ArticlePDF Available

On the Gravitization of Quantum Mechanics 1: Quantum State Reduction

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

This paper argues that the case for "gravitizing" quantum theory is at least as strong as that for quantizing gravity. Accordingly, the principles of general relativity must influence, and actually change, the very formalism of quantum mechanics. Most particularly, an "Einsteinian", rather than a "Newtonian" treatment of the gravitational field should be adopted, in a quantum system, in order that the principle of equivalence be fully respected. This leads to an expectation that quantum superpositions of states involving a significant mass displacement should have a finite lifetime, in accordance with a proposal previously put forward by Diósi and the author.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575
DOI 10.1007/s10701-013-9770-0
On the Gravitization of Quantum Mechanics 1:
Quantum State Reduction
Roger Penrose
Received: 7 September 2013 / Accepted: 3 December 2013 / Published online: 11 January 2014
© The Author(s) 2014. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com
Abstract This paper argues that the case for “gravitizing” quantum theory is at least
as strong as that for quantizing gravity. Accordingly, the principles of general relativity
must influence, and actually change, the very formalism of quantum mechanics. Most
particularly, an “Einsteinian”, rather than a “Newtonian” treatment of the gravitational
field should be adopted, in a quantum system, in order that the principle of equivalence
be fully respected. This leads to an expectation that quantum superpositions of states
involving a significant mass displacement should have a finite lifetime, in accordance
with a proposal previously put forward by Diósi and the author.
Keywords Quantum theory ·Linear superposition ·Measurement ·Gravitation ·
Principle of equivalence ·Diósi-Penrose state reduction
The title of this article (and of its companion, [16]) contains the phrase “gravitization
of quantum Mechanics” in contrast to the more usual “quantization of gravity”. This
reversal of wording is deliberate, of course, indicating my concern with the bringing
of quantum theory more in line with the principles of Einstein’s general relativity,
rather than attempting to make Einstein’s theory—or any more amenable theory of
gravity—into line with those of quantum mechanics (or quantum field theory).
Why am I phrasing things this way around rather than attempting to move for-
ward within that more familiar grand programme of “quantization of gravity”? I think
that people tend to regard the great twentieth century revolution of quantum theory,
as a more fundamental scheme of things than gravitational theory. Indeed, quantum
mechanics, strange as its basic principles seem to be, has no evidence against it from
accepted experiment or observation, and people tend to argue that this theory is so well
R. Penrose (B)
Mathematical Institute, Oxford, UK
e-mail: penroad@wadh.ox.ac.uk
123
558 Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575
established now that one must try to bring the whole of physics within its compass. Yet,
that other great twentieth century revolution, namely the general theory of relativity,is
also a fundamental scheme of things which, strange as its basic principles seem to be,
also has no confirmed experiments or observations that tell against it—provided that
we comply with Einstein’s introduction of a cosmological constant , in 1917, which
now appears to be needed to explain the very large-scale behavior of cosmology. So
why give quantum theory pride of place in this proposed union?
It is true that there are far more phenomena, on a human scale, which are found to
require quantum mechanics for their explanations, than are those that require general
relativity for their explanations—far, far more. Also, I think it is felt that since quantum
mechanics normally refers to very small things, and general relativity to very big
things—and we tend to think of big things as being made up of small things—then the
theory of the small things, i.e. quantum mechanics, must be the more fundamental.
However I think that this is misleading. Moreover, there is another issue that I regard
as far more important than this issue of size, namely that of the consistency of the
theory.
We know of the problems of the infinities that so frequently tend to arise in the
quantum theory of fields, and much work is geared to trying to eliminate or, at least,
deal with these infinities in a consistent and appropriate way. But, of course, general
relativity also has its infinities, these arising inevitably in the gravitational collapse to
a black hole, or perhaps of an entire universe. These are serious issues, representing
potential mathematical inconsistencies in the global applicability of each theory. These
are issues that certainly do need attending to, and it is often argued that the infinities of
one theory might be alleviated if the principles of the other theory can be appropriately
brought to bear on them.
But quantum mechanics also has another basic inconsistency, which applies to the
very basis of its founding principles. This is usually referred to as the “measurement
problem”, though I tend to prefer Tony Leggett’s terminology: the “measurement
paradox”. We can think of this as a fundamental conflict between two of the very
foundational principles of quantum mechanics, namely linearity and measurement.
Let us have a look at these issues, starting with linearity, which is an essential part of the
unitary evolution Uof the quantum state-vector. In Fig. 1, we envisage a high-energy
photon aimed at some brown object, which ejects various other objects as soon as the
photon hits it. In Fig. 2, a mirror is inserted in the path of the photon, and the reflected
photon hits a green object instead, which ejects a quite different family of objects
when hit by the photon. In Fig. 3, the mirror is replaced by a beam-splitter (effectively
a half-silvered mirror) which splits the photon state into a quantum superposition of
the two considered earlier, so that its state now becomes a superposition of being
transmitted, and aimed at the brown object, and of being reflected, and aimed at the
green object. Quantum linearity demands that the two superposed photon states, as
they emerge from the beam splitter each individually maintains the evolution that it
would have achieved in the absence of the other. If quantum linearity holds universally,
then the results of the photon impacts (for a photon of high energy) could be perfectly
evidently macroscopic events.
This issue was clearly appreciated by Schrödinger, as he illustrated the problem
with his famous “cat” thought experiment. In his version he considered a decay of
123
Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575 559
Fig. 1 Top Single direct photon hits brown object emitting many particles. Middle Direct photon kills cat.
Bottom Killed cat with environment, sad observer, sad thoughts
a radio-active atom, but it will fit in better with what I have to say if I employ a
beam-splitter instead. In Fig. 1, the brown object is replaced by a murderous device
(photon detector connected to a gun) which kills a cat. In Fig. 2, a mirror is inserted
between the photon source and the device, so the cat survives. But in Fig. 3, the mirror
is replaced by a beam-splitter so, according to quantum linearity (as demanded by U),
the resulting quantum state is one involving a superposition of a dead and a live cat!
