ChapterPDF Available

Abstract

Many personal reports from experienced meditators exist on how subjective time slows down in meditation practice as well as in everyday life. However, hardly any empirical work exists regarding this exceptional experience. In this theoretical chapter we discuss cognitive and neural models of time perception. We aim at showing how the subjective passage of time and duration are modified by functional states of mindfulness, i.e. by attention regulation, body awareness and emotion regulation. The ability of expert mindfulness meditators to focus more strongly on sensory experiences and to be more strongly aware of feelings and of body states leads to a slowing down of time in the present moment. Moreover, as a consequence of more efficient attention regulation capacities, memory formation is enhanced which in retrospect leads to a subjective lengthening of past duration. Empirical studies concerning time perception in meditation practitioners would help to understand meditative states and at the same time would foster knowledge on cognitive-emotional as well as neural processes underlying the experience of time.
199
S. Schmidt and H. Walach (eds.), Meditation – Neuroscientifi c Approaches
and Philosophical Implications, Studies in Neuroscience, Consciousness and Spirituality 2,
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-01634-4_11, © Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2014
Abstract Many personal reports from experienced meditators exist on how subjective
time slows down in meditation practice as well as in everyday life. However, hardly
any empirical work exists regarding this exceptional experience. In this theoretical
chapter we discuss cognitive and neural models of time perception. We aim at showing
how the subjective passage of time and duration are modifi ed by functional states of
mindfulness, i.e. by attention regulation, body awareness and emotion regulation.
The ability of expert mindfulness meditators to focus more strongly on sensory
experiences and to be more strongly aware of feelings and of body states leads to a
slowing down of time in the present moment. Moreover, as a consequence of more
effi cient attention regulation capacities, memory formation is enhanced which in
Mindfulness Meditation and the Experience
of Time
Marc Wittmann and Stefan Schmidt
M. Wittmann (*)
Institute for Frontier Areas of Psychology and Mental Health , Wilhelmstr. 3a ,
Freiburg 79098 , Germany
e-mail: wittmann@igpp.de
S. Schmidt
Department of Psychosomatic Medicine and Psychotherapy , University Medical
Center Freiburg , Hauptstr. 8 , Freiburg 79104 , Germany
Institute for Transcultural Health Studies, European University Viadrina ,
Frankfurt (Oder) , Germany
e-mail: stefan.schmidt@uniklinik-freiburg.de
Walking is very calming. One step after another,
one foot moving into the future and one in the past.
Did you ever think about this? It’s like our bodies are
caught in the middle. The hard part is staying in the
present. Really being here.
Janet Cardiff (
2005 , p. 75)
200
retrospect leads to a subjective lengthening of past duration. Empirical studies
concerning time perception in meditation practitioners would help to understand
meditative states and at the same time would foster knowledge on cognitive- emotional
as well as neural processes underlying the experience of time.
Introduction
In experienced meditators conscious awareness is altered during meditation while
attention is being focused on the experience of the present moment. Essentially, mind-
fulness meditation is understood as bringing awareness to each moment in time. Being
mindful entails attending to sensory experiences in the outside world, thoughts,
emotions and body sensations by curiously observing them with a warm- hearted
attitude of openness and acceptance (Kabat-Zinn 2005 ). One aspect that is noticed
by individuals during mindfulness meditation as well as by experienced meditators
in everyday experience is that subjective time slows down considerably – in the
present moment as well as experienced for longer periods of time (see the chapter
“The ‘sense’ of time passing” in Kabat-Zinn 2005 ).
In phenomenological analyses of subjective time by Edmund Husserl, Maurice
Merleau-Ponty or William James the dual experience of temporality is prominently
discussed as encompassing (1) the sense of a present, the feeling of nowness and (2) the
feeling of a fl ow of time leading to the experience of duration (Wittmann 2009a ).
On the one hand, we perceive the unity of the present, a fundamental temporal
window of consciousness that defi nes our sense of an extended now . On the other
hand, we experience the passage of time, best described by a stream or fl ow. The
ow constitutes itself as an event which is anticipated, then experienced, and later
remembered, and by this way generating a sense of duration. The sense of the
present moment and of the fl ow of time constitutes our experience of temporality
as complementary phenomena. Whereas there are indications that the subjective
present might be expanded in experienced meditators (Carter et al. 2005 ; Sauer et al.
2012a ), systematic studies on the passage of time and of subjective duration have
hardly been undertaken so far (but see Chihara 1989 ). In the following passages we
will concentrate mainly on this second aspect of temporality, on the perception of
the passage of time leading to the feeling of duration, although the two aspects of
temporality – the sense of the present moment and the feeling of the fl ow of time –
are intertwined phenomena.
However essential the dimension of time is for human experience, by viewing
the research literature on time perception it becomes clear that no consensus exists
on how humans experience the passage of time; many different psychological and
neurophysiological models exist (Wittmann and van Wassenhove 2009 ). Therefore,
we address the issue of time perception in meditation practice for two reasons: For one,
a better understanding of the phenomenon that time slows down for meditators – both
during meditation and in everyday experience – could lead to a better understanding
of the meditation practice itself. Second, knowledge about this phenomenon could
M. Wittmann and S. Schmidt
201
foster the understanding of how we as humans perceive time. The two aspects
underlie the motivation for this theoretical account of bringing together research
on time perception and on the effects of meditation practice. In the following
paragraphs, essential features of mindfulness meditation will be highlighted. It will
be shown how these characteristics are decisive for changes in the subjective
experience of time in meditators.
Functional Characteristics of Mindfulness Meditation as
Modulators of Subjective Time
At least four functional aspects encompass the state of mindfulness, as summarized
by Hölzel et al. ( 2011 ), namely attention regulation, body awareness, emotion regu-
lation, and changes in the perspective of the self. As will be shown, these aspects
are also dominantly involved in modulating and generating our experience of time.
Therefore, a discussion on the relationship between meditative states and time
perception will be grouped according to these domains.
1. Attention regulation
The state of meditation can be described as deliberately and continuously focusing
attention on the present moment and some authors even take attention regulation as
one of the defi ning features of meditation and mindfulness (Bishop et al. 2004 ;
Shapiro 1982 ). One way of learning attention regulation is to keep the focus of attention
on a single object, e.g. the breath, by observing the breathing in and breathing out.
The ability to focus attention on an object continuously encompasses the disregard
of distractors such as upcoming thoughts and sensations for an extended period of
time. In experimental studies experienced meditators indeed perform with higher
accuracy and speed in many components of attention such as focused attention,
sustained attention and alertness as assessed with computerized attention tests.
That is, regular meditation practice enhances the ability of attention regulation in
everyday non-meditative states (e.g., Chan and Woollacott 2007 ; Jha et al. 2007 ;
Lutz et al. 2009 ; MacLean et al. 2010 ; Valentine and Sweet 1999 ; van den Hurk
et al. 2010 ; van Leeuwen et al. 2009 ; Zeidan et al. 2010 ). This ability of meditators
to maintain focused attention over time is assumed to lead to an increased awareness
of external and internal processes and events. Thus, mindfulness practice leads to a
stronger awareness of sensory experience in the here and now as well as to an
increased ability of sustained attention (Brown and Ryan 2003 ; Sauer et al. 2012b ).
