ArticlePDF Available

Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust: An Ethic of Social Flesh

Authors:
Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust:
An Ethic of Social Flesh
Associate Professor Carol Bacchi and
Dr. Chris Beasley
Politics Discipline
School of History and Politics
University of Adelaide
Refereed paper presented to the
Australasian Political Studies Association Conference
University of Adelaide University
Australia 29 September – 1 October 2004
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 2
Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
An Ethic of Social Flesh:
A proliferation of theoretical analyses and government discourses advocate the
development of social virtues, either care or trust, as ways past a perceived
contemporary crisis around the maintenance of social connectedness. There are
references to a 'crisis in trust' (Hudson 2004: 76) or a 'crisis in civic engagement' (Szreter
2002: 589), as well as references to a 'crisis of care' (Daly and Lewis 2000: 288) or a crisis
due to a 'care gap' (Sevenhuijsen 2003: 189). While many of these accounts focus on the
internal dynamics of nation-states, others, including Zygmunt Bauman (2001) and
Emmanuel Levinas (Bernasconi and Critchley 1991), raise the significance of these
issues for an emerging global community. A shared concern is 'atomistic individualism',
identified as a threat to stable, effective government and/or humane, tolerant human
relations.
The purpose of this paper is twofold. In the first instance, we intend to map the political
visions associated with the languages of care and trust, identifying problematic
premises. Additionally, we offer 'social flesh' as an alternative ethico-political starting
place for thinking critically about politics and community. Our engagement in these
debates does not indicate an uncritical acceptance of diagnoses of 'crisis'. In fact we
challenge the way in which 'crisis talk' tends to locate the 'problem' in the character of
citizens. Our target, by way of contrast, is the hegemonic social and political imaginary
that constructs citizens as independent, self-reliant and solely responsible for social
outcomes. Social flesh is put forward as an alternative paradigm, a new imaginary,
grounded in recognition of human intersubjective embodiment. The political vision it
inspires is democratic, emphasizing the need to create institutions where diverse bodily
experiences are given voice and recognition. The paper presumes a role for theory in
political praxis. It takes its inspiration from Clare Colebrook's (2000: 90-91) argument
that thought and theory are not distanced points 'of observation on the real', but
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 3
'activities of imaging bodies' and 'an anticipation of the future' -- 'the real's way of
folding back upon itself through a multiplicity of becomings.'
In the first part of the paper we argue that early care ethicists and most trust theorists
focus their attention on the need to produce particular kinds of citizens, either caring or
trusting people. Important distinctions between care and trust perspectives will be
identified, along with attention to significant divisions within the 'trust' camp.
Overriding these distinctions we identify a disturbing agreement among trust theorists
that something is amiss in citizen behaviour, a position that, in our view, produces
citizens as responsible for the inadequacies of current political regimes and as the ones
needing to change. There appears to be a near consensus that citizens lack trust and
therefore need to be encouraged to become trusting. The major disagreements are over
the means to this end and over the kind of trust to be encouraged.
A more recent generation of care ethicists (Sevenhuijsen 1997, 1998, 2003; Tronto 1993,
2001; Kittay 1998; Folbre 2001) move past the focus on one-to-one caring and care as a
moral disposition to insist that caring be considered a collective responsibility. These
theorists become the focus in the second part of the paper. In their work, the nature of
institutional supports for caring practices, rather than the behaviour of citizens,
becomes the problem. We find the focus on the ubiquity of caring practices and the shift
from moral disposition to the form and function of institutions useful but remain
concerned about several aspects of care ethics. The ambiguity surrounding the meaning
of care, in our view, undermines its usefulness as a guiding ethic. Moreover, its highly
normative character leaves it open to political manipulation. In particular, the
asymmetrical relationship presumed between 'carers' and 'cared for' inscribes hierarchy
and hence the potential for paternalism at the core of these relationships.
In the third part of the paper, we offer an ethic of social flesh as a more equitable and
less normatively prescriptive starting place for re-imagining social and political life.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 4
Making Citizens Behave
It is useful to deal in this initial section with both early care theorists and with those
who privilege trust as the basis of ethical connectedness because, as we shall see, there
are important overlaps in the arguments. Indeed, the languages are not strictly separate,
which in itself is telling. Many who proffer trust as foundational to healthier
community talk at times about the ways in which trust will lead to sympathy for others
and a willingness to help others. According to Putnam (1993: 88-89), 'Virtuous citizens
are helpful, respectful, and trustful toward one another, even when they differ on
matters of substance'. The attributes listed as accompanying trust commonly include
sympathy, reciprocity, altruism and care (Metlay 1999: 101-102).
1
On the other side
some care ethicists retain a special place for trust. For example, Selma Sevenhuijsen
(2003: 185), a contemporary leading proponent of care ethics, declares that 'an ethic of
care presupposes an ethic of trust.' In both cases we consider the focus on social virtues
as the key to healthy social relations inadequate and even retrograde.
In other work (Beasley and Bacchi 2000; Beasley and Bacchi, forthcoming 2004; Bacchi
and Beasley, forthcoming 2005) we have highlighted the ways in which early care
ethicists (Gilligan 1982; Held 1987, 1993, 2001) describe the ability to 'care' as a moral
attribute and have discussed the problems this creates for their argument. There is a
tendency among these early care ethicists to assume that, if a person learns to care in
one-to-one relationships, this will translate into a humane concern for distant others
and into humane social arrangements generally — locally, nationally and even
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 5
internationally. Mothering is put forward as the best nursery for producing caring
citizens (Ruddick 1990). The mechanisms by which an ethic derived from interactions
between particular others may be transferred to the public and international domains
are taken for granted rather than explained. In addition the hierarchical nature of many
caring relationships, including mothering, goes almost unnoticed (Shakespeare 2000).