Sometimes people object to this direct kind of description of a quantum U-evolution,
pointing out that I do not appear to have taken into consideration the complicated
environment that must be entangled with the detector and the cat, etc.—since in the
“environmental decoherence” description of quantum measurement, this environmen-
tal involvement is all-important, the unobserved degrees of freedom in the air mole-
cules, for example, having to be averaged out in our quantum descriptions. Other
objections come from the fact that no “observer” has been brought into the picture, it
being frequently argued that it is by bringing in an observer’s consciously perceived
alternatives—necessarily of one clear outcome or another—that finally breaks the
123
560 Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575
Fig. 2 Top Photon reflected, hits green object emitting different particles. Middle Photon reflected, cat
lives. Bottom Live cat, environment, happy observer, happy thoughts
chain of continuing superpositions. In Fig. 1, I have indicated the environment, with
some dots to represent air molecules, in the situation described previously in Fig. 1.
I have also included a human observer. The observer’s conscious perception of the
dead cat is depicted in a “thought bubble”, but whether or not such a thing can be
represented as part of the quantum state is not important here, because one can see
from the observer’s unhappy expression that the cat’s demise has been consciously
perceived. In Fig. 2, I have done the same, but with the mirror inserted, so that the cat
remains alive, accompanied by a different environment, represented by some slightly
differently placed dots. Now the observer consciously perceives the cat to be alive (as
indicated in the thought bubble), and this is made evident from the now happy expres-
sion on the observer’s face. None of this appears to affect the situation arising when
the mirror is replaced by a beam splitter, as depicted in Fig. 3. The environment is now
a superposition of these two possibilities, and the observer’s facial expression is now
a superposition of a smile and a frown, as the outward expression of the superposed
conscious perception of a dead and live cat.
123
Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575 561
Fig. 3 Top Beam-split photon produces both sets of particles in superposition. Middle Beam-split photon
creates Schrödinger’s cat. Bottom Schrödinger’s cat with superposed environment, observer, and thoughts
Of course, some might object that conscious perceptions are not like this, and our
normal streams of consciousness do not involve us in perceiving such gross superpo-
sitions. Of course they do not, in our actual experiences, but I see no contradiction in
this kind of conscious perception, and we need to explain why they do not occur. The
U-evolution of the standard quantum formalism, with its implied linearity, provides,
in itself, no explanation for this remarkable but utterly familiar fact.
To get the right answer for the un-superposed nature of the perceived macroscopic
world, we need to wheel in the other part of quantum formalism, namely the reduction
Rof the quantum state, according to which the state is taken as “jumping”, probabilis-
tically, to an eigenstate of some quantum operator that is taken to represent the action
of quantum measurement. If we don’t bring in Rthen we just don’t get a description
of the physical world that we all perceive. Strictly speaking, Ris simply inconsistent
with U. Whereas Uis a continuous and deterministic evolution, Ris (normally) dis-
continuous and probabilistic. Moreover, any measuring apparatus is itself constructed
from the same kind of “stuff” that constitutes all the quantum systems that are under
examination, being built from quantum particles, quantum fields and quantum forces.
123
562 Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575
Fig. 4 Clash between basic QM and GR principles
So why do we not use Uto describe its action in the course of performing a measure-
ment?
Of course there are innumerable different ways that quantum physicists and philoso-
phers try patch up this inconsistency, normally taking Uto represent an underlying
truth of Nature and regarding Ras coming about somehow as an approximation, or
as an “interpretation” of how the quantum state is supposed to be viewed in relation
to physical reality. I do not propose to enter into a discussion of any of these alterna-
tive viewpoints, but I merely present my own view, which is to regard Uitself as an
approximation to some yet-undiscovered non-linear theory. That theory would have
to yield Ras another approximation to a reality, describing how quantum measuring
devices actually evolve in a way that subtly deviates from the action of U.
Again, there are numerous different approaches to such “realistic” evolutions, and I
shall restrict attention to my own point of view [1113], which is closely similar to one
put forward, rather earlier (but motivated by somewhat different considerations), by
Diósi [3,4], namely to regard gravitation as being the key to the issue of how standard
quantum theory is to be modified. Other rather different gravitational proposals have
123
Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575 563
Fig. 5 Schrödinger’s lump; proposal for superposition decay
been proposed by [58,17]. My own approach to this is to take the principles of general
relativity as having a defining role in how quantum mechanics is to be modified. Some
of the relevant issues, relating to the idea that gravity should be involved in this
modification of quantum mechanics are listed in Fig. 4.
In Fig. 5, I have schematically depicted a more inanimate version of the Shrodinger
cat (which had been illustrated previously in Fig. 3). Instead of the cat I have placed a
simple massive (spherical) lump of material, which is moved to the right if the detector
receives a photon but remains in its original location if that photon is deflected away
from the detector, this photon having been fired from the laser on the left of the
picture, and where there is to be a beam-splitter placed between the laser and the
detector, all as before. The scheme that Diósi and I have proposed is concerned with a
superposition between two states, each of which—had it been on its own—would have
to be a stationary state. This superposition is to be taken as being unstable (owing to
some non-linear effects coming from the putative unknown “gravitization” of standard
quantum mechanics), with a lifetime τ, of the order of
123
564 Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575
Fig. 6 Schrödinger’s lump gives space-time bifurcation
τ¯
h/EG
where the quantity EGis taken as some fundamental uncertainty in the energy of the
superposed state see [12], and the above formula is taken to be an expression of the
Heisenberg time-energy uncertainty relation (in analogy with the formula relating the
lifetime of a radioactive nucleus to its mass/energy uncertainty).
The quantity EGis the gravitational self-energy of the difference between the mass
(expectation) distributions of the two stationary states in superposition. (If the two
states merely differ from one another by a rigid translation, then we can calculate EG
as the gravitational interaction energy, namely the energy it would cost to separate
two copies of the lump, initially considered to be coincident and then moved to their
separated locations in the superposition.) The calculation of EGis carried out entirely
within the framework of Newtonian mechanics, as we are considering the masses
involved as being rather small and moved very slowly, so that general-relativistic
corrections can be ignored.