In phenomenological analyses, consciousness is understood as an island of
presence in the continuous fl ow of time (Husserl 1928 ). In more mechanistic terms,
mental presence is based on working memory function integrating perceived events
over time to form a unifi ed experience (Wittmann 2011 ). Since meditation practice
leads to an increased awareness of sensory and mental experience through heightened
attentional capacities, this ability will also infl uence memory formation because
there are fewer slips of attention and distractions from the focus of attention.
Mindfulness Meditation and the Experience of Time
202
Interestingly, the ancient Pali word for mindfulness sati has also the meaning of
‘to remember’ (Analayo 2004 ), and this is interpreted by the fact that full attention
to the present moment will facilitate memory function. As has indeed been shown,
working memory capacity is enhanced in individuals who regularly meditate;
meditators recall more learned items after a certain time span during which distractor
items are interfering (Jha et al. 2010 ; Zeidan et al. 2010 ). These attention and memory
effects of meditative practice have consequences for subjective time.
Two fundamental perspectives in time perception can be discerned: prospective
and retrospective estimates of duration (Zakay and Block 1997 ). In prospective time
experiments participants have to judge the duration of an interval they are presently
experiencing. They direct more or less attention to the passage of time while a par-
ticular duration has to be judged. If more attention is directed to time during an explicit
duration estimation task, duration is experienced as being comparatively longer than
when attention is distracted from time. The time spent waiting for a bus (when one
strongly attends to the passage of time) feels much longer than the same time interval
chatting with a friend (when being distracted from time). Studies show how an
increased working memory capacity and greater attention regulation abilities are asso-
ciated with greater accuracy in many different temporal judgment tasks (Brown 1997 ;
Pütz et al. 2012 ; Ulbrich et al. 2007 , 2009 ). That is, the ability of attention regulation in
mindfulness meditators is the key factor for explaining performance accuracy in
explicit time estimation tasks in the seconds-to-minutes range – similar to meditation
effects on general perceptual discrimination accuracy (MacLean et al. 2010 ).
In retrospective time, an observer estimates a time span that has already elapsed.
In this case, subjective duration is reconstructed from memory. That is, retrospective
duration depends on the amount of experienced contextual changes stored in memory.
The more experienced changes have been stored, the longer an interval is judged to
have lasted (Bailey and Areni 2006 ; Zakay and Block 2004 ). This relation between
memory storage and the estimation of duration holds for retrospectively judged
intervals in the seconds-to-minutes range related to working memory. But it is also
assumed to hold for long-term episodic memory where the amount of changes during
a life span is linked to the judgment of duration, i.e. how fast the last 10 years passed
(Wittmann and Lehnhoff 2005 ). Since individuals trained in mindfulness meditation
techniques are more strongly aware of sensory events and they process and store
more items in working memory, their retrospective judgement of past duration
will likely lead to the impression of longer duration and a slowing down of subjective
time. Being more strongly aware of what is happening now causes more experi-
enced changes to be stored in memory which in turn leads to a relative expansion of
retrospective duration.
2. Body awareness
The body is the vehicle or frame of reference for sensory and mental experience.
Many meditation techniques therefore incorporate instructions to focus on body
sensations. Attention is for example directed to the breathing process or to specifi c
body parts (such as in the “body scan”). Although not many studies exist in which
body awareness skills in meditators were objectively tested, experienced practitioners
M. Wittmann and S. Schmidt
203
report having a greater awareness of their body states (for an overview of empirical
ndings, see Hölzel et al. 2011 ).
Neuroimaging studies suggest that, among other regions, the insular cortex is
modulated through mindfulness meditation practice. The insula is the primary
receptive area for visceral input and for monitoring physiological states of the body
(Craig 2002 ). In two studies, experienced meditators, as compared to controls,
showed greater gray matter concentration (Hölzel et al. 2008 ) and greater cortical
thickness (Lazar et al. 2005 ) in the right anterior insula. In another study, the instruction
to concentrate on respiratory sensations lead to a greater increase in neural activa-
tion in the posterior insula in trained meditators as compared to control subjects
(Farb et al. 2012 ). Moreover, experienced meditators, who generated a loving-
kindness- compassion meditation state, showed neural activation in the right anterior
insula that was related to the degree of successfully entering the meditative state
( Lutz et al. 2008 ). Mindfulness practice can also be seen as training of interoceptive
awareness, and is thus related to changes in brain regions representing and integrating
body states.
The insular cortex, which integrates body signals over time, has in recent
conceptualizations been suggested to form the anatomical and functional basis for
the creation of the sense of time and of awareness in general (Craig 2009a ; Wittmann
2009b ). In his model, Craig ( 2002 , 2009b ) assumes that body signals received in the
dorsal posterior insula are processed and integrated in a posterior-to-anterior
progression, this progressive integration culminating in the anterior insula, when
brain activation becomes associated with the conscious awareness of bodily feelings.
Subjective feelings depend upon bodily signals, as visceral and somatosensory
feedback from the peripheral nervous system is integrated with contextual, i.e.
perceptual, motivational, social and cognitive information leading to the awareness
of complex feeling states (Damasio 1999 ; Craig 2009b ). A unifi ed meta-representation
of homeostatic feelings is built in the anterior insula which generates an experience
of the self at one moment. A succession of these meta-representations across time
would provide the continuity of subjective awareness, a series of elementary
emotional moments. Important for our context here, the experience of time would
be created by successive moments of self-realization (Craig 2009a ). The sense of
time thereafter would be related to the temporal integration of signals from the
interoceptive system.
In fact, the insular cortex has repeatedly been shown to be activated in neuroim-
aging studies of time perception (for a meta-analysis, see Wiener et al. 2010 ).
The insula might specifi cally be implicated in the feeling of the passage of time of
several seconds duration: in an event-related functional magnetic resonance imaging
(fMRI) study using temporal intervals of 9 and 18 s, activation in the dorsal posterior
insular cortex was linked to the temporal encoding of these intervals: neural activation
in this region increased with increasing interval length and peaked at the end of
the interval (Wittmann et al. 2010 , 2011 ). When these intervals had to be reproduced
as indicated by a button press, a similar linear increase of activation was seen in the
anterior insula as well as regions of the frontal cortex which peaked shortly before
the actual button press. In line with the model by Craig (
2009a ), it was suggested
Mindfulness Meditation and the Experience of Time
204
that this accumulator-like activity represented the integration of body signals over
time that was used to represent duration.
The conjecture that interoception might be at the base of time perception is
supported by a psychophysiological study showing a positive relationship between
time estimation accuracy and the slope of cardiac slowing during the perception of
temporal intervals with durations between 8 and 20 s (Meissner and Wittmann 2011 ).
This study is probably the fi rst observation of a direct association between changes
in heart rate, a measure of the autonomic body function, and the accuracy in interval
timing. That is, changes in cardiac activity, as registered in the brain, might be used as
a measure for subjective duration. Moreover, also conscious awareness of the own
heart beat as assessed with the heartbeat perception test (Pollatos et al. 2005 ) was
related to time perception accuracy. That is, individuals who are more sensitive to
their heart beat, i.e. who more accurately count the number of heart beats for a given
interval, were also more accurate in time estimation (Meissner and Wittmann 2011 ).