Equally disturbing is the tendency to distance ethical theorizing from political practice.
Annette Baier (1987: 50 in Held 1993: 86), for example, sets at odds 'the male fixation on
the special skill of drafting legislation' and attention to relations of care and trust. The
implication in the work of early care ethicists is that care ethics has its own domain,
separate from law and legalistic interventions. Such an approach indicates a limited
engagement with or interest in political processes, not just in the strict traditional sense
of governance but in the sense most feminists employ -- that is, these writers display an
oddly restricted concern with power relations in society.
While those who position 'trust' as central to cooperative, collaborative relationships are
a diverse group, the work of the most prominent and best known theorists (Putnam
1993, 2000; Fukuyama 1995) shares the limitations we observe in early care theory. Such
writings promote trust as a desirable moral quality, are ambiguous about the means of
transmission from 'lower' to 'higher' levels of sociality, and neglect the relationship
between power and trust. Beyond this group, trust theorists in general tend to
recommend the generation of trust as a desirable goal, implicitly constituting citizens
who 'lack' trust as deficient. Importantly, the turn to trust loses the focus on bodily
interconnection found in care theory, leaving citizens to perform trust negotiations in
oddly disembodied ways.
The language of trust has a long heritage in Western political theory but has
experienced something of a renaissance in the last twenty years. The expressed concern
1
Many politicians in the West have begun to take on a language which links trust and care. For example,
Mark Latham (1998: 205), leader of the Australian Labor Party, advocates an increased 'preparedness of
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 6
among those who want to privilege trust as a key element in successful collective life is
a perceived declining public interest in politics. Low voter turnout in the United States
sparked the trust revival. 'Why', trust theorists want to know, 'are citizens turning away
from civic participation and what can be done about it?' The key concern appears to be
with the kinds of people that will sustain a democratic political culture and institutions
(see Sullivan and Transue 1999). These considerations have generated a plethora of
studies around the concepts of trust, social capital and civil society.
Social capital theorists embrace a variety of political visions. There are at least three
distinct positions:
the Putnam-Fukuyama camp who claim that 'psychic engagement' (Szreter
2002: 582) in close-up relationships and activities produces the sentiments required to
facilitate cooperation and economic exchange – the 'social glue' necessary for national
cohesion;
those who prefer 'cool' to 'hot' trust, 'trust as social lubricant' rather than trust
as 'social glue';
those who insist that the government has an important role to play in
generating social capital by providing services which reduce inequalities between
citizens.
Despite their differences, we suggest that all three positions, albeit to different degrees,
direct attention to the behaviours of citizens as the key to viable democratic politics.
Each position will be discussed in turn, with a closer examination of the first, given its
prominence in popular and political discourse.
The Putnam-Fukuyama camp is most explicit in focussing on the desirability of certain
kinds of character traits among citizens. The crucial issues motivating the analysis are
'poor behaviour', evinced in crime rates and family breakdown, and 'excessive judicial
pleas for particular rights' (Helly 2003: 21), behaviour described as excessively
... citizens to trust in and care for each other'.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 7
individualistic and self-serving (Fukuyama 1995: 284).
2
We are witnessing in this view
a 'downward spiral of contemporary societies into multiple communities and atomized
individuals' (Helly 2003: 20).
3
To counter this trend there is a call for a
'retraditionalizing of civil society' (Cohen 1999: 232), the invocation of pre-modern
bonds of social solidarity. Fukuyama (1995: 351) states that 'political liberalism ... needs
the support of aspects of traditional culture.'
There are different routes to this goal, however. Fukuyama, like James Coleman (1988),
an early progenitor of social capital theory, emphasizes the importance of socialization
in close family structures. Putnam by contrast privileges social relationships in
secondary associations. Participation in secondary groups, he argues, establishes social
bonds and teaches civic skills such as 'self-discipline, moderation and appreciation of
successful collaboration' (Misztal 1996: 14). From habits of cooperation and mutual trust
emerge citizens willing to shoulder obligation, loyal citizens (Pixley 1998; Barbalet
2000), deferential citizens (Janoski 1998), and/or compliant citizens (Costello 2003: 5).
The ultimate goal is social cohesion, with trust providing the 'social glue'. In this
account trust is not, or at least not simply, an innate psychological disposition, a view
that would put severe limits on the usefulness of trying to shape character.
4
Rather trust
emerges as a characteristic that can be generated through association with those who
share core values. Putnam (1993: 177) notes:
[t]rust itself is an emergent property of the social system as much as a personal
attribute. Individuals are able to be trusting (and not merely gullible) because of
the social norms and networks within which their actions are embedded.
2
A recent article in the Melbourne Age on violence in the workplace (Robinson 2004) captured this
concern. It quoted from organisational psychologist, Dr. Peter Cotton, who suggested that people have
become more aggressive because they have a more acute awareness of their rights. This 'rights culture'
is set against 'collective or community behaviour': 'It's a lack of spirituality and the pursuit of individual
goals which seems to be motivating people — but that is also a route to unhappiness in the long term.'
3
The Australian Productivity Commission (2003: viii) Report on Social Capital mentions as a key point the
possible adverse effects of 'strong internal group cohesion', referring here to sub-groups within the polity.