Nevertheless, we are to consider that regarding EGas an energy uncertainty comes
from considerations of general-relativistic principles. In Fig. 6, I have schematically
123
Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575 565
Fig. 7 Space-time bifurcation and one branch dies
illustrated the two space-times involved, being taken as more-or-less identical until
the lump locations begin to separate. When the separation becomes significant, in an
appropriate quantum-gravity sense, then one branch dies off and the other survives
(Fig. 7). The time-scale for this to happen (according to the τ¯
h/EGformula) is
estimated as being a measure of the amount of space-time difference (shown shaded
in Fig. 8) in the regions where the two space-times in superposition differ from one
another by an amount of order unity when measured in Planck units (i.e. taking c=¯
h=
G=1). Thus the instability that results in just one of the space-time branches surviving
sets in at the kind of scale when the space-time difference is of order unity. This
measure of space-time difference is calculated according to the standard symplectic
measure that can be estimated by considerations of linearized gravitational theory see
[11].
Another, rather more rigorous, way of obtaining the τ¯
h/EGestimate is to
appeal to the principle of equivalence see [15] which is the basic foundational prin-
ciple of general relativity. Let us first imagine a table-top quantum experiment being
performed, and we wish to calculate the wavefunction of the quantum system under
123
566 Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575
Fig. 8 Decay after Planck-scale difference geometry measure
consideration, so that Schrödinger’s equation can then be used to calculate the time-
evolution of this state. In this particular case, we are interested in taking the Earth’s
gravitational field into consideration. We may envisage two different procedures for
doing this (illustrated in Fig. 9). The first (with the green coordinates) would be the
conventional quantum physicist’s approach, where we simply include a term in the
quantum Hamiltonian representing the Newtonian potential of the gravitational field,
where we are just treating the gravitational field as providing an “ordinary force” in
the same way that we would for any other force (such as an electric or magnetic force).
This procedure gives us what I shall call the Newtonian wavefunction ψ(written in
green in Fig. 9). The second procedure is more in the spirit of Einstein’s general
relativity, where we imagine doing our quantum mechanics in a freely falling frame
(purple coordinates), and in this frame there is no gravitational field, the accelerated
fall cancelling it out, and our Einsteinian wavefunction (written in purple in Fig. 9),
described in terms of these free-fall coordinates, evolves according to a Schrödinger
equation whose quantum Hamiltonian has no term representing the gravitational field.
123
Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575 567
Fig. 9 Principle of equivalence leads to phase difference
We would expect these two quantum evolutions to agree with one another—and,
indeed a famous experiment performed in 1975, by Colella, Overhauser and Werner
did confirm that Einstein’s principle of equivalence is indeed respected by quantum
mechanics in this respect. In fact, a direct calculation shows that the Newtonian and
Einsteinian wavefunctions are related to each other simply by one being a phase
multiple of the other. This multiple is explicitly shown in Fig. 9(outlined with a yellow
broken line), 3/4 of the way down the picture for the dynamics of a single particle,
and at the bottom of the picture for the dynamics of a system of many particles.
Now, surely, this shows that standard quantum mechanics is perfectly consistent
with Einstein’s equivalence principle, since an overall phase multiplier for the wave-
function ought not to affect the interpretation in terms of probabilities, when a mea-
surement (R) is performed on the system. However, there is an additional subtlety
here, because if we examine this particular phase factor we see that it contains a term
in t3in the exponent (with coefficient proportional the square g2of the gravitational
acceleration vector
g)where t(=T) is the time in both coordinate systems. Because of
this non-linear dependence of the phase factor on t, we find that the notion of positive
frequency differs in the two viewpoints (Newtonian and Einsteinian). Accordingly, the
123
568 Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575
two different reference systems, the Newtonian one and the Einsteinian one, refer to
two different quantum field theory vacua.
The fact that physics in an accelerating frame is described by a different vacuum
from that in an unaccelerated one is familiar in relativity, where according to what is
called the “Unruh effect” [2,18] the accelerated vacuum is a thermal vacuum with a
temperature ¯
hg/2πck.(kbeing Boltzmann’s constant, etc.). Here, we are considering
the Galilean limit c→∞, so we see that the temperature goes to zero. Nevertheless,
the accelerated vacuum remains different from the unaccelerated one even in this limit,
although in this limiting case the accelerated vacuum is not a thermal one, but the phase
discrepancy between the Newtonian and Einsteinian wavefunctions agrees with that
shown in Fig. 9(confirmed in a private communication from B. S. Kay).
Although, strictly speaking, the notion of alternative vacua is a feature of quantum
field theory, rather than of the “Galilean” non-relativistic quantum mechanics that
is under consideration here, the issue has direct relevance to the latter also. Standard
quantum mechanics indeed requires that energies remain positive (i.e. that frequencies
remain positive). This is not normally a problem, because the quantum dynamics
governed by a positive-definite Hamiltonian will preserve this condition. But in the
situation arising here we appear to be forced into the prospect of its violation unless
the vacua are kept separate, the presence of the t3term coming about through the
adoption of the Einsteinian perspective with regrd to the gravitational field.
In the particular experimental situation just considered, where the gravitational field
is external and given, this difference in vacua is of no particular concern, since we
can use one or the other description consistently without any discrepancy between
the two choices of vacuum, as regards the results of measurement. But when the
gravitational field itself becomes involved in a quantum superposition, the issue is
more serious. In Fig. 10 I have illustrated this kind of situation, where a massive
sphere is placed in a quantum linear superposition of two separate locations. We are to
consider how quantum mechanics is to be used to treat this situation in accordance with
the (preferred) Einsteinian viewpoint. The problem now is that in order to describe this
superposition of gravitational fields, according to this viewpoint, we are confronted
with the problem of superposing states that relate to two different vacua.
Strictly speaking this is illegal, according to the rules of quantum field theory, as
the two states that are proposed to be under superposition belong to different Hilbert
spaces. The general problem that arises would be that when we try to form an inner
product between a state described in relation to one vacuum with a state described in
relation to a different vacuum, we tend to get a divergence which violates the very rules
that Hilbert spaces are supposed to satisfy (that inner products should be finite num-
bers), and for which the probability interpretation (Born rule) now makes nonsense.
Nevertheless, we might take the view that such things come about merely because
some mathematical idealization has been made (such as is the case for momentum
states, for example, which are, strictly, not Hilbert space members) and that if full
details of the situation are properly encoded, then such divergences would not occur.
