdM]nOrdM,
where nis a standard natural number, and f∈ A, f is canonical on some
H∈ U, i.e., there is some S⊆ {1,· · ·, n}such that for all sequences
α1<···< αn, and β1<···< βnof elements of H,
f(α1,···, αn) = f(β1,···, βn)⇔ ∀iS(αi=βi).
The usual proof establishing the existence of filters meeting countably many dense
sets shows:
Proposition 3.1. If (M,A)is a countable model of GBC,then there is a generic
filter Uover (M,A).
The following result reveals the key properties of generic ultrafilters.
Theorem 3.2. If (M,A)is a model of GBC + “Ord is weakly compact and U
is (M,A)-generic, then
1. Uis (M,A)-complete;
2. Uis (M,A)-iterable;
3. Uis (M,A)-canonically Ramsey.
Proof .(1): Given f∈ A with f:OrdMκ, and κOrdM, let
Df
1:= {YP:fYis constant}.
Df
1is dense since OrdMbehaves like a regular cardinal in models (M,A) of GBC.
(2): For Xand Yin B, let us write XY(read “Xis almost contained in
Y”) if X\Yis bounded in OrdM(equivalently: X\Yis a set in M). Also, let “X
decides Y” abbreviate
XYor XOrdM\Y.
For each g:OrdM→ {0,1}, with g∈ A, let
Dg
2:= {YP:αOrdMYdecides Sg
α}.
7This notion of iterability is related to, but different from, its namesake in the theory of large
cardinals used in [Kan, p.249]. In the present context iterability provides a useful combinatorial
condition for the ultrapower construction to be iterated, using finite supports, along any linearly
ordered set. Our iterable ultrafilters are precisely the analogues of Kunen’s “M-ultrafilters” (as
in [Ku], or [Jec]) for models of GBC .
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 13
We observe that if every Dg
2is dense, then (2) holds. To show the density of
Dg
2suppose XP. We first claim that there is an A-coded sequence F=
DFα:αOrdMEsatisfying the following two properties:
()αOrdMFα=Sg
αXor Fα=X\Sg
α;
(∗∗)αOrdMT
δ<α
Fδis unbounded in X.
Argue within (M,A).For each s:α→ {0,1},define hFs
δ:δ < αiby:
Fs
δ:= Sg
δX, if s(δ) = 1;
X\Sg
δ,if s(δ)=0.
Consider the subtree τof 2<Ord consisting of function s:α→ {0,1}such that
\
δ<α
Fs
δis unbounded in X.
It is easy to see that τhas nodes of every rank αOrd,because each level of τgives
rise to a partition of Xinto 2|α|pieces, and so by Power Set and Replacement, one
of the pieces must be a proper class since Xitself is a proper class. By weak com-
pactness of Ord,τhas a branch in A, which is the desired sequence hFα:αOrdi.
We can now define a proper class Y={yα:α < Ord}by transfinite induction
within (M,A) such that Yis almost contained in every Fαas follows:
y0is the first element of F0;
For α > 0, yαis the least member of T
δα
Fδabove {yδ:δ < α}.
It is clear that Ydecides each Sg
α. Therefore Dg
2is dense.
(3): Suppose f: [OrdM]nOrdM, where nis a standard natural number,
and f∈ A. Let
Df
3:= {YP:fis canonical on Y}.
By Theorem 2.2, Df
3is dense.
Remark 3.2.1. In sharp contrast to the usual scenario in the theory of large
cardinals, aP-generic filter is never normal. This is because if f∈ A and for
every αOrdMf1{βOrdM:β > α} ∈ P, then the following set Df
4forms a
dense subset of P:
Df
4:= {YP:g:Y11Ysuch that g∈ A and g < f on Y}.
We are now in a position to examine ultrapowers and their iterations.
Lemma 3.3. The following are equivalent for a countable model (M,A)of GBC :
1. (M,A)Ord is weakly compact”.
2. There is a nonprincipal (M,A)-iterable ultrafilter U.
3. (M, S)S∈A has a proper conservative e.e.e. (N, S)S∈A.
Proof .(1) (2) follows from Proposition 3.1 and part (2) of Theorem 3.2.
For (2) (3),let (N, S)S∈A be the ultrapower of (M, S)S∈A modulo U. More
precisely, let Fbe the family of functions ffrom OrdMinto Msuch that fis
canonically coded by some element of A. For f∈ F, let [f]Ube the U-equivalence
class of fconsisting of members of Fthat agree with fon a member of U. Define
N:=(N, F ), and Sfor S∈ A as follows
N:= {[f]U:f∈ F};
14 ALI ENAYAT
[f]F[g] iff {αOrdM:f(α)E g(α)}∈U, where E=M;
[f]USiff {αOrdM:f(α)S}∈U.
Thanks to the presence of a global well-ordering in A, the Lo´s Theorem for ul-
trapowers holds in this context. Consequently, if Uis a non-principal ultrafilter,
then Nis a proper elementary extension of M(with the obvious identification of
the U-equivalence classes of constant maps with elements of M). The (M,A)-
completeness property of U, coupled with the existence of a global well-ordering in
A, assures us that Nis an end extension of N. To verify the conservativity clause
one invokes the conservativity clause to show that A={cFM:cN}8.
To establish (3) (1), suppose τis an Ord-tree coded in A. We may assume
without loss of generality that τ= (OrdM, <τ), where the tree ordering <τsatisfies
() (M, τ )α, β Ord (α <τβαβ).
Therefore, τis end extended by τ(in the sense that if α <τβOrdMthen
αOrdM).Now let δOrdN\OrdM, and define
B:= {αOrdM:α <τδ}.
Since τeτand () holds, Bforms a branch of τ, and by conservativity, B∈ A.
Note that the equivalence of (2) and (3), as well as (3) (1) do not require
the countability condition on (M,A).
For an (M,A)-iterable ultrafilter U, the fact that the U-based ultrapower does
not introduce new subsets of OrdMallows one to iterate the ultrapower formation
any finite number of times to obtain the finite iteration U ltU,n(M, S )S∈A. Indeed,
the finite iteration can also be obtained in one step by defining an ultrafilter Un
on OrdMn
. To do so, suppose XOrdMn
,where Xis coded in A. By
definition, X∈ Un+1 iff
{α1:{(α2,···, αn+1 ) : (α1, α2,···, αn+1)X}∈Un}∈U.