4
A number of studies have identified the psychological underpinnings of trust and tolerance. For
example, Marcus et al. (1995 in Sullivan and Transue 1999: 635) and Costa and McCrae (1992 in
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 8
The learning of 'trust' requires direct participation in one-to-one 'trusting' or in
associational life. The goal is to create the conditions which will produce ‘trusting’
citizens.
The focus on family/associations as the source of beneficial learning environments for
'virtuous citizens' lies behind the declared concern that, if the government provides too
many services, trust-building activities will be 'crowded out'. This explains the
popularity of volunteerism and devolution in much social capital theory (Costello 2003:
7). In Australia, for example, there are also direct links with the endorsement of 'mutual
obligation' by the political Right and 'mutual responsibility' by the political Left. The
argument here is that direct engagement by people in the performance of labour is
necessary to produce responsible citizens. We have here a 'nonstatist form of
communitarianism' (Fukuyama 1995: 279).
Care issues are relegated in this agenda to a responsibility of the domestic sphere. The
Australian Productivity Commission's Report (2003: ix) on Social Capital specifies that
home based care 'can be a more desirable and practical option than nursing home care'.
This is because democratic citizens are considered to need particular attributes and
skills, and these are seen to be produced though engagement in close-up activities such
as caring. The social bonding which takes place in these activities will, it is argued,
produce active citizens, countering the supposed apathy displayed in low voter
turnout.
5
There is an assumption here that close-up relationships produce
characteristics which transmit to the larger public sphere. A curious tension emerges in
the argument. Citizens will learn to trust government, but this trust cannot mean that
Sullivan and Transue 1999: 635) found that neuroticism, extroversion and openness to experiences all
predict levels of political tolerance fairly accurately.
5
We say 'supposed apathy' because we challenge the common view that low voter turn-out indicates the
kind of sluggish disinterest implied by the word 'apathy'. We prefer to characterise the growing aversion to
forms of political participation like voting as 'disaffection', capturing feelings of alienation and discontent.
This point is picked up later in the paper.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 9
they will want the government to provide basic services because citizens need to
provide these services themselves in order to develop 'trust' in government.
Social capital theory of this ilk marks a shift within liberalism from a wariness
regarding trust to an endorsement of trust as an imperative. In Locke citizens could trust
government if government proved worthy of trust. Now citizens are told that they
should, indeed, must trust government, or be found wanting in their performance as
citizens (Hardin 1999: 23). Fukuyama (1995: 7) declares: 'a nation's well-being, as well as
its ability to compete, is conditioned by a single, pervasive cultural characteristic, the
level of trust inherent in a society'. This trust depends upon the expression of common
traditions and norms, imposing cultural coherence on diverse 'others'.
The imperative 'to trust' produces trust as a form of governmentality (Mckay 2000: 2).
Nikolas Rose (1999: Chapter 5) traces the paradoxical development of a focus on
community in a period dominated by visions of independent economic actors. This
paradox is resolved, he argues, in the decision to govern through community/ies.
Communities and their constituents are to be held responsible for their own fate and for
the fate of the nation. It follows that citizens who do not trust are characterized as
deficient. An early study by Eckstein (1984 in Damico et al. 2000: 378) attributes the
failure of the poor to participate in politics or the workplace to 'the authoritarian culture
of the poor'. In contrast, Fukuyama (1995: 10) attributes the low trust evinced among
Afro-Americans to their lack of strong community. In these analyses outgroups cannot
win. They are described either as having too much or too little community.
Numerous authors question the assumption in Fukuyama and Putnam that 'virtues'
learned at home or in secondary associations translate into effective citizen participation
(Newton 2001: 173; Damico et al. 2000: 377; Misztal 1996: 199-200). This concern
regarding transmission parallels our challenge to early care ethicists who anticipated a
generalisation of caring sentiments from mothers to broad social arrangements.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 10
Going further, some trust theorists argue that — contra the claim of upward
transmission — close-up relationships, commonly referred to as generating bonding
social capital, can and do produce conflict, not cooperation, at higher political levels
(Sennett 1974). These trust theorists prefer a less intense, more 'civil' kind of trust,
though there are sharp disagreements among them about the kind of political order
'cool trust' involves. On the one side are those who praise 'cool' trust as creating just
sufficient lubrication for free and rational citizens to interact, with the role of
government limited to the provision of legal infrastructure (Silver 1985; Krygier 1996).
On the other side there are those who endorse forms of bridging and linking social
capital, based on cooperation among unequals, with a central role for the equalizing
policies of government (Szreter 2002; Fattore et al. 2003).
Martin Krygier (1996) typifies the first 'cool trust' camp. He argues that multi-member
polities need just enough trust to facilitate 'routine social relations' among 'non-
intimates'. This 'cool' trust is to be distinguished from more organic forms of trust
based on love or 'deep connection', trust which he sees as 'inimical to civil society'. Cool
trust, according to Krygier, produces a 'moderately inclusive' civility. This restrained
civility is preferable because it involves
multitudes of independent actors, going about their individual or freely chosen
affairs … able to choose to associate and participate (or not) in an independent
public realm, with an economy of dispersed economic actors and markets,
undergirded by a socially embedded legal order which grants and enforces legal
rights. (Krygier 1996:8).