But how are we to deal with this when the very Hilbert spaces are diiferent, so that
superpositions cannot actually be performed? An analogous situation might come from
some mathematical treatments of, for example, a superconductor, where one might
consider the superconducting state to be described in relation to a vacuum different
123
Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575 569
Fig. 10 Displaced mass: illegal superposition of different vacua
from the standard one. Of course, if an actual physical superconductor were in a quan-
tum state belonging to a Hilbert space with a different vacuum from that of the Hilbert
space describing the system before the superconducting state were set up, then there
would be no way to build a superconductor, since transitions from one Hilbert space
to another, each with a different vacuum, would be “against the rules” of standard
quntum field theory.
In the case of our superposed states of displaced massive spheres, we must imag-
ine that the “illegality” in performing the superposition between states from different
Hilbert states would take some time (τ) to make itself manifest in the physics. It
has been hard, so far, to see how to make this completely unambiguous, but it seems
that one can make a preliminary estimate by applying the Heisenberg time-energy
uncertainty principle, rather in the way that this is done for a radioactive nucleus.
For such a nucleus, there is a (mass-energy) uncertainty that is in reciprocal relation
to its lifetime. Here the argument is similar (the converse of this), where we pro-
pose to estimate a superposition’s lifetime from a fundamental energy uncertainty
that it necessarily possesses by virtue of the clash between the general-relativistic and
123
570 Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575
quantum principles that are being invoked in relation to the description of stationary
gravitational fields in quantum linear superposition. We can try to estimate the error
that is involved in trying to form a stationary state out of the superposition of loca-
tions, where we take the view that the divergences involved in the superposition will
come about from the coefficient of t3in the “discrepancy” phase factor that we see in
Fig. 10, namely
(M/3¯
h)(
g2
g1)2.
If we take the integral of this expression over space, at one moment of the time t(=T),
as a measure of this error, then we obtain the quantity EGdescribed earlier (the grav-
itational self-energy of the difference between the two mass distributions involved.
(See [12] for this derivation and for an alternative motivation for this energy uncer-
tainty.) When EGis substituted into Heisenberg’s time-energy uncertainty formula,
we get the aforementioned estimate of the lifetime of such a superposed state, before
it spontaneously decays into one alternative or the other.
One point should be made clear about this proposal [3,4,11,12], namely that all R
processes of state-reduction are to be the result of actions of this gravitational proposal.
In a deliberate measurement by means of a conventional quantum detector, Rwould
be triggered by some movement of mass within the detector, sufficient to reduce the
state within a very small period of time τ. In other situations, where there is no
deliberate measurement of the quantum system, but some considerable entanglement
with an extended random environment, the major mass displacement would likely
come about from the mass displacement of material within that environment, so when
the environment state collapses to one or the other so does that of the quantum system
itself, because the two parts, being entangled, both reduce together. This makes contact
with the point of view whereby Ris deemed to occur via environmental decoherence,
but now we have a clear ontology of an objectively real reduction of the quantum state,
and we do not have to appeal to some vague concept of the environmental degrees of
freedom being, in some sense, “unobservable”.
In order to get an impression of the role of EGwe can first think of the case of
a solid spherical ball of radius a, made from some uniform massive material of total
mass m, where the ball is in a superposition of two locations, differing by a distance
b. See Fig, 11. We use a Newtonian calculation to work out the value of EG, obtaining
the expression depicted in the figure. The only point of particular relevance here, in
this expression, is the fact that for a displacement successively from coincidence to
contact of the two instance of the sphere, the value of EGis already nearly 2/3 of the
value it would reach for a displacement all the way out to infinity. Thus, for a uniformly
solid body like this, we do not gain much by considering displacements in which the
two instances of the body are moved apart by a distance of more than roughly its own
diameter.
Of course, ordinary material is not really uniform in mass distribution, like this,
but consists of huge numbers of nuclei where most of the mass is concentrated, where
we might try to consider that the actual mass distribution is distributed among precise
point-like locations of the quarks and electrons—marked in brown, in the middle of
Fig. 12. However, when we then try to calculate EGby considering a very slightly
123
Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575 571
Fig. 11 Newtonian self-energy for displaced uniform balls
shifted mass distribution, taking the difference between the two (the mass difference
distiribution indicated by the brown–green difference shown in Fig. 13), then we get
an infinite answer if the mass distributions are actually taken as the delta functions
representing these point-particle locations. Such an infinite answer for EGwould give
azero decay time, in other words an instantaneous reduction of any superposed state
of actual material—and we would have no quantum mechanics!
Clearly this is not the correct answer, and indeed the procedure has not been carried
out correctly, because (as noted earlier) the procedure of calculating EGapplies only
when each of the two states in superposition is actually stationary. A state involv-
ing delta function mass distributions like this would not be stationary, according to
Schrödinger’s equation, since the delta-function mass distributions would instantly
spread out from these locations. What we need to do is first to solve the stationary
Schrödinger equation for the material in our object. Even this would lead to a nonsense,
however, if carried out strictly, for an actual stationary state, since such a state would
have to be spread out over the entire universe, and we would now get the opposite
problem of obtaining a zero answer for EG.
123
572 Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575
Fig. 12 Different models of mass concentration
What one tends to do, in practice, when considering the wavefunction of a stationary
state is to factor out the mass centre, regarding the wavefunction to be concerned with
distances relative to the mass centre. This procedure is a little artificial, and one can
adopt the more systematic procedure of modifying the Schrödinger equation in the
form of the self-coupled “Schrödinger-Newton equation”, for a wavefunction ψ, which
incorporates an additional term in the Hamiltonian, that is given by the gravitational
potential due to the expectation value of the mass distribution in ψitself see [10,13].
The “Newton” term prevents the stationary solutions from being infinitely spread out.
In situations of relevance here, to a reasonable enough approximation, this amounts to
the aforementioned procedure of factoring out the mass centre, and then just solving the
Schrödinger equation. This saves us from having to solve the non-linear Schrödinger-
Newton equation in detail in order to calculate EG. On the other hand, incorporating
the Schrödinger-Newton equation has another theoretical importance in also providing
the possible stable stationary states to which a quantum superposition can reduce by
the operation of R.