(the iterability condition ensures that Un+1 is well-defined). Moreover, the process
of ultrapower formation modulo Ucan be iterated along any linear order Lto
yield the iterated ultrapower UltU,L(M, S)S∈A. There are two equivalent ways of
describing the isomorphism type of UltU,L(M, S )S∈A:
1. The model theoretic approach: This is essentially Gaifman’s iteration method in
his treatment of models of arithmetic [G]. Using an iterable ultrafilter Uone first
defines, for each positive natural number n, a complete n-type Γnover the model
(M, S)S∈A by defining Γn(x1,···, xn) as the set of formulas ϕ(x1,···, xn) such that
{(α1,···, αn):(M, S )S∈A ϕ(α1,···, αn)}∈Un.
Here ϕis a formula in the language L={∈} ∪ {S:S∈ A} (since for each
mM, {m}∈A,for all intents and purposes Lhas constant symbols for elements
of Mas well). Now augment the language Lwith a set of new constant symbols
{cl:lL}, and define ΨL:= {cl1cl2:l1<Ll2}and
TU,L:= ΨL∪ {ϕ(cl1,···, cl1) : ϕ(x1,···, xn)Γn(x1,···, xn)}.
8See [Kan, Lemma 19.1(c)] for a similar proof.
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 15
TU,Lturns out to be a complete Skolemized theory. Therefore UltU,L(M, S )S∈A can
be meaningfully defined as the prime model of TU,L.
2. The algebraic approach: This is how iterated ultrapowers are handled in set
theory `a la Kunen [Ku].Let I= [L]= the family of finite subsets of L. One
builds a category Cwhose objects are models of the form NS,for SI,and whose
morphisms are maps
πS1,S2:NS1NS2,with S1S2I,
such that the following properties hold:
N=M, and for SIwith |S|=n > 1,NS=M(OrdM)n/Un;
πS1,S2is an elementary embedding, whenever S1S2I;
πS1,S3=πS2,S3πS1,S2, whenever S1S2S3I.
In this approach, UltU,L(M, S)S∈A is defined as the direct limit of the category C.
One can then use the usual arguments from the theory of iterated ultrapowers (as
in [Jec], or [Kan]) to establish the following result.
Theorem 3.4. Suppose (N, S)S∈A := U ltU,L(M, S )S∈A,and l:= cN
l,where
(M,A)GBC, and Uis a nonprincipal (M,A)-iterable ultrafilter.
1. Elements of Nare of the form f(l1,···, ln),where f∈ A, and l1<···< ln;
2. for every L-formula ϕ(x1,···, xn),
Nϕ(l1,···, ln)iff {(α1,···, αn)OrdMn
:Mϕ(α1,···, αn)}∈Un;
3. {l:lL}is a set of order indiscernibles in (N, S)S∈A of order type L;
4. every automorphism hof Linduces an automorphism jhof (N, S )S∈A defined
by
jh(f(l1,···, ln)) = f(h(l1),···, h(ln)).
Theorem 3.5. Suppose (M,A)GBC + “Ord is weakly compact ”, and let
hbe an automorphism of a linearly ordered set Lwith no fixed points. If Uis
(M,A)-generic, then the fixed point set of the automorphism jhof (N, S)S∈A
:= UltU,L(M, S )S∈A is precisely M.
Proof .Note that by part (2) of Theorem 3.2, Uis (M,A)-iterable and there-
fore Theorem 3.4 applies. Clearly jhfixes each aMsince the constant map
fa(x) = ais in A. To see that jhfixes no member of N\M, suppose that for some
f(l1,···, ln)N,
(1) f(h(l1),···, h(ln)) = f(l1,···, ln).
Since f∈ A,by Theorem 3.2 there is some H∈ U,and some S⊆ {1,···, n}such
that for all sequences α1<···< αnand β1<···< βnof elements of H,
(2) f(α1,···, αn) = f(β1,···, βn)⇔ ∀iS(αi=βi).
Moreover, since Hn∈ Un,
(3) (l1,···, ln)(H)n, whenever l1<L···<Lln.
(1), (2), and (3) together imply that S=.So fmust be constant on H, hence
f(l1,···, ln)M.
16 ALI ENAYAT
Proof of Theorem A.Start with a consistent completion Tof Z F C +Φ. By
Theorem 2.1 there is a countable Mmodel of Tthat expands to a model (M,A) of
GBC +“Ord is weakly compact”. Use Proposition 3.1 to fix some generic ultrafilter
Uover (M,A), and let
(N, S)S∈A := U ltU,Z(M, S)S∈A,
where Zis the ordered set of integers. Consider the automorphism
n7−hn+ 1
of Z. By Theorem 3.5 jhis an automorphism of (N, S)S∈A whose fixed point set
is precisely M.
4. MAHLO CARDINALS FROM AUTOMORPHISMS
In this section we turn the table around and establish a “reversal” of Theorem
A. More specifically, in part (2) of Theorem B we show that over the weak fragment
EST +GW of ZF +GW (discussed in the preliminaries section), Z F C + Φ is
necessary for Theorem A. The proof of Theorem B relies on Theorem 2.1 and
Lemmas 4.1 through 4.5.
Through this section, L:= {∈,C}, and N:= (N , F, C)ES T (L) +
GW .
For MN, Mis the submodel (M, E , J) of N, where E:= FM2, and
J:= CM2.
Mis a C-cut of N, if Nproperly C-end extends M(i.e., aMb
N\M, a Cb) and N\Mhas no C-least member.
Suppose Mis a C-cut of N.Mis a strong C-cut of N, if for each function
fNwhose domain includes M, there is some sin N, such that for all
mM,
f(m)/Miff sCf(m).
This is the set theoretic analogue of the Kirby-Paris notion of strong cuts
[KP].
Lemma 4.1. Suppose Mis a C-cut of N.
1. aN\McNsuch that Nc={x:xCa}”, and McF.
2. [∆0(L)-overspill ]If ϕ(x)is a 0(L)-formula such that every element of Mis
a solution of ϕ(x), then there is a solution of ϕ(x)in N\M.
Proof .(1) is an immediate consequence of GW and the assumption that M
is C-end extended by N. To verify (2) assume the contrary and fix cNsuch that
McF. By ∆0(L)-Separation, for some sN,
Ns={xc:¬ϕ(x)} 6=.
Therefore shas a C-least element by GW , which must be the C-least member of
N\M, contradiction.