The role of government is limited to upholding this legal order. Cool trust, it is argued,
relies on common traditions and norms and produces tolerance of 'weakly expressed
communal identities'.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 11
In this account trust is compatible with economic rationalism. Indeed, the subject of this
model of social relations is the rational, disembodied self-interested actor of the current
hegemonic economic paradigm. While there is some suggestion of a tempering of
atomistic individualism, it is no more than this. In addition Krygier’s approach
indicates an antagonism to interconnection. He asserts that cool distancing from
particularities produces tolerance, and hence he endorses broad commonalities and
weakly identified communal identities. This implies that sub-national identities are
considered to be problematic and should therefore be discouraged.
The second challenge to 'hot' associational trust offers a dramatically different vision of
social relations and the role of the state. In this version of social capital, Bourdieu-
inspired theorists identify close-up or bonding social capital as a resource employed in
the reproduction of social class. Newton (1999: 185), for example, makes the point that
'generalized interpersonal trust' is most strongly expressed 'not by members of
voluntary organizations ... but by the winners in society, insofar as it correlates most
strongly with education, satisfaction with life, income, class and race'. Because of a
commitment to a more egalitarian social vision, these theorists describe an important
role for the state in generating bridging and linking social capital by breaking down
boundaries between unequals. There is still a commitment to make the poor 'more
trusting', but the problem is no longer represented to be their lack of community or their
excess of community (see above), but their exclusion from full social participation. The
government is allocated a key role in evening out the social disparities which alienate
the poor and in creating a 'socially inclusive' society. In this scenario state and civil
society are interdependent. Trust flows downward from integrative social structures.
Fattore et al. (2003: 171) offer evidence that people who have confidence in social
institutions are more trusting generally.
Significantly, Szreter (2002), a keen supporter of state-generated social capital, insists
that social relations must be 'respectful' before they can generate trust. Respect as a
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 12
virtue marks his commitment to egalitarian values and a democratic polity. We see this
as a significant step forward in conceptualizing ethical social relations. Richard Sennett
(2004) pursues the importance of respect as a starting place for egalitarian politics.
However, in our view, the emphasis in Sennett on cultivating this 'virtue' in relations
between 'weak' and 'strong' citizens underplays human interdependence and
interconnection across the board, leaving in place an inegalitarian ethic of
protectionism.
6
As we argue later, assumptions that the 'strong' must 'take care' of the
'weak' provide limited starting places for imagining truly ethical community.
The dangers inherent in this model of social relations are clear in Szreter. Disturbingly,
in his view 'social capital can only flourish where a society sufficiently embraces the
values of egalitarianism combined with order and hierarchy' (Szreter 2002: 595.
Emphasis added.). More disturbing still are the different roles marked out for the rich
and poor in the social drama Szreter describes. The rich, according to Szreter, must
learn to recognize the plight of the poor and to react sensitively. If they do not do this,
they bear responsibility for the alienation of those less well-off. ‘At least some among
the elite must have their imagination enthused' and
if none among the wealthy and powerful in society will countenance this ... they
cannot be surprised if the poor draw their own defensive conclusions about the
nature of respect, reciprocity, and trust in their society. (Szreter 2002: 587, 613)
Szreter's heroes are turn-of-the-century Progressives, in particular reformers involved in
social experiments like Hull House. The paternalistic nature of relations between
6
There are links here with Iris Marion Young's (2003) critique of protectionist social relations that
constitute some groups as needing protection and other groups as able to deliver it.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 13
reformers and the poor in these experiments goes unremarked.
7
If this is the best social
capital egalitarians can deliver, it is sadly inadequate.
8
Other Bourdieu-inspired social capital theorists recognize with Szreter that more
powerful groups are usually in command of more social capital, and that trust as a
public good is unevenly distributed (Evers 2003; Fattore et al. 2003). Hence, unlike
Putnam, Fukuyama and Costello, who warn about the 'crowding out' effects of
government intervention, they see a role for government in 'social capital building'
(Evers 2003: 18). In different accounts this role is described as 'giving citizens a say and
a co-responsibility in designing future welfare states' and 'opinion building' (Evers 2003:
18), or providing more social resources, 'opportunities, income and welfare — that
make people willing and able to participate in their communities' (Fattore et al. 2003:
174). These versions of social capital provide a necessary corrective to 'civil society
determinism' (Evers 2003: 17), the impression that all else follows from associational
participation with no explanation of the mechanisms for transmission. However, these
accounts remain part of a project geared to producing 'trusting citizens' as the key to
social order and social cohesion, a project we consider misguided and even dangerous.
We do not wish to downplay the significance of the distinctive social visions among
social capital theorists. Analyses like Szreter's (and we could add the work of Eva Cox
2000) show that it is much too simple to claim that social capital theory is necessarily
anti-state. Indeed, Szreter (2002) makes it easier to identify those social capital theorists
7
Hull House was established by Jane Addams in Chicago in 1889. It formed part of what was called the
'settlement movement', a movement prompted by the desire to teach middle-class values to slum
dwellers. The settlement movement formed part of a wider reform approach commonly called
'progressivism', in which reformers saw themselves as members of a competent ruling elite who could
create a cradle-to-grave blueprint for a new, better-ordered society (Bacchi 1983: 11).
8
Social inclusion analyses commonly display the problems just identified in Szreter. They tend to assume
that the 'poor' are a distinct group (the lower 30%) who need to be assisted by the benevolent to integrate
(Levitas 1996: 17; 1998). Denise Helly (2003: 21) describes the image of society in social inclusion
analyses as 'a society made up of a central locus of individuals and a margin of failures'. A social
inclusion response is to define 'populations at risk, those considered unfit of (sic) an economic and social
performance without social assistance', and convince them to 'change their behavior and become more
qualified.'