123
Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575 573
Fig. 13 Different models of displaced mass concentrations
It might be presumed, since we are looking at space-time differences whose mea-
sure is of the order of the extremely tiny Planck scale, that nothing of observable
consequence would be likely to come from considertions of this kind. Indeed, experi-
ments aimed at testing the influences of quantum mechanics on space-time structure—
the presumed consequences of “quantum gravity” in the usual interpretation of that
term—would be enormously far from what can be achieved by current technology.
However, we are here concerned with the role of gravitational principles on the struc-
ture of quantum mechanics, not the other way about, where the experimental situation
is very different. One way of looking at this issue is to realize that the scales at
which quantum mechanics is expected to influence space-time structure would indeed
be the absurdly tiny Planck length (¯
hG/c3)1/21.6×1035m and Planck time
(¯
hG/c3)1/25.4×1044s, these being so very tiny, compared with ordinary scales,
because they involve dividing a very small quantity by a very large one. However, the
quantity of relevance to our considerations of the “gravitization of quantum mechan-
ics” under consideration here is τ¯
h/EG,which is one very small quantity divided
by another very small quantity (since EGis scaled by the gravitational constant), which
123
574 Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575
Fig. 14 Bouwmeester experiment (schematic)
need be neither very small nor very large. Accordingly, one must examine the quanti-
ties involved in any proposed experiment very carefully, to see whether the time scale
τturns out to be one that comes within the scope of the experiment being envisaged.
In Fig. 14, I have sketched the rough idea see [9] underlying an experiment that has
been under development by Dirk Bouwmeester and colleagues, at the Universities of
Leiden (Netherlands) and California (Santa Barbara, CA, USA), for several years now,
where a tiny cubical mirror (105m in dimension) is to be put into a superposition of
two different locations, differing from one another by about the diameter of an atomic
nucleus. This is to be achieved by multiple impacts (106of them) by a single photon,
which has been beam-split into a quantum superposition of two alternative routes, in
only one of which the photon hits the tiny mirror. This mirror is to be maintained in
its superposed state for seconds or perhaps up to minutes which, depending on the
details, might be a sufficient time τfor the decay of the superposition to take place
(according to the aforementioned state-reduction proposal). This spontaneous state
reduction could be tested by subsequently reversing the photon routes, and observing
whether there is consequent lack of phase coherence between the two branches of the
123
Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575 575
beam-split photon, such breaking of phase coherence leading to the possible activation
of the detector at the top of the picture. Clearly there are enormous difficulties in
eliminating unwanted possibilities of decoherence, etc., but there appears to be a
reasonable prospect of a result from experiments of this kind within the next decade.
Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License
which permits any use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author(s) and
the source are credited.
References
1. Colella, R., Overhause, A.W., Werner, S.A.: Observation of gravitationally induced quantum interfer-
ence. Phys. Rev. Lett. 34, 1472 (1975)
2. Davies, P.C.W.: Scalar production in Schwarzschild and Rindler metrics. J. Phys. A. 8, 609 (1975)
3. Diósi, L.: A universal master equation for the gravitational violation of quantum mechanics. Phys.
Lett. 120A, 377–81 (1987)
4. Diósi, L.: Models for universal reduction of macroscopic quantum fluctuations. Phys. Rev. A40, 1165–
1174 (1989)
5. Károlyházy, F.: Gravitation and quantum mechanics of macroscopic bodies. Nuovo Cim. A 42, 390
(1966)
6. Károlyházy, F.: Gravitation and quantum mechanics of macroscopic bodies. Magyar Fizikai Polyoirat
12, 24 (1974)
7. Károlyházy, F., Frenkel, A., Lukács, B.: On the possible role of gravity on the reduction of the wave
function. In: Penrose, R., Isham, C.J. (eds.) Quantum Concepts in Space and Time, pp. 109–128.
Oxford University Press, Oxford (1986)
8. Kibble, T.W.B.: Is a semi-classical theory of gravity viable? In: Isham, C.J., Penrose, R., Sciama, D.W.
(eds.) Quantum Gravity 2: A Second Oxford Symposium, pp. 63–80. Oxford University Press, Oxford
(1981)
9. Marshall, W., Simon, C., Penrose, R., Bouwmeester, D.: Towards quantum superpositions of a mirror.
Phys. Rev. Lett. 91(13–16), 130401 (2003)
10. Moroz, I.M., Penrose, R., and Tod, K.P.: Spherically-symmetric solutions of the Schrödinger-Newton
equations. Class. Quantum Grav. 15, 2733–2742 (1998)
11. Penrose, R.: Gravity and quantum mechanics. In: Gleiser, R.J., Kozameh, C.N., Moreschi, O.M. (eds.)
General Relativity and Gravitation 13. Part 1: Plenary Lectures 1992, pp. 179–189. Institute of Physics
Publishing, Bristol, Philadelphia (1998).
12. Penrose, R.: On gravity’s role in quantum state reduction. Gen. Relativ. Gravit. 28, 581–600 (1996)
13. Penrose, R.: Quantum computation, entanglement and state-reduction. Phil. Trans. Roy Soc. (Lond.)
A356, 1927–1939 (1998)
14. Penrose, R.: The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the Universe. Jonathan Cape,
London (2004)
15. Penrose, R.: Black holes, quantum theory and cosmology (Fourth International WorkshopDICE 2008).
J. Phys. Conf. Ser. 174, 012001 (2009)
16. Penrose, R.: On the gravitization of quantum mechanics 2: conformal cyclic cosmology. Found. Phys.
(2014). doi:10.1007/s10701-013-9763- z
17. Percival, I.C.: Quantum spacetime fluctuations and primary state diffusion. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A451,
503–13 (1995)
18. Unruh, W.G.: Notes on black hole evaporation. Phys. Rev. D 14, 870 (1976)
123
... The virtual particles of the field can in this manner also provide an information exchange between physical reality and the non-zero local field to which they belong by the phenomenon of resonance ( Figure 4). Even the force of gravity, a yet poorly understood phenomenon, may be related to this field, because of its retarding effect on the movement of material: the phenomenon of inertia (Penrose 2014;Setterfield 2017) suggests that quantum gravity at the Planck-scale level is instrumental in the capture of quantum information in our brain (Meijer and Korf 2013;Meijer et al 2020;Meijer 2023). Typical features of quantum physics are depicted in Figure 3. ...