Theorem B. If jis an automorphism of Nwhose fixed point set Mis a C-initial
segment of N, and A:= {aFM:aN},then:
1. (M,A)GBC + “Ord is weakly compact ;
2. MZF C + Φ.
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 17
Note that Theorem 2.1 shows that the second part of Theorem B follows from its
first part. The proof of part (1) of Theorem B will be presented after establishing
Lemmas 4.2 through 4.5. We begin verifying some basic closure properties of M.
For the rest of this section jis an automorphism of Nwhose fixed point
set Mis a proper C-initial segment of N.
Lemma 4.2.
1. MeN.
2. If aNand aFM,then aM.
3. If aM,bN, and Nba,then bM.
Proof .(1) is an immediate consequence of coupling the definition of a C-cut with
GW . For (2), suppose aNand aFM. Then for every xN,
NxaNxj(a).
Hence by Extensionality, j(a) = a, so aM. Finally, (3) follows easily from (2).
Lemma 4.3. Msatisfies ES T (L) + GW + Power Set.
Proof .Lemma 4.2 is our tool for verifying that Minherits ES T (L) + GW
from N: Extensionality and Foundation are inherited by part (1); Pairs and Union
are inherited by part (2); ∆0(L)-Separation is inherited by part (3). Infinity holds
by coupling the assumption that Mforms a C-initial segment of N, with the fact
that ωNis first order definable in N(and is therefore fixed by every automorphism
of N). GW is also easily verified by parts (1) and (2) of Lemma 4.2.
To verify Power Set in M, observe that by part (3) of Lemma 4.2, if aM
then all subsets of a(in the sense of N) are in M. By part (1) of Proposition 4.1,
there is some cNsuch that McF, and by ∆0(L)-Separation in Nthe set
d:= {xc:xa}exists in N. Since dMby part (3) of Proposition 4.2, this
shows that Msatisfies Power Set.
Lemma 4.4 unveils the most important feature of M. It will be used in Lemma
4.5 to uniformly translate global predicates in (M, S)S∈A to local ones in N.
Lemma 4.4. Mis a strong C-cut of N.
Proof .Recall that by assumption Mis a C-initial segment of N. Clearly Mis
aC-cut of Nsince if ais the C-least element of N\M, then by a reasoning similar
to the proof of part (2) of Lemma 4.2, j(a) = a, which contradicts a /M. Next,
suppose fis the graph of a function in Nwhose domain includes M. Let g:= j(f),
and note that f /M,g /M, and f6=g. Therefore:
(1) mM[f(m) = g(m)f(m)M].
We wish to find sNsuch that for all mM, f (m)/Miff sCf(m).Without
loss of generality there is some m0Mwith f(m0)/M. Fix cNsuch that
McFand
Nc(f(f)(∪ ∪ f)g(g)(∪ ∪ g)).
Let mMwith m0Cm, and consider the ∆0(L)-formula ϕ(x) with parameters
m,fand g:
ϕ(x, m) := vc[vCmand (x=f(v)6=g(v))].
18 ALI ENAYAT
Note that by ∆0(L)-Separation Nthinks that for every mMwith m0Cm,
{xc:ϕ(x, m)}exists and has a C-least member h(m).By (1), for every mM
with m0Cm, h(m)N\M. Therefore,
(2) mM[m0CmNmCh(m)].
Observe that the predicate ψ(m) expressing mCh(m) is a ∆0(L)-formula, because
all the quantifiers of ψcan be limited to c. So by ∆0(L)-overspill there is some
aN\Msuch that NaCh(a).The desired sdemonstrating the strength of M
in Nis h(a) since
(3) mM[m0CmNh(a)Eh(m)],
which, coupled with (2), implies
(4) mM[h(a)Cmf(m)/M].
Lemma 4.5. Let L={∈} ∪ {S:S∈ A}.For every L-formula
ϕ(
x ,
S),
with free variables
xand parameters
Sfrom A,there is some 0(L)-formula
θϕ(
x ,
b),
where
bis a sequence of parameters from N,such that for all sequences
aof
elements of Mof the same length as
x ,
(M, S)S∈A ϕ(
a ,
S)iff Nθϕ(
a ,
b).
Proof .Fix an element dNwith MdF. Since EST does not guarantee
the existence of Cartesian products, we first wish to show that for each standard
natural number nthere is some element cnNsuch that M(cn)Fand the
n-fold Cartesian product (cn)nexists in N. By Lemma 4.3, Power Set holds in
M, so for every standard natural number nand every xM, Mthinks that the
Cartesian product xnexists. Given a fixed standard natural number n, consider
the ∆0(L)-formula ψn(x) :
ψn(x) := ydzd(“y={td:tCx}” and z=yn).
Since every element of Mis a solution to ψn, by ∆0(L)-overspill there is some
solution aof ψnin N\M. The desired cnis {td:tCa}.
We construct θϕby recursion on the complexity of ϕas follows:
If ϕis an atomic formula of the form Si(v), where vis a term, then choose
bNsuch that bFM=Si, and define θϕ:= (vb). For other atomic
formulas ϕ, θϕ:= ϕ.
If ϕ=¬δ, then θϕ:= ¬θδ;
If ϕ=δ1δ2, then θϕ:= θδ1θδ2;
If ϕ=(v ,
x) and the length of
xis n, then consider the function
f(
x) defined in Non (cn+1)nby
f(
x) := the C-least vcn+1 such that θδ(v,
x),
if vcn+1 θδ(v,
x); and 0 otherwise. Note that the graph of fis defined
by a ∆0(L)-formula within N, so fis coded in Nsince the n-fold Cartesian
product (cn+1)n+1 exists in Nas arranged earlier. By Lemma 4.4, there
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 19
is some sN, such that for all mM, f (m)Miff f(m)Es. Now
use GW to find bNsuch that Nb={x:xCs},and define:
θ(v,
x):= vb θδ(v,
x).
We are now in possession of sufficient machinery to present:
Proof of Theorem B.By Lemma 4.3 Msatisfies E ST (L)+ Power Set +
GW . Hence we only need to verify:
(1) Σ(L)-Replacement, where L={∈} ∪ {S:S∈ A},and
(2) Ord is weakly compact.
To establish Σ(L)-Replacement, suppose that for some L-formula ϕ(x, y) (with
suppressed parameters), and some aM,
() (M, S)S∈A xa!y ϕ(x, y ).
We first wish to find a C-initial segment of Ncontaining Mon which the formula
θϕ(x, y) (whose parameters are also suppressed) defines the graph of a function
whose domain is a subset of a. This can easily be accomplished by ∆0(L)-overspill:
fix dNwith MdFand consider the ∆0(L)-formula ψ(v):
ψ(v) := xa[1yd(yCvand θϕ(x, y))].