This summary of fi ndings implies a clear hypothesis related to meditators who
are trained to be aware of their body processes. First of all, if the sense of time is so
strongly related to the awareness of body processes, then the focus on subjective
time will inevitably lead to a slowing down of the passage of time in meditators who
are more aware of their body processes. Two factors of meditation procedures are
dispositional for becoming aware of the fl ow of time, possibly through body
awareness. The instruction to focus on the present moment is inherently time
related. The meditator deliberately guides his or her awareness to the temporality of
experience. One could even say, during meditation the sense of time passing is
heightened, extremely so especially for beginners who often experience time as
passing much too slowly, sometimes provoking inner restlessness and boredom.
Moreover, the rhythmical nature of breathing and the heart beat constitutes a bodily
meter that refers to the passing of time. In fact, the breathing cycle of a relaxed state
with a period of approximately 3 s corresponds to the duration of an experienced
moment in the fl ow of time (Wittmann 2011 , 2012 ). Moreover, there are some tasks
in meditation which explicitly direct present moment attention to bodily signals,
i.e. performing the so-called body scan in mindfulness meditation, or full bodily
attention in a wide-focused mindfulness state. In this sense meditation is a state of
body awareness in the present moment. Understanding the state of being mindful
will lead to an understanding of the sense of time as embodied experience.
3. Emotion regulation
Mindfulness meditation enhances emotional well-being. Healthy individuals
who meditate regularly report fewer negative mood states, fewer ruminative thoughts
as well as more positive states of mind (Jain et al. 2007 ; Jha et al. 2010 ). In clinical
settings, structured group programs of mindfulness-based stress reduction reduce
negative affect in patients with physical, psychosomatic and psychiatric disorders
(Fjorback and Walach 2012 ; Grossman et al. 2004 ; Piet and Hougaard 2011 ) and the
same can be seen in non-clinical populations (Sedlmeier et al. 2012 ). Experiential
openness and acceptance of thoughts and feelings in mindfulness meditation, in
essence, means that upcoming mood states are in the focus of attention, even when
M. Wittmann and S. Schmidt
205
negative emotions are experienced (Hölzel et al. 2011 ). Mindfulness practitioners
expose themselves to their affective experiences in a non-reactive manner and thus
learn to cope with their mood states. Sustained attention to these states leads to a
situation of exposure, which in turn and over time may lead to the decrease or even
extinction of an emotional reaction. However, emotion regulation in this sense does
not necessarily imply a down-regulation of emotion but a greater awareness of
mood states and an increased ability of emotional control while experiencing these
states. Indeed, one of the mechanisms of mindfulness seems to be the reduction of
avoidance behavior (Sauer et al. 2011 ). An individual learns to accept his or her
automatic emotional reactions and thus not to enhance them by aversion or attraction.
As a consequence, higher levels of positive affect can be experienced (Ekman et al.
2005 ; Jha et al. 2010 ).
The sense of time is intimately linked to affective states. In periods of severe
mental distress such as in depression or anxiety the passage of time slows down
considerably and time intervals are overestimated (Bschor et al. 2004 ; Wittmann
et al. 2006 ). In everyday life, boredom is the prototypical mood state in which time
passes too slowly. The feeling of an existential vacuum directs attention to time
since no meaningful distraction is experienced which in turn leads to a (painful)
feeling that subjective time slows down. Moreover, in experimental settings,
subjects overestimate the duration of emotional stimuli which last several hundred
milliseconds to a few seconds, bodily arousal, attention, and sentience being
discussed for explaining these effects of time experience (Droit-Volet and Gil 2009 ;
Schirmer 2011 ; Wittmann 2009b ). Specifi cally, it is assumed that increased physi-
ological arousal leads to a faster speed of an internal pacemaker underlying time
perception (Gil and Droit-Volet 2012 ). A faster speed of such an internal clock
would lead to the accumulation of more pulses emitted by a hypothetical pacemaker
operating in the seconds range (Zakay and Block 1997 ). There is ample evidence of
an overestimation of duration in the sub- and supra-second range of mostly negative
emotional stimuli which is related to higher physiological arousal. However, also
the presentation of positive emotional stimuli, associated with higher physiological
arousal, can lead to a relative overestimation of duration as compared to neutral
stimuli (Lambrechts et al. 2011 ).
By trying to integrate the aforementioned fi ndings on the relationship between
emotion and time perception, a tentative hypothesis would be that experts in meditation
practice who experience a positive emotional tone and who are more sensitive to
their upcoming mood states, while attending to the temporal aspects of perception,
will feel a general slowing of the pace of time. A stronger awareness of emotional
states is related to an increase in accumulated pulses of an assumed pacemaker-
accumulator and thus would lead to a relative prolongation of subjective time. In
addition, also a retrospective account of time perception can explain why time slows
down for experienced meditators. A stronger attentional focus on present experience
coupled with a positive emotional tone will lead to an enhanced encoding of events.
This in turn results in more items collected in memory. When looking back in time
more memories can be retrieved which amounts to a relative prolongation of a perceived
time span as opposed to a situation where less memorable events are retrieved.
Mindfulness Meditation and the Experience of Time
206
Summary
Contemporary philosophical conceptions of the self which take into account fi ndings
from the neurosciences and psychology have a striking resemblance to Buddhist
teachings concerning the perception of a self (Hölzel et al. 2011 ). The programmatic
title of the book Being no one . The self-model theory of subjectivity (Metzinger
2004 ) summarizes the notion that there is no static self as a permanent entity or
substance, but that ongoing mental processes are engaged in producing a transient
model of the self. On a basic level, the bodily self, as created by the continuous
visceral and proprioceptive input from the body, is the functional anchor of phenomenal
experience (Damasio 2003 ). According to the model proposed by Craig ( 2009a , b )
integration processes of body signals culminating in the anterior insula as meta-
representations of successive emotional moments are associated with the experience
of an embodied and extended self in time. Importantly, phenomenological concep-
tualizations have put forward the idea that subjective time emerges through the
existence of the self across time as embodied entity (Kiverstein 2009 ; Zahavi 2005 ).
Mindfulness meditation is the enhanced awareness of the present moment and this
psychological state is associated with brain areas involved in processing of the
bodily self (Farb et al. 2007 ).
In mindfulness meditation a practitioner focuses on the experience of the embodied
self at the present moment. Being mindful in everyday life is equivalent to being
conscious of one’s body states and feelings, of oneself at this particular moment in
time. Because the feeling of time is created through attending to the embodied self
at the present moment, being exceptionally mindful slows down the passage of time.
Moreover, subjective time slows down in retrospect because greater awareness of
one’s experiences leads to enriched memory contents, which in turn expands sub-
jective duration. An increased focus on an experienced self at the present moment
slows down the subjective passage of time – now and in retrospect.
References
Analayo, V. 2004. Satipatthana: The direct path to realization . Cambridge: Windhorse.