... This matrix of such space units is usually called quantum foam or spacetime foam (Wheeler 1994) bearing units that function as operators. Known examples of such space elements are twistors (Penrose 2014), being clearly related to nested torus geometry. Such units are supposed to operate on every fractal scale, from very small (Planck scale) to very large (black holes), and can be conceived as the collection points of the various force fields: gravity, dark energy, zero-point energy, electromagnetism, and Higgs fields, etc. ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper pays special attention to the interfacing of the field of universal consciousness and our personal brain in relation to a potential afterlife and postulates a toroidal event horizon workspace of the brain that allows a symmetric 4-Dimensional (4-D) to 3-Dimensional (3-D) quantum information flux and holographic personal memory integration. The geometry of a 3-D brain, embedded in a 4-D realm, may explain the phenomena of functional brain binding, qualia, intuition, serendipity, synchronicity, extra-sensory perception, and other well-established parapsychological phenomena. Brain function is conceptualized as guided by the Zero-point Energy (ZPE) Field (ZPF)-derived pilot waves that support consciousness, even in the absence of neuronal activity, such as in Near-Death Experiences (NDE). The brain's toroidal organization exhibits quaternionic dynamics and thereby allows an opening to 4-D geometry and, consequently, to universal consciousness and the ZPF. This personal holographic workspace, that is associated with but not reducible to the brain, collects active information in a "brain event horizon," as an internal and fully integral model of the self. At death or transition of our material body, this personal mental knowledge domain dissociates from the body, yet it is retained because entangled and meaningful quantum information can never be destroyed. In NDE, this uncoupling is only temporal, but reveals universal consciousness in a fully transparent manner, since in this condition non-neuronal information processing is preserved. This preservation occurs through fractal semi-harmonic frequencies, from the ZPE field, that reflect an entangled personal register of each conscious being. The proposed concept, therefore, contradicts the tentative and promissory materialist solution to the mind-body problem. Instead, it substantiates the notion that the brain can act as a kind of "receiver" by filtering (sub)conscious states through holographic resonance with universal consciousness through specific coherent oscillation domains in the body. Yet, it is recognized that our self-consciousness can also act as a damping filter for information from this universal knowledge field. The latter aspect of a "dual filter theory" is apparently perturbed at states of modified brain function such as NDE, deep meditation, and use of psychomimetic drugs, that all expose us to an unknown cosmic perspective. The presence of a mental, field-receptive, resonant workspace, might be termed our "supervening double" (or "soul," not implying religious doctrine), and provides an interpretation framework for widely reported but poorly understood transpersonal conscious states. These may even imply that death can be conceived as a transition to another state of existence, yet we realize that all of us already belong to such an eternal domain in our present lives. Therefore, the present model may imply the potential for the survival of individual consciousness, qualifying conscious individuals as designated survivors and eternal beings. La survie de la conscience et l'anticipation d'une vie après la mort d'après la physique actuelle Résumé Cet article accorde une attention particulière à l'interface entre le champ de la conscience universelle et notre cerveau individuel en relation avec une éventuelle vie après la mort. Il postule un espace de travail toroïde de l'horizon des événements du cerveau qui permet un flux d'information quantique symétrique de 4 dimensions (4-D) à 3 dimensions (3-D) et une intégration holographique de la mémoire individuelle. La géométrie d'un cerveau tridimensionnel intégrée dans un domaine quadridimensionnel peut expliquer les phénomènes de liaison fonctionnelle du cerveau, de qualia, d'intuition, de sérendipité, de synchronicité, de perception extra-sensorielle et d'autres phénomènes parapsychologiques avérés. La fonction cérébrale est conceptualisée comme étant guidée par des ondes pilotes dérivées du champ d'énergie du point zéro (en anglais : ZPE Zero-point Energy, ZPF Zero-point Energy Field) qui assistent la conscience même en l'absence d'activité neuronale, comme dans les expériences de mort imminente (EMI). L'organisation toroïde du cerveau présente une dynamique de quaternions permettant ainsi une ouverture à la géométrie quadridimensionnelle et, par conséquent, à la conscience universelle et au ZPF. Cet espace de travail holographique personnel-à savoir associé au cerveau mais non réductible à celui-ci-recueille des informations actives dans un "horizon d'événements cérébraux", en qualité de modèle interne et totalement intégral du soi. Lors de la mort, ou transition, de notre corps matériel, ce domaine de connaissance mentale individuelle se dissocie du corps physique, mais il est conservé parce que l'information quantique intrinsèque, significative, ne peut être détruite. Dans l'EMI, ce découplage n'est que temporel, mais il révèle la conscience universelle de manière totalement transparente, puisque dans cet état, le traitement de l'information non-neuronale est conservé. Ceci se produit par le biais de fréquences semi-harmoniques fractales, issues du champ d'énergie du point zéro, qui reflètent un registre personnel intriqué de chaque être conscient. Le concept proposé contredit donc l'option de solution matérialiste, éphémère, momentanée, au problème corps-esprit. En effet, il étaye la notion selon laquelle le cerveau peut agir comme une sorte de "récepteur" en filtrant les états (sub)conscients par résonance holographique avec la conscience universelle, à travers des domaines d'oscillation cohérente spécifiques situés dans notre corps. Ceci étant, nous savons actuellement que notre conscience de soi peut également agir comme un filtre d'amortissement pour les informations provenant de ce champ de connaissance universelle. Ce dernier aspect de la "théorie du double filtre" est apparemment perturbé dans des états de fonction cérébrale modifiée, tels l'EMI, la méditation profonde et l'utilisation de drogues psychomimétiques, du moment qu'ils exposent à une perspective cosmique inconnue. La présence d'un espace de travail mental, réceptif au champ et résonnant, que nous pouvons appeler "double survenant" (ou "âme", sans toutefois impliquer de doctrine religieuse) fournit un cadre d'interprétation pour les états de conscience trans-personnels fréquemment signalés mais encore mal compris. Ces modèles peuvent même impliquer que la mort peut être conçue comme une transition vers un autre état d'existence, bien que nous puissions nous rendre compte, de notre vivant, que nous appartenons tous déjà à un tel domaine éternel. Par conséquent, le modèle que nous proposons peut impliquer le potentiel de survie de la conscience individuelle, qualifiant les individus conscients de survivants désignés et d'êtres éternels.