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 14
who are anti-state. It follows that people who believe that the state has an important role
to play in providing collective services may well find the kind of analyses offered here a
convincing defense of social capital and trust (or respect) as useful ways to talk about
collective social relationships.
However, there are disturbing commonalities in social capital theory that we think need
to be highlighted. In particular there is a shared belief that 'trust' is a good thing, that
citizens lack trust, and that ways must be found to encourage citizens to trust one
another and the government. Despite important disagreements about the conditions
needed to produce 'trust' and about the best kind of 'trust' to encourage, the conviction
is that the fate of liberal democracy is bound up, at the last, with the 'quality of citizens'
(Berkowitz 1999: Preface in Wallach 2000: 169).
Social capital theorists of whatever ilk thus appear to accept that there is a crisis in civic
engagement, a 'problem' of citizen 'apathy', and this belief drives their commitment to
find ways to 'motivate' 'trust'. This grounding assumption is readily challenged. As
Dennis Altman (2001) has indicated in his comments on Putnam’s thesis concerning the
decline of American social and communal ties, mobilization around AIDS at least raises
doubts about the scope of Putnam’s claims. Moreover, it is possible to argue, as does
Ronald Inglehart (1999: 236), that elite-forms of participation like voting are declining
while other forms of citizen activism are flourishing.
9
There is also evidence that people
can declare their distrust of government all the while expressing a desire for
government to play a significant role in the provision of collective services (Fattore et al.
2003). Distrust of government most often correlates with distrust of specific political
regimes, not of government in general (Damico et al. 2000). Given this, in some
circumstances, distrust would have to be considered a sign of a healthy, not a
languishing, polity.
9
Verba, Schlozman, and Brady (1995 in Brewer 2003: 7) found evidence that decreased voting is not
accompanied by a general decrease in citizen activism or campaign related activities.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 15
In our view, the language of crisis around trust and 'civic engagement' creates the
conditions for sheeting home responsibility for these 'problems' to citizens themselves.
Sociality is seen to depend upon the inculcation of desired character traits, as in early
care theory, or of desirable citizen behaviours. An ethical sociality depends in these
accounts on creating ‘caring citizens’ or 'trusting citizens' or 'respecting citizens'. The
assumption here is that people are not caring or trusting, and need to be encouraged to
become so. This ignores the practices that maintain people in their embodied social
relations on a daily basis. Recognizing that caring is an on-going human practice
directs attention away from the feared 'limitations' of citizen character/behaviour to the
shape and form of those practices. This agenda, pursued by second generation care
ethicists, marks a significant shift in perspective in the pursuit of ethical community.
Care as a Collective Responsibility
Political theorists Joan Tronto (1993, 2001) and Selma Sevenhuijsen (1997, 1998a, 1998b)
have attempted to deal directly with the limitations of a moral philosophy version of an
ethic of care. They insist that feminists need to stop thinking about care as a
moral
disposition. Rather care ought to be seen as an important social practice which should be
considered in political deliberations about institutional responses to need. This move
shifts the discussion from one-to-one caring relationships to institutional caring
arrangements (see also Engster 2004). It draws attention to the already existing caring
practices of citizens, rather than presuming, as trust theorists tend to, that citizens need
to learn to trust and to care.
Feminists have a contested relationship to care, however. Carol Thomas (1993) notes a
divide between those who direct attention to the care that women provide in domestic
arrangements and who demand that this care be socially recognized, as against those
who insist that it is no longer adequate to call upon women to meet society's caring
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 16
needs. Increasingly this tension is being resolved in the direction of the latter position as
a response to what is commonly identified as a growing 'care gap'. This deficit in care is
attributed in large part to the increased participation of women in paid labour and their
consequent inability to provide as much personal care as they provided previously
(Sevenhuijsen 2003: 181). The focus increasingly in feminist analyses is upon finding
ways to meet this 'care deficit' (Misra 2003).
Despite this shared goal it is possible to identify serious disagreements about how this
need should be met. Sevenhuijsen, for example, in keeping with early care ethicists, is
concerned to delineate carefully a restricted role for the state. She refers disparagingly
to 'cockpit notions of government', echoing British PM Tony Blair when he rejects a
view of government as actively ‘rowing’ in favour of one which merely 'steers' (Blair
and Schroeder 1999). Despite expressed concerns about a 'de-caring of the welfare state',
her focus is explicitly on the importance of civil society. In this vision the role of public
policy is to create 'social spaces in which people can practice care, responsibility and
trust' (Sevenhuijsen 2003: 187). Sevenhuijsen's commitment to active citizenship and
'trust as social practice' (Severhuijsen 1998b) reiterates aspects of social capital theory,
specifically the insistance that 'citizen activities' provide the basis of social ties and
commitment. Like the early care ethicists Sevenhuijsen seems more than a little
uncertain about possible links between an ethic of care and state policy making. In
contrast, Nel Noddings (2002 in Engster 2004: 119) and Eva Feder Kittay (1999 in
Engster 2004: 120) use care ethics to ground a defense of a stronger welfare state.