Bailey, N., and C.S. Areni. 2006. Background music as a quasi clock in retrospective duration
judgments. Perception and Motor Skills 102: 435–444.
Bishop, S.R., M. Lau, S. Shapiro, L.E. Carlson, N.D. Anderson, J. Carmody, Z.V. Segal, S. Abbey,
M. Speca, D. Velting, and G. Devins. 2004. Mindfulness: A proposed operational defi nition.
Clinical Psychology: Science and Practice 11: 230–241.
Brown, S.W. 1997. Attentional resources in timing: Interference effects in concurrent temporal and
nontemporal working memory tasks. Perception and Psychophysics 59: 1118–1140.
Brown, K.W., and R.M. Ryan. 2003. The benefi ts of being present: Mindfulness and its role in
psychological well-being. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 84: 822–848.
Bschor, T., M. Ising, M. Bauer, U. Lewitzka, M. Skerstupeit, B. Müller-Oerlinghausen, and
C. Baethge. 2004. Time experience and time judgment in major depression, mania and healthy
subjects. A controlled study of 93 subjects. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica 109: 222–229.
M. Wittmann and S. Schmidt
207
Cardiff, J. 2005. The walk book. By Mirjam Schaub, edited by Thyssen-Bornemisza Art
Contemporary Vienna in collaboration with Public Art Fund, New York.
Carter, O.L., D.E. Presti, C. Callistemon, Y. Ungerer, G.B. Liu, and J.D. Pettigrew. 2005. Meditation
alters perceptual rivalry in Tibetan Buddhist monks. Current Biology 15: R412–R413.
Chan, D., and M. Woollacott. 2007. Effects of level of meditation experience on attentional focus:
Is the effi ciency of executive or orientation networks improved? Journal of Alternative and
Complementary Medicine 13: 651–657.
Chihara, T. 1989. Zen meditation and time-experience. Psychologia 32: 211–220.
Craig, A.D. 2002. How do you feel? Interoception: The sense of the physiological condition of the
body. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3: 655–666.
Craig, A.D. 2009a. Emotional moments across time: A possible neural basis for time perception in
the anterior insula. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364: 1933–1942.
Craig, A.D. 2009b. How do you feel – now? The anterior insula and human awareness. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 10: 59–70.
Damasio, A. 1999. The feeling of what happens: body and emotion in the making of consciousness .
San Diego: Harcourt.
Damasio, A. 2003. Feelings of emotion and the self. Annals of the New York Academy of Science
1001: 253–261.
Droit-Volet, S., and S. Gil. 2009. The time-emotion paradox. Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society B 364: 1943–1954.
Ekman, P., J.R. Davidson, M. Ricard, and B.A. Wallace. 2005. Buddhist and psychological perspec-
tives on emotions and well-being. Current Directions in Psychological Science 14: 59–63.
Farb, N.A., Z.V. Segal, H. Mayberg, J. Bean, D. McKeon, Z. Fatima, and A.K. Anderson. 2007.
Attending to the present: Mindfulness meditation reveals distinct neural modes of self- reference.
Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 2: 313–322.
Farb, N.A., Z.V. Segal, and A.K. Anderson. 2012. Mindfulness meditation training alters cortical
representations of interoceptive attention. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 8: 15–26.
Fjorback, L.O., and H. Walach. 2012. Meditation based therapies – a systematic review and some
critical observations. Religions 3: 1–18.
Gil, S., and S. Droit-Volet. 2012. Emotional time distortions: The fundamental role of arousal.
Cognition and Emotion 26: 847–862.
Grossman, P., L. Niemann, S. Schmidt, and H. Walach. 2004. Mindfulness-based stress reduction
and health benefi ts. A meta-analysis. Journal of Psychosomatic Research 57: 35–43.
Hölzel, B.K., U. Ott, H. Hempel, A. Hackl, K. Wolf, R. Stark, and D. Vaitl. 2008. Investigation of
mindfulness meditation practicioners with voxel-based morphometry. Social Cognitive and
Affective Neuroscience 3: 55–61.
Hölzel, B.K., S.W. Lazar, T. Gard, Z. Schuman-Olivier, D.R. Vago, and U. Ott. 2011. How does
minfulness work? Proposing mechanisms of action from a conceptual and neural perspective.
Perspectives on Psychological Science 6: 537–559.
Husserl, E. 1928. Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewußtseins . Halle: Max
Niemeyer Verlag.
Jain, S., S.L. Shapiro, S. Swanick, S.C. Roesch, P.J. Mills, I. Bell, and G.E. Schwartz. 2007.
A randomized controlled trial of mindfulness meditation versus relaxation training: Effects of
distress, positive states of mind, rumination, and distraction. Annals of Behavioral Medicine
33: 11–21.
Jha, A.P., J. Krompinger, and M.J. Baime. 2007. Mindfulness training modifi es subsystems of
attention. Cognitive, Affective, and Behavioral Neuroscience 7: 109–119.
Jha, A.P., E.A. Stanley, A. Kiyonaga, L. Wong, and L. Gelfand. 2010. Examining the protective
effects of mindfulness training on working memory capacity and affective experience.
Emotion
10: 54–64.
Kabat-Zinn, J. 2005. Coming to our senses . New York: Hyperion.
Kiverstein, J. 2009. The minimal sense of self, temporality and the brain. Psyche 15: 59–74.
Mindfulness Meditation and the Experience of Time
208
Lambrechts, A., N. Mella, V. Pouthas, and M. Noulhiane. 2011. Subjectivity of time perception: A visual
emotional orchestration. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 5: 73.
Lazar, S.W., C.E. Kerr, R.H. Wasserman, J.R. Gray, D.N. Greve, M.T. Treadway, M. McGarvey,
B.T. Quinn, J.A. Dusek, H. Benson, S.L. Rauch, C.I. Moore, and B. Fischl. 2005. Meditation
experience is associated with increased cortical thickness. NeuroReport 16: 1893–1897.
Lutz, A., J. Brefczynski-Lewis, T. Johnstone, and R.J. Davidson. 2008. Regulation of the neural
circuitry of emotion by compassion meditation: Effects of meditative expertise. PLoS ONE
3(3): e1897.
Lutz, A., H.A. Slagter, N.B. Rawlings, A.D. Francis, L.L. Greischar, and J.R. Davidson. 2009.
Mental training enhances attentional stability: Neural and behavioral evidence. The Journal of
Neuroscience 29: 13418–13427.
MacLean, K.A., E. Ferrer, S.R. Aichele, D.A. Bridwell, A.P. Zanesco, T.L. Jacobs, B.G. King,
E.L. Rosenberg, B.K. Sahdra, P.R. Shaver, B.A. Wallace, G.R. Mangun, and C.D. Saron. 2010.
Intensive meditation training improves perceptual discrimination and sustained attention.
Psychological Science 21: 829–839.
Meissner, K., and M. Wittmann. 2011. Body signals, cardiac awareness, and the perception of
time. Biological Psychology 86: 289–297.
Metzinger, T. 2004. Being no one. The self-model theory of subjectivity . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Piet, J., and E. Hougaard. 2011. The effect of mindfulness-based cognitive therapy for prevention
of relapse in recurrent major depressive disorder: A systematic review and meta-analysis.