By () and Lemma 4.5, every element of Mis a solution to ψ. Hence by ∆0(L)-
overspill there is some aN\Msatisfying ψ. Let c={td:tCa}in the sense
of N. Note that:
if m0aE,m1cF,and Nθϕ(m0, m1), then m1M.
Hence
{ycF:Nxa θϕ(x, y)}={yM:Mxa ϕ(x, y)}.
By ∆0(L)-Separation in N, the left hand side of the above equation is the extension
of some element mN. But since mFM, by part (2) of Lemma 4.2, mM.
This completes the verification of Σ(L)-Replacement in M.
We now know that (M, S)S∈A is a model of GBC. To show that Ord is weakly
compact in (M,A), we need to refine the reasoning used in the proof of (3) (1)
of Lemma 3.3 in order to use ∆0(L)-overspill instead of elementarity. Suppose τ
is an Ord-tree coded in A. Thanks to the existence of a global well-ordering in A
we may assume without loss of generality that τ= (M, <τ) for some relation <τ
of the form rM, where rN, and
(M, τ )x, y (x <τyxCy).
Fix cNwith McE. Let kbe the field of r, and consider the relational
structure τ:= (k, <τ)N. For xk, let τ(x)=(x, x2<τ),and let θ(v)
be the ∆0(L)-formula:
zc[“z={y:yCv}” and “τ(z) is a tree” and x, y z(x <τyxCy)].
Clearly for all mM, Nθ(m). Therefore by ∆0(L)-overspill there is an element
of N\Msatisfying ϕ. This shows that there is some initial segment τof τin N
whose field kcontains M, and <τis stronger than Con k. It follows that τdoes
not introduce any new elements below the elements of τ(in the sense of the tree
20 ALI ENAYAT
ordering).So we can choose tk\M, and define the desired branch B∈ A of τby
B:= {mM:m <τt}.
Remark 4.5. It is shown in [E-4] that, similar to Theorem A, Theorem 1.1 also
has a reversal: If Nis a model of the fragment I-∆0of P A (also known as bounded
arithmetic) that has an automorphism whose fixed point set is a proper initial
segment Mof N, then Mis a model of P A.
Remark 4.6. By a theorem of Kaye, Kossak, and Kotlarski [KKK, Theorem 5.6],
for a countable recursively saturated model Mof P A, the condition “Iis a strong
elementary cut of M” is equivalent to the condition “there is an automorphism of
Mwhose fixed point set is precisely I”. The analogue of this result for models of
set theory is established in [E-5].
5. CONSEQUENCES FOR N F U
In this section we reap the benefits of Theorems A and B for the Quine-Jensen
system of set theory N F U . The theory N F U was introduced by Jensen [Jen] as a
modification of Quine’s elegant formulation NF (New Foundations) [Q] of Russell’s
theory of types. N F is a first order theory formulated in the usual language of set
theory {∈} whose axioms consist of the stratifiable comprehension scheme and the
usual extensionality axiom. The stratifiable comprehension scheme is the collection
of sentences of the form “{x:ϕ(x)}exists”, provided there is an integer valued
function fwhose domain is the set of all variables occurring in ϕ, which satisfies
the following two requirements:
1. f(v) + 1 = f(w), whenever (vw) is a subformula of ϕ;
2. f(v) = f(w), whenever (v=w) is a subformula of ϕ.
Since the formula ϕ(x) := (x=x) is stratifiable, NF proves the existence of
a universal set, but the stratification requirement allows NF to avoid - at least
seemingly - the usual paradoxes of the existence of “large sets” such as Russell’s
and Burali-Forti’s. However, the formal consistency of NF relative to any ZF -style
system of set theory remains an open question.
Jensen’s variant N F U of N F is obtained by modifying the extensionality axiom
so as to allow urelements (hence the Uin N F U ). Inspired by Specker’s work [Sp]
on the equiconsistency of NF with the simple theory of types augmented by the
ambiguity scheme, Jensen made a breakthrough by establishing the consistency of
N F U relative to the fragment ZBQC9of Zermelo set theory consisting of EST +
Power Set. Jensen’s method, as refined by Boffa [Bo], shows that one can construct
a model of
N F U +:= NF U + Choice + Infinity,
starting from a model Mof ZBQC that has an automorphism jwith j(κ)(2κ)M
for some infinite cardinal κof M.In the other direction, Hinnion [Hi] showed that in
every model of Aof N F U +one can uniformly interpret a Zermelian structure ZA
of ZF C \{Power Set}, and a nontrivial endomorphism kof ZAonto a proper initial
9Zermelo set theory with bounded quantification was independently discovered by MacLane
who dubbed it ZBQC and championed it as a parsimonious foundation for mathematical practice
[Mac, p.373]. Curiously, ZB QC was also isolated by Ressayre [Re], in his work on the model
theory of weak systems of set theory (Ressayre calls this theory Bounded Set Theory, BST ).
Mathias’ [Mat] is an excellent source of information about ZB QC.
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 21
segment of ZA. Hinnion’s work on Zwas rediscovered by Holmes [Ho-1], whose
account prompted Solovay [So] to provide an alternative streamlined development of
Z. The endomorphism kcan be used to “unravel” ZAto a model (Z)Aof ZBQC
that has a nontrivial automorphism j. Consequently, the construction of models
of the radical system N F U is reduced to building appropriate automorphisms of
models of fragments of orthodox set theory. To summarize:
Theorem 5.1. (Jensen-Boffa-Hinnion) N F U +has a model iff there is a model M
of ZBQC that has an automorphism jsuch that for some infinite cardinal κof
M, (2κ)Mj(κ).
The system N F U A is obtained by augmenting the theory NF U +with the
axiom10 “every Cantorian set is strongly Cantorian”. A set Xis said to be Canto-
rian if there exists a bijection between Xand the set of its singletons UCS(X) :=
{{x}:xX}.Strongly Cantorian sets, on the other hand, are sets Xfor which
the graph of the “obvious” bijection x7−→ {x}between Xand UC S(X) forms
a set. In the framework of the usual Zermelo-style systems of set theory, every
nonempty set is obviously strongly Cantorian. However, in N F U the universal set
Vand many other “large” sets are not Cantorian. Moreover, there are models of
N F U in which the set of finite cardinals provides an example of a Cantorian set
that fails to be strongly Cantorian. The following result shows that building models
of N F U A amounts to building appropriate automorphisms of models of the theory
ZBQC({∈,C}) + GW (C).