10
The fact that care ethics can produce such contrasting political visions indicates that,
with 'care' as our yardstick of ethical practice, we remain very much in the realm of
interpretation. Sevenhuijsen is well aware of this but contends that it is useful,
nonetheless, to try and create 'rhetorical and discursive space for moral narratives of
10
A good deal of recent feminist policy analysis (see Misra 2003) wishes to establish 'carework' as a
public responsibility.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 17
care, which are marginalized in dominant discourses' (Sevenhuijsen 1998: 60). We
accept the importance of expanding the universe of political discourse as a means to
invigorating ethico-political debate and indeed wish to make a contribution to this
project, but we have serious reservations about 'care' as an ideal.
11
In our view, care is
both too ambiguous and too normative, leaving it open to abuse.
In other work (Beasley and Bacchi, forthcoming 2004; Bacchi and Beasley, forthcoming
2005) we note the alignment of endorsements of an ethic of care with traditional
conceptions of heterosexual family and sexuality, signalling a limit to the claim that an
ethic of care fosters sensitivity to difference and context. In addition, despite expressed
desires to avoid paternalism, an asymmetrical relationship is constructed between those
needing care and those delivering care, undermining the egalitarian potential of the
analysis. Sevenhuijsen (1998b: 7), for example, follows in the footsteps of early care
ethicists with her detailed exploration of one-to-one caring arrangements which
presuppose relations of dependence and vulnerability.
12
Even in accounts like Szreter’s
(2002) that insist on institutional provision of care, however, 'recipients' of care are
positioned as other than 'donors', as 'in need' in ways that 'donors' are presumed not to
be.
This kind of distinction appears also in some postmodern attempts to ground a new
ethical sociality. Levinas' reflections on ethical responsibility, for example, assume a
'radical asymmetry' in the 'apprehension of the Other', where the 'suffering of the one
before me' calls me 'out of my own insular subjectivity' (Dunphy 2004: 3). Relatedly,
Margrit Shildrick (2001: 238) notes how Iris Marion Young draws upon Levinas to
'theorize her reflections on public address and political inclusion.' Once again, the
11
Important feminist theorists like Iris Marion Young (1997: 82-3 in Sybylla 2001: 75) would like to see the
ethics of care extended to 'serve as a general ethical theory to ground a normative conception of politics
and policy.'
12
Roe Sybylla (2001: 72) identifies the ways in which caring can create weakness and dependence,
patronizing or diminishing the recipient. In her view, to counter this tendency, respect must come first and
there must be a refusal to speak for others.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 18
emphasis is on the ways in which the 'bodily need and possibility for suffering' of the
other 'makes an unavoidable claim on me' (Young 1999: 107 in Shildrick 2001: 238).
While postcolonial theorist Ghassan Hage (2003a, 2003b) enunciates an account of care
that is clearly about political caring based upon a notion of interconnection as social
practice, he conceives of the nurturing welfare state generating caring in individual
citizens, such that they will be able to care for ‘others’, especially those in need. In other
words the caring 'exchange' is still viewed as a form of reciprocated altruism.
The point we wish to make here is that those who want to promote institutional
responsibility for caring practices fail to identity the way in which their accounts retain
a hierarchical relationship between 'givers' and 'receivers'. Sennett's (2004) insistence on
the need for a respectful character to the interchange between 'weak' and 'strong'
provides a useful corrective here (see also Szreter 2002). However, so long as our ethical
starting place is benevolence, or compassion, or gift giving, or altruism, we reinstate
aspects of hierarchy which undermine egalitarian social relations (see Minow 1990;
Bacchi 2001; 2004). Iris Marion Young is acutely sensitive to the problematic aspects of
dependency relationships. She notes (2003: 16) that 'rights and dignity of individuals
should not be diminished just because they need help and support'. To this end she
points out the importance of challenging the assumption that 'a need for support or care
is more exceptional than normal'. Along similar lines Margrit Shildrick (2002) suggests
'a new mode of ethics that holds at its centre the vulnerability of being' (Clough 2003:
111). These insights are crucial for our argument and we pursue them below in our
reflections on embodied interconnection.
Social Flesh: a new political ethic
Second generation care ethicists mark a significant advance on earlier care theory by
shifting the focus from moral disposition to caring practices. Recognizing that caring
practices already take place highlights the limitations of theory that starts from a premise
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 19
that citizens have to be motivated to 'trust' or 'care' in order to generate integrative
sociality. However, caring practices are only one part of the complex and interweaving
layers of interconnection that characterise contemporary social relations. Our
necessarily embodied intersubjective existence involves caring but goes beyond caring
relationships to include shared occupation of geographical space, shared usage of
infrastructure and ongoing social interdependence within and across borders.
Recognition of these relationships, we suggest, marks a new point of departure for re-
imagining social and political life.
This line of thought involves conceptualizing citizens as embodied. As mentioned
earlier, the subject of trust theory is decidedly disembodied, marking a serious
limitation in its scope and usefulness. Notably second generation care ethicists put
embodiment on the political agenda but they deal only with quite specific aspects of
embodiment — those to do with bodily maintenance and nurturance, such as elder care
and child care (Beasley and Bacchi, forthcoming 2004; Bacchi and Beasley, forthcoming
2005). This limited focus emphasizes the dichotomy between those who care and those
cared for, highlighting the asymmetry we find so disturbing. Visions of ethical
community require, in our view, a broader conception of embodied intersubjectivity.