Clinical Psychology Review 31: 1032–1040.
Pollatos, O., W. Kirsch, and R. Schandry. 2005. On the relationship between interoceptive awareness,
emotional experience, and brain processes. Cognitive Brain Research 25: 948–962.
Pütz, P., P. Ulbrich, J. Churan, M. Fink, and M. Wittmann. 2012. Duration discrimination in the
context of age, sex, and cognition. Journal of Cognitive Psychology 24: 893–900.
Sauer, S., H. Walach, and N. Kohls. 2011. Gray’s behavioural inhibition system as a mediator of
mindfulness towards well-being. Personality and Individual Differences 50: 506–511.
Sauer, S., J. Lemke, M. Wittmann, N. Kohls, U. Mochty, and H. Walach. 2012a. How long is now
for mindfulness meditators? Personality and Individual Differences 52: 750–754.
Sauer, S., H. Walach, S. Schmidt, T. Hinterberger, S. Lynch, A. Büssing, and N. Kohls. 2012b.
Assessment of mindfulness: Review on state of the art. Mindfulness . doi: 10.1007/s12671-
012-0122-5 .
Schirmer, A. 2011. How emotions change time. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 5: 58.
Sedlmeier, P., J. Eberth, M. Schwarz, D. Zimmermann, F. Haarig, S. Jaeger, and S. Kunze. 2012.
The psychological effects of meditation: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin 138:
1139–1171.
Shapiro, D. 1982. Overview: Clinical and physiological comparison of meditation with other
self- control strategies. American Journal of Psychiatry 139: 267–274.
Ulbrich, P., J. Churan, M. Fink, and M. Wittmann. 2007. Temporal reproduction: Further evidence
for two processes. Acta Psychologica 125: 51–65.
Ulbrich, P., J. Churan, M. Fink, and M. Wittmann. 2009. Perception of temporal order: The effects
of age, sex, and cognitive factors. Aging, Neuropsychology and Cognition 16: 183–202.
Valentine, E.R., and P.L.G. Sweet. 1999. Meditation and attention: A comparison of the effects of
concentrative and mindfulness meditation on sustained attention. Mental Health, Religion and
Culture 2: 59–70.
van den Hurk, P.A.M., F. Giommi, S.C. Gielen, A.E.M. Speckens, and H. Barendregt. 2010.
Greater effi ciency in attentional processing related to mindfulness meditation. The Quarterly
Journal of Experimental Psychology 63: 1168–1180.
van Leeuwen, S., N.G. Müller, and L. Melloni. 2009. Age effects on attentional blink performance
in meditation. Consciousness and Cognition 18: 593–599.
Wiener, M., P. Turkeltaub, and H.B. Coslett. 2010. The image of time: A voxel-wise meta-analysis.
NeuroImage 49: 1728–1740.
Wittmann, M. 2009a. The subjective ow of time. In The encyclopedia of time , ed. H.J. Birks,
1322–1324. Thousand Oaks: SAGE Publications.
M. Wittmann and S. Schmidt
209
Wittmann, M. 2009b. The inner sense of time. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B
364: 1955–1967.
Wittmann, M. 2011. Moments in time. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 5: 66.
Wittmann, M. 2012. Gefühlte Zeit: Kleine Psychologie des Zeitempfi ndens . München: C.H. Beck.
Wittmann, M., and S. Lehnhoff. 2005. Age effects in perception of time. Psychological Reports 97:
921–935.
Wittmann, M., and V. van Wassenhove. 2009. The experience of time: Neural mechanisms and the
interplay of emotion, cognition and embodiment. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society B 364: 1809–1813.
Wittmann, M., T. Vollmer, C. Schweiger, and W. Hiddemann. 2006. The relation between the
experience of time and psychological distress in patients with hematological malignancies.
Palliative and Supportive Care 4: 357–363.
Wittmann, M., A.N. Simmons, J. Aron, and M.P. Paulus. 2010. Accumulation of neural activity in
the posterior insula encodes the passage of time. Neuropsychologia 48: 3110–3120.
Wittmann, M., A.N. Simmons, T. Flagan, S.D. Lane, J. Wackermann, and M.P. Paulus. 2011.
Neural substrates of time perception and impulsivity. Brain Research 1406: 43–58.
Zahavi, D. 2005. Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the fi rst-person perspective . Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Zakay, D., and R.A. Block. 1997. Temporal cognition. Current Directions in Psychological Science
6: 12–16.
Zakay, D., and R.A. Block. 2004. Prospective and retrospective duration judgments: An executive-
control perspective. Acta Neurobiologiae Experimentalis 64: 319–328.
Zeidan, F., S.K. Johnson, B.J. Diamond, Z. David, and P. Goolkasian. 2010. Mindfulness training
improves cognition: Evidence of brief mental training. Consciousness and Cognition
19: 597–605.
Mindfulness Meditation and the Experience of Time
... Accordingly, this research moves beyond the religiously grounded meditation travel/retreat (Wang et al., 2021) to embark on a more generalizable travel phenomenon for body-soul self-improvement. This meditation-induced process further reflects an alternative approach in transformative tourism (Chen et al., 2017;Wittmann & Schmidt, 2014;Wolf, Ainsworth, & Crowley, 2017) and heeds the call from Sheldon (2020) to annotate a series of paths leading from meditation to means that could motivate tourists to seek their inner journeys. Hence, meditation pilgrimage moves beyond religious and wellness practices to embark on the transformative domain of mind and soul healing for tourists. ...
... These experiential outcomes have incentivized participants to continue engaging in the recreational activity through traveling to meditation centers. Although Jiang et al. (2018) refer to them as experience in general, the literature commonly acknowledges that meditation could result in a flow experience during trips (Wittmann & Schmidt, 2014). ...
... It thus heeds the call from Sheldon (2020, p. 1) to annotate a series of paths leading from meditation to means that could motivate tourists to seek "how outer journeys can transform our inner consciousness, leading to awakening or enlightenment." Such an inner journey not only allows tourists to be mindful of their very existence, as the literature suggests (Chen et al., 2017;Sheldon, 2020;Wang et al., 2021;Wittmann & Schmidt, 2014;Wolf et al., 2017). The findings also clearly demonstrate that the journey possesses other mental, emotional, and physiological benefits that could heal our body and soul, hence adding new nuances to the transformative tourism stream of work. ...
Article
Meditation has largely been associated with its religious connotation in the tourism literature. The present research steers away from that tradition to focus on meditative practices as a leisure activity. It addresses the literature void by conducting a survey study on meditation tourists who participated in a 7-day meditation excursion. Based on attention restoration theory and the two-factor theory of emotion, this research contributes to the literature by underscoring a theoretical synthesis of the transformative potential of meditation on tourists' psychological and emotional wellness. It moves beyond the religiously grounded meditation retreat to offer a more generalizable travel phenomenon for body–soul self-improvement. It opens a new avenue for meditation travel by attention restoration through an arousal–cognition perspective. This wellness-related tourism has great potential to gain further popularity for those who have suffered mental and physical stress from the pandemic and other life adversities.