Theorem 5.2. (Folklore). Let T0:= ZBQC({∈,C}) + GW (C).
1. If AN F U A, then there is an initial segment Nof (Z)Asatisfying T0such
that the collection of Cantorian elements (CZ )Aof ZAform a C-cut of N,and
there is an automorphism jof Nwhose fixed point set is (C Z )A.
2. If NT0has an automorphism jfixing a C-cut Mof N,and for some infinite
cardinal κ, (2κ)Mj(κ), then there is a model Aof N F U A such that Mis
isomorphic to (CZ)A.
Holmes introduced an extension N F U M of N F UA in [Ho-1] and proved in [Ho-
2] that N F U M is consistent relative to ZF C + “there is a measurable cardinal”.
This provided an upper bound for the consistency strength of N F U A until Solovay
established the unexpected calibrations of (1) the consistency strength of N F U A
in terms of Mahlo cardinals [1995, unpublished], and (2) the consistency strength
of the system N F U B in terms of weakly compact cardinals [So] (N F U B is an
intermediate system between NF U A and N F UM ). The next result uses Theorems
A and B to reveal an intimate connection between Z F C + Φ and N F U A.
Theorem 5.3. The following are equivalent for a theory T in the language {∈}:
1. Tis a consistent completion of ZF C + Φ.
2. There is a model Aof N F U A such that T=T h(CZ)A.
Proof .For (1) (2), suppose Tis a consistent completion of Z F C + Φ. By
Theorem A there is a model M= (M , E, C) of Tsuch that MZF (C) + GW ,
and Mhas a proper elementary C-end extension Nsuch that Mis the fixed point
set of some automorphism of N. So by part (2) of Theorem 5.2, there is a model
10This axiom was first considered by Henson [He].
22 ALI ENAYAT
Aof N F U A such that T=T h(CZ )A.(2) (1) is an immediate consequence of
coupling part (1) of Theorem 5.2 with Theorem B.
Corollary 5.4. (Solovay for LCZ , Holmes [Ho-2] for CZ)N F U A proves the exis-
tence of n-Mahlo cardinals in CZ.
Corollary 5.5. (Solovay) The following theories are equiconsistent:
1. T1:= ZF C +{there is an n-Mahlo cardinal”:nω}.
2. T2:= N F U A.
Proof .To see that Con(T1)Con(T2), assume that T1has a model M. By
Proposition of Section 2, Z F C + Φ is finitely satisfiable in Mand therefore
ZF C + Φ is consistent. Now use (1) (2) of Theorem 5.3. The implication
Con(T2)Con(T1) is an immediate consequence of (2) (1) of Theorem 5.3.
Our last corollary, which follows directly from Corollaries 2.1.1 and 2.1.2 and
Theorem 5.3, shows that if N F UA is consistent, then it cannot settle the truth
value of many statements, such as V=Lor Continuum Hypothesis, in CZ.
Corollary 5.6. Assume N F U A is consistent. If ψis a statement of set theory
satisfying either
1. ZF `ψholds in L”, or
2. ZF C `for some poset P, 1Pψ,
then there is a model Aof N F U A such that (CZ)Aψ.
Remark 5.7. Part 1 of Theorem 5.2, Theorem B, and [E-2, Theorem 3.6] together
imply that there are countable models of ZF C + Φ that are not isomorphic to any
model of the form (CZ)A, with AN F U A. However, every countable recursively
saturated model of Z F C + Φ is of the form (CZ)A, for some AN F U A. This
can be verified by coupling Theorem 5.3 with the classical theorem of Barwise and
Ressayre [D, Theorem 4.59] on the resplendence property of countable recursively
saturated models. Conversely, it can be shown (using Theorem B, Theorem 5.2,
and [E-3, Theorem 4.5(i)]) that if AN F U A and ωAis nonstandard, then (CZ)A
is recursively saturated.
References
[Bar] J. Barwise, Admissible Sets and Structures, Springer-Verlag, Berlin (1975).
[Bau] J. Baumgartner, Canonical partition relations,J. Sym. Logic, vol. 40 (1975), pp. 541-554.
[Bo] M. Boffa, ZFJ and the consistency problem for NF,Jahrbuch der Kurt-G¨odel-
Gesellschaft, pp. 102-106 (1988).
[D] K. Doets, Basic Model Theory, CSLI publications, Stanford (1996).
[E-1] A. Enayat, On certain elementary extensions of models of set theory,Trans. Amer.
Math. Soc. vol. 283 (1984), pp. 705-715.
[E-2] , Conservative extensions of models of set Theory and generalizations,J. Sym. Logic,
vol. 51 (1986), pp. 1005-1021.
[E-3] , Power-like models of set theory,J. Sym. Logic, vol. 66 (2001), pp.1766-1782.
[E-4] , From bounded to second order arithmetic via automorphisms, in preparation.
[E-5] , Automorphisms of models of set theory, in preparation.
[ER] P. Erd¨os and R. Rado, A combinatorial theorem,J. London Math. Society, vol. 25
(1950), pp. 249-255.
[Fe] U. Felgner, Comparisons of the axioms of local and global choice,Fund. Math. vol. 71
(1971), pp. 43-62.
[Fo] Forster, Set Theory with a Universal Set, Second ed., Oxford Logic Guides, vol. 31,
Oxford University Press (1995).
AUTOMORPHISMS, MAHLO CARDINALS, AND NFU 23
[G] H. Gaifman, Models and types of arithmetic, Ann. Math. Logic,vol. 9 (1976), pp.
223-306.
[He] W. Henson,Type-raising operations on cardinals and ordinals in Quine’s “New Founda-
tions”,J. Sym. Logic, vol.39 (1973), pp. 59-68 .
[Hi] R. Hinnion, Sur la th´eorie des ensembles de Quine, Ph. D. thesis, UMD Brussels
(1975).
[Ho-1] R. Holmes, Elementary Set Theory with a Universal Set, Cahiers du Centre de
Logic, vol. 10, Academia, Louvain la-Neuve, Belgium (1998).
[Ho-2] , Strong axioms of infinity in NFU, J. Sym. Logic, vol. 66 (2001), pp. 87-116.
[Jec] T. Jech, Set Theory, Academic Press, New York (1978).
[Jen] B. Jensen, On the consistency of a slight (?) modification of Quine’s New Foundations,
Synthese, vol. 19 (1969), pp. 250-263 .