... Accordingly, an intense theoretical effort was devoted to develop consistent non-linear and stochastic modifications of the Schrödinger dynamics, such as solving the measurement problem while preserving the quantum mechanical predictions for microscopic objects. The two major approaches are Continuous Spontaneous Localization models (CSLs) [15][16][17][18][19] and the Diósi-Penrose model (DP) [20][21][22][23][24]. An unavoidable effect related to spontaneous collapse consists of a faint electromagnetic radiation emission, called spontaneous radiation, which is not predicted by the standard QT. ...
Article
Full-text available
In this work, we report on tests performed with an experimental apparatus prototype based on a broad-energy germanium detector aimed at investigating topical, foundational issues in quantum mechanics: i.e., possible violations of the spin-statistics connection and models of dynamical wave function collapse. Our recent phenomenological analyses demonstrated the importance of pushing the research of new physics signal, predicted in these fields, to an energy range below 10 keV. We describe the development of the dedicated data acquisition system and of the pulse shape discrimination algorithm, which have already allowed us to get a factor two improvement in the lower energy threshold. Future plans are discussed to further improve the lower energy threshold to the level of a few keV.
... The origin of such a stochasticity might be interpreted as pseudo-random rather than truly indeterministic since the noise that is introduced into the system dynamics could be a reflection of the underspecified state of the environment with which the system is interacting, rather like the noise experienced by an open system like a Brownian particle in classical mechanics. Within such a framework we consider the stochastically evolving density matrix to be a physically real property of the quantum system [36][37][38][39][40][41][42][43], instead of merely a tool to calculate the average evolution or representing the (subjective) state of our knowledge [44][45][46][47][48][49][50][51][52], which is still the subject of debate, also in the context of quantum trajectories [17,[53][54][55][56][57]. Nevertheless, results obtained from QSD are consistent with the Born rule, and are therefore compatible with the axioms of quantum mechanics. ...
Article
Full-text available
We investigate the quantum Zeno effect (QZE) in spin 1/2, spin 1 and spin 3/2 open quantum systems undergoing Rabi oscillations, revealing unexplored features for the spin 1 and spin 3/2 systems. The systems interact with an environment designed to perform continuous measurements of an observable, driving the systems stochastically towards one of the eigenstates of the corresponding operator. The system-environment coupling constant represents the strength of the measurement. Stochastic quantum trajectories are generated by unravelling a Markovian Lindblad master equation using the quantum state diffusion formalism. These are regarded as a more appropriate representation of system behaviour than consideration of the averaged evolution since the latter can mask the effect of measurement. Complete positivity is maintained and thus the trajectories can be considered as physically meaningful. The QZE is investigated over a range of measurement strengths. Increasing the strength leads to greater system dwell in the vicinity of the eigenstates of the measured observable and lengthens the time taken by the system to return to that eigenstate, thus the QZE emerges. For very strong measurement, the Rabi oscillations resemble randomly occurring near-instantaneous jumps between eigenstates. The trajectories followed by the quantum system are heavily dependent on the measurement strength which other than slowing down and adding noise to the Rabi oscillations, changes the paths taken in spin phase space from a circular precession into elaborate figures-of-eight. For spin 1 and spin 3/2 systems, the measurement strength determines which eigenstates are explored and the QZE is stronger when the system dwells in the vicinity of certain eigenstates compared to others.
... Conformal invariance is a good candidate for the role of a fundamental symmetry, which, along with other symmetries, increases the likelihood of the Universe emerging from "nothing" [1]. Similar ideas are supported by many researchers such as Roger Penrose [2] and Gerard 't Hooft [3]. ...
Article
Full-text available
The action of an ideal fluid in Euler variables with a variable number of particles is used for the phenomenological description of the processes of particle creation in strong external fields. It has been demonstrated that the conformal invariance of the creation law imposes quite strict restrictions on the possible types of sources. It is shown that combinations with the particle number density in the creation law can be interpreted as dark matter within the framework of this model.
Article
Full-text available
Physics is living an era of unprecedented cross-fertilization among the different areas of science. In this perspective review, we discuss the manifold impact that state-of-the-art cold and ultracold-atomic platforms can have in fundamental and applied science through the development of platforms for quantum simulation, computation, metrology and sensing. We illustrate how the engineering of table-top experiments with atom technologies is engendering applications to understand problems in condensed matter and fundamental physics, cosmology and astrophysics, unveil foundational aspects of quantum mechanics, and advance quantum chemistry and the emerging field of quantum biology. In this journey, we take the perspective of two main approaches, i.e., creating quantum analogues and building quantum simulators, highlighting that independently of the ultimate goal of a universal quantum computer to be met, the remarkable transformative effects of these achievements remain unchanged. We wish to convey three main messages. First, this atom-based quantum technology enterprise is signing a new era in the way quantum technologies are used for fundamental science, even beyond the advancement of knowledge, which is characterised by truly cross-disciplinary research, extended interplay between theoretical and experimental thinking, and intersectoral approach. Second, quantum many-body physics is unavoidably taking center stage in frontier’s science. Third, quantum science and technology progress will have capillary impact on society, meaning this effect is not confined to isolated or highly specialized areas of knowledge, but is expected to reach and have a pervasive influence on a broad range of society aspects: while this happens, the adoption of a responsible research and innovation approach to quantum technologies is mandatory, to accompany citizens in building awareness and future scaffolding. Following on all the above reflections, this perspective review is thus aimed at scientists active or interested in interdisciplinary research, providing the reader with an overview of the current status of these wide fields of research where cold and ultracold-atomic platforms play a vital role in their description and simulation.
Article
Full-text available
This document presents a summary of the 2023 Terrestrial Very-Long-Baseline Atom Interferometry Workshop hosted by CERN. The workshop brought together experts from around the world to discuss the exciting developments in large-scale atom interferometer (AI) prototypes and their potential for detecting ultralight dark matter and gravitational waves. The primary objective of the workshop was to lay the groundwork for an international TVLBAI proto-collaboration. This collaboration aims to unite researchers from different institutions to strategize and secure funding for terrestrial large-scale AI projects. The ultimate goal is to create a roadmap detailing the design and technology choices for one or more kilometer--scale detectors, which will be operational in the mid-2030s. The key sections of this report present the physics case and technical challenges, together with a comprehensive overview of the discussions at the workshop together with the main conclusions.