... Finally, only one study incorporated the CHIME; (Bergomi et al., 2013(Bergomi et al., , 2014. Relying on CHIME (Bergomi et al., 2013), Wittmann et al. (2014) reported using a 37-item CHIME questionnaire assessing mindfulness via the proposed 8-factor structure that potentially has a wider scope than the FFMQ (Baer et al., 2006). These factors are inner and outer awareness (assessing the awareness of either internal or environment-sourced stimuli), acting with awareness (related to a metacognitive insight into the reason behind behavior), acceptance (including a non-judgmental and accepting attitude towards events and actions), decentering (including a non-reactive and observant look upon experiences as they unfold), openness to experiences (related to a permissive or curious attitude in considering alternative actions and perspectives), relativity (regarding appreciation of thoughts as subjective and transient entities), and insight (referring to an insightful appreciation of experiences). ...
... This, arguably, may explain the positive correlations observed with past negative perspective; as, the past negative time perspective correlates negatively with indicators of mental health (Roseanu et al., 2008;Watson, 2017;Zimbardo & Boyd, 2008) and a negative evaluation of self implies a judgmental attitude being unjustly inflicted. Taken together, the above critique can be offered for the observation that Wittmann et al. (2014) did not provide an explanation for, to help guide future studies on exploring the matter further. ...
... The MMT also highlights the importance of momentary experiences of state mindfulness and their cumulative influence on improving the trait nature of mindfulness-a point that speculates further implications on how BTP, alongside with DM, can be trained and better utilized as a response to current stressors. Indeed, state changes in mindfulness can influence perceived duration of the present moment, possibly influencing adaptive responses to current situational demands (Droit-Volet et al., 2015;Sauer et al., 2012;Wittmann & Schmidt, 2014). ...
Article
Full-text available
Objectives Research on the effects of time perspectives and dispositional mindfulness on psychological well-being can be potentially insightful. However, time perspective and dispositional mindfulness constructs have mostly been studied separately, leaving room for discussion regarding their interactions. There is, so far, a limited number of empirical studies and no systematic review on this area of research. This systematic review thus aimed at providing an informative outline. Method Key databases including Scopus and Web of Knowledge were screened, and the most recent search was conducted in June 2023. Initially, 593 entries were found to meet the criterion of cross-sectional design. Final analysis incorporated the narrative synthesis strategy for resulting 16 eligible articles. Results Dispositional mindfulness is closely related to a flexible shift in time perspectives, called the balanced time perspective. In general, dispositional mindfulness was found to positively correlate with an optimistic view of both the past and the future, and it was also positively linked to savoring the present moment experiences. Furthermore, a non-judgmental focus is central to mindful decentering when being attentive to the actual characteristics of present stimuli. Conclusions The balanced time perspective is an important construct possibly linking dispositional mindfulness and time perspectives. The present-eudaimonic perspective, self-compassion, and decentering are variables that can further help guide research in outlining complex interactions that also relate to psychological well-being. Future research is advised to include longitudinal and experimental designs for a more comprehensive understanding of relevant interactions. Preregistration This study was preregistered to PROSPERO with the number CRD42021241388.
... On the other hand, intrinsic models associate brain oscillations with the activity of statedependent networks, representing perceived time, or the speed and level of neural information processing and entropy, acting as indicators of perceived time 15,16 . Among neural oscillators, the occipital alpha waves have attracted particular attention [17][18][19][20][21][22][23][24] . ...
Article
Full-text available
Alpha oscillations have been implicated in time perception, yet a consensus on their precise role remains elusive. This study directly investigates this relationship by examining the impact of alpha oscillations on time perception. Resting-state EEG recordings were used to extract peak alpha frequency (PAF) and peak alpha power (PAP) characteristics. Participants then performed a time generalization task under transcranial alternating current stimulation (tACS) at frequencies of PAF−2, PAF, and PAF+2, as well as a sham condition. Results revealed a significant correlation between PAP and accuracy, and between PAF and precision of one-second time perception in the sham condition. This suggests that alpha oscillations may influence one-second time perception by modulating their frequency and power. Interestingly, these correlations weakened with real tACS stimulations, particularly at higher frequencies. A second analysis aimed to establish a causal relationship between alpha peak modulation by tACS and time perception using repeated measures ANOVAs, but no significant effect was observed. Results were interpreted according to the state-dependent networks and internal clock model.
... Farb et al. (2007) validated the active involvement of a right lateralized network including lPFC, AIC, secondary sensory cortex, and inferior parietal lobule, which suggests experiential focus centers on the present in trained meditators. Mindfulness meditators may perceive a slowing of time in the present based on their ability to focus more strongly on sensory experiences and to be more strongly aware of feelings and of body states (Wittmann and Schmidt, 2014). The argument that AIC is integrated into perception of time intervals in the range of seconds to sub-seconds is supported by fMRI task results (Livesey et al., 2007). ...
Article
Full-text available
Background Mindfulness affects human levels of experience by facilitating the immediate and impartial perception of phenomena, including sensory stimulation, emotions, and thoughts. Mindfulness is now a focus of neuroimaging, since technical and methodological developments in magnetic resonance imaging have made it possible to observe subjects performing mindfulness tasks. Objective We set out to describe the association between mental processes and characteristics of mindfulness, including their specific cerebral patterns, as shown in structural and functional neuroimaging studies. Methods We searched the MEDLINE databank of references and abstracts on life sciences and biomedical topics via PubMed using the keywords: “mindfulness,” “focused attention (FA),” “open monitoring (OM),” “mind wandering,” “emotional regulation,” “magnetic resonance imaging (MRI)” and “default mode network (DMN).” This review extracted phenomenological experiences across populations with varying degrees of mindfulness training and correlated these experiences with structural and functional neuroimaging patterns. Our goal was to describe how mindful behavior was processed by the constituents of the default mode network during specific tasks. Results and conclusions Depending on the research paradigm employed to explore mindfulness, investigations of function that used fMRI exhibited distinct activation patterns and functional connectivities. Basic to mindfulness is a long-term process of learning to use meditation techniques. Meditators progress from voluntary control of emotions and subjective preferences to emotional regulation and impartial awareness of phenomena. As their ability to monitor perception and behavior, a metacognitive skill, improves, mindfulness increases self-specifying thoughts governed by the experiential phenomenological self and reduces self-relational thoughts of the narrative self. The degree of mindfulness (ratio of self-specifying to self-relational thoughts) may affect other mental processes, e.g., awareness, working memory, mind wandering and belief formation. Mindfulness prevents habituation and the constant assumptions associated with mindlessness. Self-specifying thinking during mindfulness and self-relational thinking in the narrative self relies on the default mode network. The main constituents of this network are the dorsal and medial prefrontal cortex, and posterior cingulate cortex. These midline structures are antagonistic to self-specifying and self-relational processes, since the predominant process determines their differential involvement. Functional and brain volume changes indicate brain plasticity, mediated by mental training over the long-term.