[Kan] A. Kanamori, The Higher Infinite, Springer-Verlag, Berlin (1994).
[Kau] M. Kaufmann, Blunt and topless end extensions of models of set theory,J. Sym. Logic
48 (1983), pp. 1053-1073.
[KKK] R. Kaye, R. Kossak, and H. Kotlarski, Automorphisms of recursively saturated models of
arithmetic,Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, vol. 55 (1991), pp.67-99.
[KP] L. Kirby and J. Paris, Initial segments of models of Peano’s axioms, in Lecture Notes
in Mathematics, vol. 619, Springer-Verlag, 1977, pp. 211-226.
[Ku] K. Kunen, Some applications of iterated ultrapowers in set theory,Ann. Math. Logic 1
(1970), pp. 179-227.
[Mac] S. MacLane, Mathematics, Form and Function, Springer-Verlag (1986).
[Mat] A. Mathias, The strength of Mac Lane set theory, vol. 110 (2001), no. 1-3, pp. 107–234.
[Q] W.V.O. Quine, New foundations for mathematical logic,Amer. Math. Monthly, vol.
44 (1937), pp. 70-80.
[Re] J. P. Ressayre, Mod`eles non standard et sous-syst`em remarquable de ZF, in Modeles Non
Standard en Arithmetic et Theorie des Ensembles (J. P. Ressayre and A. Wilke,
ed.), Publication Mathematiques de l’Universite Paris 7, Paris (1986).
[Ro] J.B. Rosser, Logic for Mathematicians, McGraw-Hill, reprinted (with appendices) by
Chelsea, New York (1978).
[SS] J. Schmerl and S. Shelah, On power-like models for hyperinaccessible cardinals,J. Sym.
Logic 37 (1972), pp. 531-537
[So] R. Solovay, The consistency strength of NFUB, preprint available at Front for the Mathe-
matics ArXiv, http://front.math.ucdavis.edu
[Sp] E. Specker, Typical ambiguity,Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science (E.
Nagel, ed.), Stanford (1962).
... The gist of our generalization of Gaifman's result is that any countable model (M, A) of the theory GBC + "Ord is weakly compact" 3 has an elementary rank-end-extension N , such that SSy M (N ) = (M, A). This result was actually obtained in [Enayat, 2004], but in this paper a more detailed result is proved, see Theorem 8.6. ...
... In [Enayat, 2004] it is shown that the L 0 -consequences of GBC + "Ord is weakly compact" are the same as for ZFC + Φ, where Φ = {∃κ."κ is n-Mahlo and V κ ≺ Σn V " | n ∈ N}. ...
... It will be helpful to think of the ultrapower as a function (actually functor) of L rather than as a function of (M, A), so we introduce the alternative notation Gaifman [Gaifman, 1976] essentially proved the theorem below for models of arithmetic. A substantial chunk of its generalization to models of set theory was proved for specific needs in [Enayat, 2004]. ...
Preprint
A theoretical development is carried to establish fundamental results about rank-initial embeddings and automorphisms of countable non-standard models of set theory, with a keen eye for their sets of fixed points. These results are then combined into a "geometric technique" used to prove several results about countable non-standard models of set theory. In particular, back-and-forth constructions are carried out to establish various generalizations and refinements of Friedman's theorem on the existence of rank-initial embeddings between countable non-standard models of the fragment $\mathrm{KP}^\mathcal{P}$ + $\Sigma_1^\mathcal{P}$-Separation of $\mathrm{ZF}$; and Gaifman's technique of iterated ultrapowers is employed to show that any countable model of $\mathrm{GBC}$ + "$\mathrm{Ord}$ is weakly compact" can be elementarily rank-end-extended to models with well-behaved automorphisms whose sets of fixed points equal the original model. These theoretical developments are then utilized to prove various results relating self-embeddings, automorphisms, their sets of fixed points, strong rank-cuts, and set theories of different strengths. Two examples: The notion of "strong rank-cut" is characterized (i) in terms of the theory $\mathrm{GBC}$ + "$\mathrm{Ord}$ is weakly compact", and (ii) in terms of fixed-point sets of self-embeddings.
... By NFUA is meant the system NFU (with stratified pairing) together with the axioms of infinity and choice and the axiom "every Cantorian class is strongly Cantorian". In Holmes (1998), chapter 20, it is shown how to interpret ZFC in an extension of NFU stronger than NFUA via a certain class of isomorphism types of pointed well-founded extensional relations; this interpretation works in NFUA as well by recent results of Enayat (2004). In fact, much stronger extensions of ZFC come along with that interpretation: in unpublished work, Solovay established the equiconsistency of NFUA with ZFC + "there exist n-Mahlo cardinals" (for each n ∈ ω); a published proof of that is to be found in Enayat (2004), Theorem 5.5. ...
... In Holmes (1998), chapter 20, it is shown how to interpret ZFC in an extension of NFU stronger than NFUA via a certain class of isomorphism types of pointed well-founded extensional relations; this interpretation works in NFUA as well by recent results of Enayat (2004). In fact, much stronger extensions of ZFC come along with that interpretation: in unpublished work, Solovay established the equiconsistency of NFUA with ZFC + "there exist n-Mahlo cardinals" (for each n ∈ ω); a published proof of that is to be found in Enayat (2004), Theorem 5.5. The strength of the full system in Holmes (1998) has been shown to be that of Morse-Kelley set theory MK plus measurability (in a suitable sense) of the proper class ordinal (the class of all ordinals considered as a virtual ordinal) Holmes (2001). ...
... Actually, NFU is quite weak, proof-theoretically, compared to PA(Solovay, unpublished). As shown byEnayat (2004), one can obtain an extension of NFU equivalent in strength to PA by adding "every set is finite" and "every Cantorian set is strongly Cantorian" as axioms (cf. the final section below for the notions of Cantorian and strongly Cantorian sets in the framework of NFU). ...
... By NFUA is meant the system NFU (with stratified pairing) together with the axioms of infinity and choice and the axiom "every Cantorian class is strongly Cantorian". In Holmes (1998), chapter 20, it is shown how to interpret ZFC in an extension of NFU stronger than NFUA via a certain class of isomorphism types of pointed well-founded extensional relations; this interpretation works in NFUA as well by recent results of Enayat (2004). In fact, much stronger extensions of ZFC come along with that interpretation: in unpublished work, Solovay established the equiconsistency of NFUA with ZFC + "there exist n-Mahlo cardinals" (for each n ∈ ω); a published proof of that is to be found in Enayat (2004), Theorem 5.5. ...