Chapter
Standard General Relativity assumes that, in the absence of classical matter sources, spacetime is empty. This chapter considers and analyses the new behaviours of the gravitational field that appear when one substitutes this emptiness by a reactive vacuum, stemming in particular from the idea of vacuum provided by quantum field theory. We restrict our study to spherically symmetric configurations, and take a simple free quantum scalar field as a proxy to more complicated formulations. Our analysis is split into a study of static and of dynamical configurations. Under the assumption of staticity, we find and describe the different asymptotically flat self-consistent solutions that appear when using a vacuum Renormalised Stress-Energy Tensor (RSET) as an additional source in the Einstein equations. Of particular interest is the discovery that, as opposed to standard general relativity, the new theory naturally contains static ultracompact stellar configurations which could observationally be mistaken for black holes (BHs). Then, in our study of dynamical configurations, we investigate the possibility of these same vacuum effects changing the internal gravitational processes after an initial gravitational collapse in a way which shows a path towards forming the aforementioned ultracompact configurations. This has lead us to analyse several dynamical situations seldom contemplated in the literature. Of special relevance, we find that the inner horizon that all realistic BHs should contain could inflate outwards quickly enough to meet the outer one before any appreciable Hawking evaporation has taken place.
Article
Full-text available
Given a unitary evolution U on a multipartite quantum system and an ensemble of initial states, how well can U be simulated by local operations and classical communication (LOCC) on that ensemble? We answer this question by establishing a general, efficiently computable upper bound on the maximal LOCC simulation fidelity—what we call an “LOCC inequality.” We then apply our findings to the fundamental setting where U implements a quantum Newtonian Hamiltonian over a gravitationally interacting system. Violation of our LOCC inequality can rule out the LOCCness of the underlying evolution, thereby establishing the nonclassicality of the gravitational dynamics, which can no longer be explained by a local classical field. As a prominent application of this scheme we study systems of quantum harmonic oscillators initialized in coherent states following a normal distribution and interacting via Newtonian gravity, and discuss a possible physical implementation with torsion pendula. One of our main technical contributions is the analytical calculation of the above LOCC inequality for this family of systems. As opposed to existing tests based on the detection of gravitationally mediated entanglement, our proposal works with coherent states alone, and thus it does not require the generation of largely delocalized states of motion nor the detection of entanglement, which is never created at any point in the process. Published by the American Physical Society 2024
Article
Spontaneous unitarity violations were recently proposed as a cause of objective quantum state reduction. This complements proposals based on stochastic modifications of Schrödinger's equation, but also differs from them in several aspects. Here, we formalize the description of models for spontaneous unitarity violation, and show that they generically imply models of dynamical quantum state reduction driven by colored noise. We present a formalism for exploring such models as well as a prescription for enforcing explicit norm-preservation, and we show that the resulting pure state dynamics is described by a modified von Neumann-Liouville equation which in a particular limit reduces to the Gorini-Kossakowski-Sudarshan-Lindblad master equations. We additionally show adherence to Born's rule emerging in the same limit from a physical constraint relating fluctuating and dissipating components of the model.
Article
Full-text available
The 2nd Law of thermodynamics was driven by the Big Bang being extraordinary special, with hugely suppressed gravitational degrees of freedom. This cannot have been simply the result of a conventional quantum gravity. Conformal cyclic cosmology proposes a different picture, of a classical evolution from an aeon preceding our own. The ultimate Hawking evaporation of black holes is key to the 2nd Law and requires information loss, violating unitarity in a strongly gravitational context.
Article
Some general foundational issues of quantum mechanics are considered and are related to aspects of quantum computation. Th importance of quantum entanglement and quantum information is discussed and their curious acausal properties are addressed. The question of quantum state reduction is also considered, and a specific suggestion for a gravitational state–reductio scheme is put forward. A general proposal for an experiment to test this scheme is also suggested.
Article
We have used a neutron interferometer to observe the quantum-mechanical phase shift of neutrons caused by their interaction with Earth's gravitational field.
Article
This paper examines various aspects of black-hole evaporation. A two-dimensional model is investigated where it is shown that using fermion-boson cancellation on the stress-energy tensor reduces the energy outflow to zero, while other noncovariant techniques give the Hawking result. A technique for replacing the collapse by boundary conditions on the past horizon is developed which retains the essential features of the collapse while eliminating some of the difficulties. This set of boundary conditions is also suggested as the most natural set for a preexistent black hole. The behavior of particle detectors under acceleration is investigated where it is shown that an accelerated detector even in flat spacetime will detect particles in the vacuum. The similarity of this case with the behavior of a detector near the black hole is brought out, and it is shown that a geodesic detector near the horizon will not see the Hawking flux of particles. Finally, the work of Berger, Chitre, Nutku, and Moncrief on scalar geons is corrected, and the spherically symmetric coupled scalar-gravitation Hamiltonian is presented in the hope that someone can apply it to the problem of black-hole evaporation.
Article
Contents: 1. The problem of the superposition principle. 2. The possible role of gravity. 3. The imprecision in space-time structure. 4. Wave propagation. 5. Microscopic and macroscopic behaviour. 6. Possible experiments. 7. Conclusion.
Article
As part of a programme in which quantum state reduction is understood as a gravitational phenomenon, we consider the Schrödinger-Newton equations. For a single particle, this is a coupled system consisting of the Schrödinger equation for the particle moving in its own gravitational field, where this is generated by its own probability density via the Poisson equation. Restricting to the spherically-symmetric case, we find numerical evidence for a discrete family of solutions, everywhere regular, and with normalizable wavefunctions. The solutions are labelled by the non-negative integers, the nth solution having n zeros in the wavefunction. Furthermore, these are the only globally defined solutions. Analytical support is provided for some of the features found numerically.
Article
The procedure used recently by Hawking (1975) to demonstrate the creation of massless particles by black holes is applied to the Rindler coordinate system in flat space-time. The result is that an observer who undergoes a uniform acceleration kappa apparently sees a fixed surface radiate with a temperature of kappa /2 pi . Some implications of this result are discussed.