On this subject feminist body theory offers important advances on conventional views
about the 'relationship between' body and self. However, much of this theory remains
thinly physical, abstract and representational (Beasley and Bacchi 2000: 347). A key
limitation is the lack of attention to a critical aspect of bodily materiality — that is, its
formation and location within a political sociality as a body among bodies. There is a
neglect of the social space within which embodied subjects operate and a neglect of
inter-subject relations. On this point it is disappointing that Young's (2002) work on the
lived body pays insufficient attention to the necessarily social nature of bodily
interactions. This explains, we would suggest, the ease with which Young separates the
formation of identity from social structural factors: 'The person ... is an actor; she has an
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 20
ontological freedom to construct herself in relation to this facticity' (Young 2002: 415).
Young's insight in other work (2003) that we all need care and support seems to
disappear from her analysis of identity formation.
13
Some postmodern reflections on dominant Western conceptions of embodiment are
useful here. Lara Merlin (2003:165) points out that the 'Western body is constituted
through a fear of lack and of loss'. This subject attempts to 'defend itself against their
dual threats by folding in on itself, thereby precluding any relation with the other'. The
prominent place of acquisitive individualism in contemporary social theory confirms
this account, as do public policies predicated on rationalist decision-making or
cognition. Levinas (Wyschogrod 2003: 62) offers a different starting place for reflecting
on embodied subjectivity. He interprets sensation as 'depending on two distinct
functions of bodily existence: first, vulnerability and susceptibility, sensation's passive
side, and second, aesthetic ... articulation in its active dimension.' This leads to the
observation that corporeality is susceptible to pain and wounding, to sickness and
ageing: 'Pain penetrates to the heart of the active cognitive self and calls it to order.
Thus the ethical body in its susceptibility to wounding, to outrage and hurt ...
challenges the structure of the self as an egology' (Wyschogrod 2003: 63).
14
Despite the value of these insights, as noted earlier, this analysis retains a focus on 'the
fragility of the other' and the 'radical generosity of altruistic existence' (Wyschogrod
2003: 63), reinstating asymmetry at the core of the relationship. We suggest that
recognition of our common intersubjective embodiment marks a different ethical
moment. It shifts the focus from those constituted as dependent to human
interconnection. As Damico et al. (2000: 379) point out: '[M]any social interactions take
13
Roe Sybylla (2001: 73) notes perceptively that, while Young (1997: 83) speaks against paternalism,
she comes 'dangerously close to it herself when she writes in reference to pregnant drug users, "The
privileged and the powerful have a duty to ... protect the vulnerable from the consequences of their
compromised situation".' There are echoes here of Szreter's desire to 'enthuse' the imaginations of the
'elite'.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 21
place with people at a great distance from us. This distance does not lessen our
dependence on them: Indeed, our interdependence increases.' In this vein Kittay (1998:
133) remarks that there are no self-reliant workers and that 'self-sufficiency is a
conceptual chimera in a capitalist economy'. The challenge theoretically is to maintain
this insight and not lapse into versions of sociality that construct some groups as needy
and others as beneficent.
We offer the concept of social flesh as a way forward in rethinking the complex nature
of the interaction between subjectivity, embodiment, intimacy, social institutions and
social interconnection. Social flesh generalizes the insight that caring practices already
take place on an ongoing basis to recognition of the broad, complex sustenance of life
that characterizes embodied intersubjective existence. There is no sense here of 'givers'
and 'receivers'; rather we are all recognized as receivers of socially generated goods and
services. Social flesh necessarily inhabits a specific geographical space, emphasizing the
importance of environmentalist efforts to preserve that space (Macken 2004: 25). Social
flesh also marks our diversity, challenging those who would privilege some bodies over
others. We would also suggest that social flesh is less normatively prescriptive than
care. It is not a directive to behave in any particular way. Rather it provides a new basis
for thinking about the sorts of institutional arrangements necessary to acknowledge
social fleshly existence. The effect is to 'open up the scope of what counts as relevant'
(Shildrick 2001: 238). For example, it allows a challenge to current conceptualizations
which construct attention to the 'private sphere' as compensatory rather than as
necessary (Beasley and Bacchi 2000: 350).
We believe that this intervention, demanding a rethinking of the nature of embodied
interconnection, is particularly important as current government policies already
presume particular conceptions of bodies, often with undemocratic consequences. In
14
G. Thomas Couser (1997 in Major 2002: 41) agrees that 'body dysfunction is perhaps the most
common threat to the appealing belief that one controls one's destiny.'
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 22
other work (Bacchi and Beasley 2002) we identify a dichotomy operating in public
policy between conceptions of bodies as controlled by citizens, and conceptions of
citizens as controlled by their bodies. On the one side we find that the presumption of
bodies controlled by citizens underpins policies which do not 'infringe' on rational
body-controlling citizens, leaving in place structures that disenfranchise many. On the
other side the assumption that some citizens cannot control their bodies provides the
rationale for forms of often coercive regulation. Social flesh challenges the 'control over
body'/'controlled by body' distinction, and hence provides a different starting place for
institutional design.
Conclusion
In times like these, a new ethico-political ideal is required to contest the adequacy of
dominant understandings of social interaction as matters of choice and rational
decision-making.
15
Along with some trust and some care theorists, we wish to displace
the current hegemonic status of atomistic individualism. Contra much of this theory,
however, we consider the problem to lodge, not in the character deficiencies of citizens,
but at the level of social imaginaries. Theory that describes citizens as uncaring or as
lacking in trust leaves unchallenged the presumption that individuals shape their own
futures. In some versions (Fukuyama 1995; Costello 2003), in fact, it reasserts exactly
this belief. In our view, even those like Szreter and Hage who insist that political
institutions ought to provide basic social supports and to take the lead in generating
viable social relations, continue to insist that the outcome will be the production of
'trusting' or 'caring' citizens.