... In Holmes (1998), chapter 20, it is shown how to interpret ZFC in an extension of NFU stronger than NFUA via a certain class of isomorphism types of pointed well-founded extensional relations; this interpretation works in NFUA as well by recent results of Enayat (2004). In fact, much stronger extensions of ZFC come along with that interpretation: in unpublished work, Solovay established the equiconsistency of NFUA with ZFC + "there exist n-Mahlo cardinals" (for each n ∈ ω); a published proof of that is to be found in Enayat (2004), Theorem 5.5. The strength of the full system in Holmes (1998) has been shown to be that of Morse-Kelley set theory MK plus measurability (in a suitable sense) of the proper class ordinal (the class of all ordinals considered as a virtual ordinal) Holmes (2001). ...
... Actually, NFU is quite weak, proof-theoretically, compared to PA(Solovay, unpublished). As shown byEnayat (2004), one can obtain an extension of NFU equivalent in strength to PA by adding "every set is finite" and "every Cantorian set is strongly Cantorian" as axioms (cf. the final section below for the notions of Cantorian and strongly Cantorian sets in the framework of NFU). ...
... The gist of our generalization of Gaifman's result is that any countable model (M, A) of the theory GBC + "Ord is weakly compact" 3 has an elementary rank-endextension N , such that SSy M (N ) = (M, A). This result was actually obtained in [6], but in this paper a more detailed result is proved, see Theorem 8.6. ...
... In [6] it is shown that the L 0 -consequences of GBC + "Ord is weakly compact" are the same as for ZFC + , where = {∃κ · "κ is n-Mahlo and V κ ≺ n V " | n ∈ N}. ...
... Gaifman [11] essentially proved the theorem below for models of arithmetic. A substantial chunk of its generalization to models of set theory was proved for specific needs in [6]. (f) We may assume that L extends K and that G(L) extends G(K). ...
Article
Full-text available
A theoretical development is carried to establish fundamental results about rank-initial embeddings and automorphisms of countable non-standard models of set theory, with a keen eye for their sets of fixed points. These results are then combined into a “geometric technique” used to prove several results about countable non-standard models of set theory. In particular, back-and-forth constructions are carried out to establish various generalizations and refinements of Friedman’s theorem on the existence of rank-initial embeddings between countable non-standard models of the fragment \({\mathrm {KP}}^{{\mathcal {P}}}\) + \(\Sigma _1^{{\mathcal {P}}}\)-Separation of \({\mathrm {ZF}}\); and Gaifman’s technique of iterated ultrapowers is employed to show that any countable model of \({\mathrm {GBC}} + \text {``}{\mathrm {Ord}}\text { is weakly compact''}\) can be elementarily rank-end-extended to models with well-behaved automorphisms whose sets of fixed points equal the original model. These theoretical developments are then utilized to prove various results relating self-embeddings, automorphisms, their sets of fixed points, strong rank-cuts, and set theories of different strengths. Two examples: The notion of “strong rank-cut” is characterized (i) in terms of the theory \({\mathrm {GBC}} + \text {``}{\mathrm {Ord}}\text { is weakly compact''}\), and (ii) in terms of fixed-point sets of self-embeddings.
... This was facilitated by the technical break-through of iterated ultrapowers, introduced by Gaifman and later adapted by Kunen to a set theoretical setting. In [Enayat, 2004], Gaifman's results along these lines were partly generalized to models of set theory. They are further refined and generalized in Section 5.1 of the present monograph. ...
... There are various interesting axioms that can be added to NFU to increase its consistency strength. As the understanding of automorphisms of nonstandard models of ZF-style set theories has increased, several results on the consistency strength of such extensions of NFU have been obtained in the work of Solovay [Solovay, 1997], Enayat [Enayat, 2004] and McKenzie [McKenzie, 2015]. NFU proves Infinity and is equiconsistent with Mac Lane set theory; Ext S + SC S is weaker and does not prove Infinity. ...
... In [Enayat, 2004] it is shown that the L 0 -consequences of GBC + "Ord is weakly compact" are the same as for ZFC + Φ, where ...
Preprint
This thesis concerns embeddings and self-embeddings of foundational structures in both set theory and category theory. The first part of the work on models of set theory consists in establishing a refined version of Friedman's theorem on the existence of embeddings between countable non-standard models of a fragment of ZF, and an analogue of a theorem of Gaifman to the effect that certain countable models of set theory can be elementarily end-extended to a model with many automorphisms whose sets of fixed points equal the original model. The second part of the work on set theory consists in combining these two results into a technical machinery, yielding several results about non-standard models of set theory relating such notions as self-embeddings, their sets of fixed points, strong rank-cuts, and set theories of different strengths. The work in foundational category theory consists in the formulation of a novel algebraic set theory which is proved to be equiconsistent to New Foundations (NF), and which can be modulated to correspond to intuitionistic or classical NF, with or without atoms. A key axiom of this theory expresses that its structures have an endofunctor with natural properties.
... Then a parametrically M-definable set X ⊆ M 2 belongs to U 2 precisely when for almost all m 1 ∈ M, it is the case that for almost all m 2 ∈ M the pair m 1 , m 2 is in X . 7 To make that precise, it is convenient to introduce notation for a section of X , so let: ...
... Iterated ultrapowers have proved indispensable in the study of inner models of large cardinals ever since Kunen's work [25]; see Jech's monograph [18,Chapter 19] for the basic applications, and Steel's lecture notes [31] for the state of the art. The applications of iterated ultrapowers in set theory are focused on well-founded models of set theory, however iterated ultrapowers are also an effective tool in the study of automorphisms of models of set theory (where well-founded models are of little interest since no well-founded model of the axiom of extensionality has a nontrivial automorphism); see, e.g., [7,11]. Iterated ultrapowers have also found many applications elsewhere, e.g., in the work of Hrbáček [17], and Kanovei and Shelah [19] on the foundations of nonstandard analysis. ...