Chapter
Background: Previous research has shown that mindfulness is associated with slower passage of time in everyday life, and with lower self-reported time pressure. This study investigates some of the potential mechanisms behind these relationships. Methods: 318 participants submitted their responses to an online survey which collected data regarding passage of time judgments, time pressure, trait mindfulness, temperament, task load, and metacognitions about time. Using commonality and dominance analyses, we explored how these variables contributed, either alone or jointly, to predicting how fast (or slow) time seems to pass for participants, or how pressed for time they felt. Results: Mindfulness and temperament had some overlaps in their ability to predict passage of time judgments and time pressure for durations at the month and 2-month scales. The temperamental trait of extraversion/surgency, as well as the Non-judging and Non-reacting facets of mindfulness were among the best predictors of passage of time judgments and time pressure. Attention-related variables were mainly related to time perception via their involvement in joint effects with other variables. Results also suggested that metacognitions about time interacted with other variables in predicting passage of time judgments, but only at the month scale. Finally, among all the variables included in this study, task load had the highest degree of involvement in predictions of self-reported time pressure at the week and month scales, but it contributed relatively little to predicting passage of time judgments. Conclusions: Results suggest that mindfulness relates to passage of time through its involvement in inferential processes. The data also shows how different factors are related to PoTJ at different time scales. Finally, results suggest the existence of both similarities and differences in how passage of time and time pressure relate to the other included variables. Keywords Mindfulness; Temperament; Metacognition; Task load; Psychological time; Time perception; Passage of time judgments; Time pressure
Article
Full-text available
Several recent studies have explored the relationships between mindfulness and time perception, an area of research that has become increasingly popular in the last 10–15 years. In this article, we present a systematic integrative review of the evidence on this subject. We also integrate the field’s findings into a conceptual framework which considers the multifaceted nature of both mindfulness, and time perception research. To identify the relevant literature, we searched the following databases using relevant keywords: PsycINFO; Medline; EBSCO Host Psychology and Behavioral Sciences Collection; and Web of Science. These searches were last performed on the 4th of May 2022, and additional hand searches were also conducted. To be included, articles had to be in English and contain original data about the potential relationship(s) between mindfulness and time perception. Articles which did not present usable data about the relationship(s) between the variables of interest were excluded. In total, 47 research articles were included in the review (combined sample size of ∼5800 participants). Risks of bias in the selected studies were evaluated using two separate assessment tools designed for this purpose. Through an integrative narrative synthesis, this article reviews how mindfulness may relate to time perception for various reference frames, and for various time perception measures and methods. It also provides new insights by exploring how a wide range of findings can be integrated into a coherent whole, in light of some relevant time perception models and mindfulness theories. Altogether, the reviewed data suggest the existence of complex and multifaceted relationships between mindfulness and time perception, highlighting the importance of considering many factors when planning research or interpreting data in this field. Limitations of the current review include the scarceness of data for certain categories of findings, and the relatively low prevalence of studies with a randomized controlled design in the source literature. This research was partly funded by a grant from the Natural Science and Engineering Research Council of Canada.
Article
Full-text available
Human consciousness is characterized by constant transitions in time. On the other hand, what is consciously experienced always possesses the temporal feature of “now.” In consciousness, “now” constantly holds different contents, yet it remains “now” no matter how far it goes. This duality is thematized in Husserlian phenomenology as “the standing-streaming now.” Although this phrase appears contradictory in everyday language, it has a structure that can be clearly understood and formalized. In this paper, we show that this structure can be described as a monoid in category theory. Furthermore, monoids can be transformed into the coslice category, which corresponds to the way of perceiving present moments as juxtaposed in succession. The seemingly contradictory nature of the “now” as both flowing and standing can be precisely structured and comprehended through the monoid, while the perspective of the “now” as discrete points on a timeline can be effectively formalized using the coslice category. This framework helps us more precisely understand the differences between ordinary consciousness and meditative consciousness, specifically the experience of the “eternal now.” We illustrate how the meditative states of consciousness presented in the early Buddhist scriptures (Pali Canon) and Dōgen’s Shōbōgenzō remarkably reflect a monoid structure.
Article
Time is a fundamentally important dimension of human experience and responding adaptively in terms of this dimension is critical to human personal and societal functioning. However, there is an important distinction to be made between responding to time as a physical or nonarbitrary dimension of existence and time as an abstract concept. It is the latter that is critical to the type of self-knowledge and societal organization that is unique to human life. Relational frame theory (RFT) sees relational framing, and temporal relational framing in particular, as key to this uniquely human level of responding. The purpose of this article is to (1) explain temporal relational framing and the relevant research into this skill; (2) discuss existing psychological research into time-related skill sets in humans; and (3) explore how the RFT approach to human temporal responding might amplify and extend the existing research base, in particular with respect to the acquisition and training of key aspects of temporal responding.
Article
Full-text available
The purpose of the current review study is to provide representative evidence regarding the effectiveness of mindfulness training strategies on the development of metacognitive skills for people with special education needs. In addition, we explore the role of virtual reality in the efficacy of mindfulness interventions among people with learning disabilities, neurodevelopmental disorders, intellectual disabilities, and behavioral disorders. In addition, we present innovative mindfulness training strategies, appropriate for metacognitive skills training in special education. Finally, we seek the features that possibly make virtual reality a fertile ground for the implementation of mindfulness training. The results showed that mindfulness training improves the metacognitive skills needed for the inclusion of people with disabilities. Virtual reality constitutes an effective assistive technology that can facilitate mindfulness training in various contexts, accelerating positive outcomes in mental and physical health, academic performance, and well-being.
Article
Education in the 21st century is called upon to prepare students with disabilities to enter a high-consciousness society where people can learn, think and react fast. The current review paper aims at investigating the role of fast learning in special education. We trace the essential indicators of speed learning with a special focus on those factors that are most relevant to learning disabilities. Afterward, we present evidence-based training techniques and strategies that rapidly rewire the brain and speed up learning. In addition, we examine the role of ICTs as essential training tools in speed learning. Finally, we discuss the role of metacognition in training fast and conscious learners. The results of this review showed that speed learning training techniques improve all those factors that accelerate learning such as spatial attention, visual span, processing speed, speed reaction, executive functions, metacognition, and consciousness. Most important, fast learning strategies meliorate control processes and spatial intelligence which is extremely fast and powerful. Metacognition provides learners with all those meta-abilites needed to enter a state of peak performance. This study also points to the option of including speed training strategies in schools to create inclusive learning environments and help students with or without disabilities to transcend their limitations and become conscious and high-capacity learners.
Article
Full-text available
The experience of the present moment is characterized by an integrative mechanism that fuses successive events into a unitary phenomenological experience with a temporal limit of about 3 s. We hypothesized that proficiency of mindfulness expands the ability to stabilize an ambiguous percept in a bistable image paradigm using the Necker Cube, and that this effect is associated with individual differences in the level of mindfulness. Expanded duration of nowness as indicated by the ability to stabilize a bistable image stimulus for a longer period of time may improve cognitive resources and thus be of practical interest. In a sample of n = 38 meditators and n = 38 non-meditators, meditators showed longer duration of subjective nowness. This effect was associated with individual mindfulness levels. It is concluded that the subjective now can be longer for meditators than for non-meditators, and individual levels of mindfulness may convey this effect.