Article
Full-text available
We present a novel, perspicuous framework for building iterated ultrapowers. Our framework naturally lends itself to the construction of a certain type of indiscernibles, here dubbed $\textit{tight indiscernibles}$, which are shown to provide smooth proofs of the following results: $\textbf{Theorem.}$ Suppose $\mathcal{M=(}M,...)$ is an infinite structure. $\textbf{(A)}$ There is a proper elementary extension $\mathcal{M}^{\ast}$ of $\mathcal{M}$ such that some automorphism $\alpha$ of $\mathcal{M}^{\ast}$ pointwise fixes exactly $M$, i.e., $\alpha(m)=m$ if and only if $m\in M$. $\textbf{(B)}$ There is a family of proper elementary extensions $\{\mathcal{M}_{i}:i\in \omega \}$ of $\mathcal{M}$ whose intersection is $M$, such that for all $i$, $\mathcal{M}_{i}$ is a proper elementary extension of $\mathcal{M}_{i+1}$. $\textbf{(C)}$ Let $I$ be any set. Then there is a family $\{\mathcal{M}_{S}:S\subseteq I\}$ of proper elementary extensions of $\mathcal{M}$ such that $\mathcal{M}_{S_{0}}\prec \mathcal{M}_{S_{1}}$ whenever $S_{0}\subseteq S_{1}\subseteq I$ with the additional property that $M_{S_{0}}\cap M_{S_{1}}=M$ for all disjoint $S_{0},$ $S_{1}$.
... There are various interesting axioms that can be added to NFU to increase its consistency strength. As the understanding of automorphisms of nonstandard models of ZF-style set theories has increased, several results on the consistency strength of such extensions of NFU have been obtained in the work of Solovay [Solovay, 1997], Enayat [Enayat, 2004] and McKenzie [McKenzie, 2015]. In this paper we define NFU as a theory in the language {∈, S, −, − }, where S is a predicate distinguishing sets from atoms and −, − is a primitive pairing function, axiomatized as Ext S + SC S + P + Sethood, where Ext S and SC S are extensionality and stratified comprehension for sets, P regulates −, − and Sethood regulates S, to be specified below. ...
Article
New Foundations ($\mathrm{NF}$) is a set theory obtained from naive set theory by putting a stratification constraint on the comprehension schema; for example, it proves that there is a universal set $V$. $\mathrm{NFU}$ ($\mathrm{NF}$ with atoms) is known to be consistent through its close connection with models of conventional set theory that admit automorphisms. A first-order theory, $\mathrm{ML}_\mathrm{CAT}$, in the language of categories is introduced and proved to be equiconsistent to $\mathrm{NF}$ (analogous results are obtained for intuitionistic and classical $\mathrm{NF}$ with and without atoms). $\mathrm{ML}_\mathrm{CAT}$ is intended to capture the categorical content of the predicative class theory of $\mathrm{NF}$. $\mathrm{NF}$ is interpreted in $\mathrm{ML}_\mathrm{CAT}$ through the categorical semantics. Thus, the result enables application of category theoretic techniques to meta-mathematical problems about $\mathrm{NF}$ -style set theory. For example, an immediate corollary is that $\mathrm{NF}$ is equiconsistent to $\mathrm{NFU} + |V| = |\mathcal{P}(V)|$. This is already proved by Crabb\'e, but becomes intuitively obvious in light of the results of this paper. Just like a category of classes has a distinguished subcategory of small morphisms, a category modelling $\mathrm{ML}_\mathrm{CAT}$ has a distinguished subcategory of type-level morphisms. This corresponds to the distinction between sets and proper classes in $\mathrm{NF}$. With this in place, the axiom of power objects familiar from topos theory can be appropriately formulated for $\mathrm{NF}$. It turns out that the subcategory of type-level morphisms contains a topos as a natural subcategory.
Chapter
Since their inception, the Perspectives in Logic and Lecture Notes in Logic series have published seminal works by leading logicians. Many of the original books in the series have been unavailable for years, but they are now in print once again. This volume, the twenty-sixth publication in the Lecture Notes in Logic series, contains the proceedings of the 'Workshop and Conference on Logic, Algebra and Arithmetic' held at the Institute for Studies in Theoretical Physics and Mathematics (IPM) in Tehran, Iran in October, 2003. These papers are mostly revised and expanded versions of those that were originally presented at the meeting and address all areas of mathematical logic. The book also includes a short history of mathematical logic in Iran.
Thesis
Full-text available
"New Foundations", or NF, is an axiomatic set theory proposed by Quine, whose properties and the implementation of ordinary mathematical objects in it are quite different from the standard set theory. This system deviates from the mainstream of set-theoretic research, while its relative consistency remains one of the best known and oldest open problems in consistency problems. This paper gives an overview of the state of research in NF, including the motivation, the mathematics within it, standard techniques, related systems, and recent developments.
Article
This paper consists in the formulation of a novel categorical set theory, ML Cat , which is proved to be equiconsistent to New Foundations (NF), and which can be modulated to correspond to intuitionistic (denoted with an “I” on the left) or classical NF, with atoms (denoted with a “U” on the right) or not:
Article
Saunders Mac Lane has drawn attention many times, particularly in his book Mathematics: Form and Function, to the system ZBQC of set theory of which the axioms are Extensionality, Null Set, Pairing, Union, Infinity, Power Set, Restricted Separation, Foundation, and Choice, to which system, afforced by the principle, TCo, of Transitive Containment, we shall refer as MAC. His system is naturally related to systems derived from topos-theoretic notions concerning the category of sets, and is, as Mac Lane emphasises, one that is adequate for much of mathematics. In this paper we show that the consistency strength of Mac Lane's system is not increased by adding the axioms of Kripke–Platek set theory and even the Axiom of Constructibility to Mac Lane's axioms; our method requires a close study of Axiom H, which was proposed by Mitchell; we digress to apply these methods to subsystems of Zermelo set theory Z, and obtain an apparently new proof that Z is not finitely axiomatisable; we study Friedman's strengthening of , and the Forster–Kaye subsystem KF of MAC, and use forcing over ill-founded models and forcing to establish independence results concerning MAC and ; we show, again using ill-founded models, that proves the consistency of ; turning to systems that are type-theoretic in spirit or in fact, we show by arguments of Coret and Boffa that KF proves a weak form of Stratified Collection, and that is a conservative extension of MAC for stratified sentences, from which we deduce that proves a strong stratified version of ; we analyse the known equiconsistency of MAC with the simple theory of types and give Lake's proof that an instance of Mathematical Induction is unprovable in Mac Lane's system; we study a simple set theoretic assertion—namely that there exists an infinite set of infinite sets, no two of which have the same cardinal—and use it to establish the failure of the full schema of Stratified Collection in Z; and we determine the point of failure of various other schemata in MAC. The paper closes with some philosophical remarks.
Article
Without Abstract