Book
What is a self? Does it exist in reality or is it a mere social construct—or is it perhaps a neurologically induced illusion? The legitimacy of the concept of the self has been questioned by both neuroscientists and philosophers in recent years. Countering this, in Subjectivity and Selfhood, Dan Zahavi argues that the notion of self is crucial for a proper understanding of consciousness. He investigates the interrelationships of experience, self-awareness, and selfhood, proposing that none of these three notions can be understood in isolation. Any investigation of the self, Zahavi argues, must take the first-person perspective seriously and focus on the experiential givenness of the self. Subjectivity and Selfhood explores a number of phenomenological analyses pertaining to the nature of consciousness, self, and self-experience in light of contemporary discussions in consciousness research. Philosophical phenomenology—as developed by Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, and others—not only addresses crucial issues often absent from current debates over consciousness but also provides a conceptual framework for understanding subjectivity. Zahavi fills the need—given the recent upsurge in theoretical and empirical interest in subjectivity—for an account of the subjective or phenomenal dimension of consciousness that is accessible to researchers and students from a variety of disciplines. His aim is to use phenomenological analyses to clarify issues of central importance to philosophy of mind, cognitive science, developmental psychology, and psychiatry. By engaging in a dialogue with other philosophical and empirical positions, says Zahavi, phenomenology can demonstrate its vitality and contemporary relevance. Bradford Books imprint
Book
Psychologie und Hirnforschung ist es in den letzten Jahren gelungen, unseren Zeitsinn zu enträtseln. Der Leser des Buches erfährt, wie unser Gehirn wirklich tickt und wie wir zu unserem Gefühl von zeitlicher Dauer kommen. Er lernt, dass der Umgang mit der Zeit für Erfolg im Leben wichtiger ist als etwa der IQ. Wir sind unserem Zeitgefühl nicht hilflos ausgeliefert, sondern können es durch Achtsamkeit beeinflussen. Gefühlte Zeit bestimmt unsere Entscheidungen im Alltag: Sollen wir auf den Aufzug warten oder die Treppen nehmen, stelle ich mich jetzt in die Schlange oder komme ich später wieder? Ökonomische Fragen sind zeitabhängig: Soll ich mein Geld langfristig anlegen oder für mein Traumauto ausgeben? Gefühlte Zeit bestimmt aber auch unser Verhältnis zum Älterwerden: Auf einmal spüren wir, dass wir nicht mehr der junge Mensch sind, für den wir uns immer hielten. Mit Erschrecken bemerken wir, dass mit zunehmendem Alter die Zeit immer schneller vergeht. Unsere Erfahrung von Zeit sagt etwas über uns selbst aus. Wir sind gewissermaßen die Zeit, unser Zeitgefühl reflektiert unsere Lebensweise und unser Selbst. Zum geglückten Leben gehört ein reifer Umgang mit der gefühlten Zeit – im Augenblick wie aufs Ganze des Lebens gesehen.
Article
Cognitive neuroscientists are currently busy searching for the neural signatures of conscious experience. I shall argue that the notion of neural correlates of consciousness employed in much of this work is subject to two very different interpretations depending on how one understands the relation between the concepts of "state consciousness" and "creature consciousness." Localist theories treat the neural correlates of creature consciousness as a kind of background condition that must be in place in order for the brain to realize particular conscious experiences. Holists on the other hand take the neural correlates of creature consciousness to be a part of the core realizer of a particular conscious experience. My aim in this paper will be threefold. First I argue we should understand creature consciousness as a property of those creatures that have a minimal sense of self. Given this conception of creature consciousness I argue that the localist position is untenable: Creature consciousness cannot simply be a background condition. Finally I argue that the minimal sense of self is a consequence of the temporal structure of consciousness. It follows that any theory of NCCs must explain how experiences with a complex temporal structure can be implemented in neural processing.
Article
Cognitive neuroscientists are currently busy searching for the neural signatures of conscious experience. I shall argue that the notion of neural correlates of consciousness employed in much of this work is subject to two very different interpretations depending on how one understands the relation between the concepts of “state consciousness” and “creature consciousness.” Localist theories treat the neural correlates of creature consciousness as a kind of background condition that must be in place in order for the brain to realize particular conscious experiences. Holists on the other hand take the neural correlates of creature consciousness to be a part of the core realizer of a particular conscious experience. My aim in this paper will be threefold. First I argue we should understand creature consciousness as a property of those creatures that have a minimal sense of self. Given this conception of creature consciousness I argue that the localist position is untenable: Creature consciousness cannot simply be a background condition. Finally I argue that the minimal sense of self is a consequence of the temporal structure of consciousness. It follows that any theory of NCCs must explain how experiences with a complex temporal structure can be implemented in neural processing.
Book
According to Thomas Metzinger, no such things as selves exist in the world: nobody ever had or was a self. All that exists are phenomenal selves, as they appear in conscious experience. The phenomenal self, however, is not a thing but an ongoing process; it is the content of a "transparent self-model." In Being No One, Metzinger, a German philosopher, draws strongly on neuroscientific research to present a representationalist and functional analysis of what a consciously experienced first-person perspective actually is. Building a bridge between the humanities and the empirical sciences of the mind, he develops new conceptual toolkits and metaphors; uses case studies of unusual states of mind such as agnosia, neglect, blindsight, and hallucinations; and offers new sets of multilevel constraints for the concept of consciousness. Metzinger's central question is: How exactly does strong, consciously experienced subjectivity emerge out of objective events in the natural world? His epistemic goal is to determine whether conscious experience, in particular the experience of being someone that results from the emergence of a phenomenal self, can be analyzed on subpersonal levels of description. He also asks if and how our Cartesian intuitions that subjective experiences as such can never be reductively explained are themselves ultimately rooted in the deeper representational structure of our conscious minds. Bradford Books imprint
Article
The performance of concentrative and mindfulness meditators on a test of sustained attention (Wilkins' counting test) was compared with controls. Both groups of meditators demonstrated superior performance on the test of sustained attention in comparison with controls, and long-term meditators were superior to short-term meditators. Mindfulness meditators showed superior performance in comparison with concentrative meditators when the stimulus was unexpected but there was no difference between the two types of meditators when the stimulus was expected. The results are discussed in relation to the attentional mechanisms involved in the two types of meditation and implications drawn for mental health.
Article
Timing is essential to the functioning of organisms. Perhaps because the time dimension plays such an important role in human life, the psychology of time was an important topic of early psychological research and theorizing. An examination of the role that time plays in people's lives can focus on various aspects of temporal experience. For example, a researcher can study what makes people judge events to be simultaneous, or judge one event as preceding or following another event. In this article, we focus on the processes that subserve experiences of short duration (ranging from seconds to minutes). Duration timing is essential for representing the immediate external environment. For example, driving or crossing a busy street requires the continual estimation of speed and duration. As people wait in a queue while shopping or receiving a service, feelings of lengthened duration may determine whether they complete the transaction or abandon it. A person using computer software assesses the time required to complete an operation; if this duration seems excessive, the attitude regarding the software will be negative. Because many everyday situations involve duration estimation, it is important to understand the underlying processes.