15
Mitchell Dean (1997 in Larner 2002: 19) notes that neo-liberalism is 'more an ethos or an ethical ideal,
than a set of completed or established institutions'. This highlights the need to offer contesting ethical
ideals that allow us to imagine political alternatives. Here we offer the bare bones of an ethical ideal we
call ‘social flesh’, an ideal that clearly requires elaboration in future work.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 23
Our starting place, by way of contrast, is the insight offered by care ethics, that caring
practices are already ongoing. We broaden this insight to include the full range of social
practices that sustain social fleshly existence. This broadening removes the asymmetrical
power relations lodged in descriptions of relations between 'carers' and 'cared for',
between 'givers' and 'receivers'. It shifts the discussion from the need for compassion
and open-hearted generosity to recognition of embodied interconnection. The focus
becomes mutual, instead of self-, reliance.
As an ethico-political ideal, social flesh demands a political response. In this context, we
do not consider characterizations of the political as 'always manipulation'
16
or as a 'male
fixation' (Baier 1987: 50 in Held 1993: 86) to be adequate. Indeed, the ideal of social flesh
is precisely about political sociality. However, this ideal does not presume that forms of
social recognition that flow from it are predictable or laudable. Rather it creates a point
of departure for imagining and debating appropriate forms of responsive
interconnection. This requires democratic institutional spaces with a broad constituency
empowered to share stories about social fleshly experience.
16
Levinas asserts a 'hiatus' between ethics and politics due to the assumption that politics is always
manipulation (Bell 2001).
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 24
References
Altman, Dennis (2001) ‘Case to the Contrary’, The Gay and Lesbian Review Worldwide 8(2):
39.
Bacchi, Carol (1983) Liberation Deferred? The ideas of the English-Canadian Suffragists, 1877-
1918
. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Reprinted 1985, 1987.
Bacchi, Carol (2001) 'Dealing with "difference"' in Paul Nursey-Bray and Carol Bacchi
(eds) Left Directions: Is there a Third Way? Perth: University of Western Australia
Press.
Bacchi, Carol (2004) 'Policy and Discourse: Challenging the Construction of Affirmative
Action as Preferential Treatment', Journal of European Public Policy 11(2): 128-146.
Bacchi, Carol and Beasley, Chris (2002) 'Citizen Bodies: is embodied citizenship a
contradiction in terms?' Critical Social Policy 22(2): 324-352.
Bacchi, Carol and Beasley, Chris (forthcoming 2005) 'Biotechnology and the political
limits of "care"' in Margrit Shildrick and Roxanne Mykitiuk (eds) Rethinking Feminist
Bioethics: The Challenge of the Postmodern. New York: MIT Press.
Baier, Annette (1987) 'The Need for More than Justice' in M. Hanen and K. Nielsen (eds)
Science, Morality and Feminist Theory. Calgary: University of Calgary Press.
Barbalet, J. M. (2000) 'Vagaries of Social Capital: Citizenship, Trust and Loyalty' in Ellie
Vasta (ed.) Citizenship, Community and Democracy. London: Macmillan. pp. 91-106.
Beasley, Chris and Bacchi, Carol (2000) 'Citizen Bodies: embodying ciitizens -- a feminist
analysis', International Feminist Journal of Politics, 2.
Beasley, Chris and Bacchi, Carol (forthcoming 2004) 'Imagine an ethical future: the
political limits of "care" in re-imagining notions of interconnection/community', paper
presented at the Gender Roundtable, University of Adelaide, 23 April, 2004. Under
consideration by Australian Feminist Studies.
Bauman, Z. (2001)
Community: Seeking Safety in an Insecure World
. Cambridge: Polity.
Bell, V. (2001) 'On ethics and feminism: reflecting on Levinas' ethics of non-
(in)difference', Feminist Theory 2: ?
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 25
Berkowitz, Peter (1999) Virtue and the Making of Modern Liberalism . Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Bernasconi, R. and Critchley, S. (eds) (1991) Re-Reading Levinas. Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
Blair, Tony and Schroeder, Gerhard (1999) 'Europe: The Third Way', Publicaciones y
Documentos, 7 June, p.4.
<http://www.fes.org.ar/FESARG/Publicacio...NeueMitteTonyBlair_GerhardSchorode
r.htm>
Bourdieu, Pierre (1985) 'The Forms of Capital' in John G. Richardson (ed.) Handbook of
Theory and Research for the Sociology of Education. New York: Greenwood.
Brewer, Gene A. (2003) 'Building social capital: civic attitudes and behavior of public
servants', Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 13(1): 5-26.
Clough, Robyn (2003) Review of Margrit Shildrick. Embodying the Monsters:
Encounters with the Vulnerable Self. London: Sage. Feminist Theory 4(1): 110-112.
Cohen, Jean (1999) 'Trust, voluntary association and workable democracy: the
contemporary American discourse of civil society' in Mark E. Warren (ed.) Democracy
and Trust.
Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 208-248.
Colebrook, Claire (2000) 'From Radical Representations to Corporeal Becomings: The
Feminist Philosophy of Lloyd, Grosz, and Gatens', Hypatia 15(2): 76-93.
Coleman, James (1990) Foundations of Social Theory. London: Belknap Press.
Coleman, Peter (2004) 'Spin takes on Trust', Weekend Australian April 17-18. Review of
Kieron O'Hara (2004) Trust: From Socrates to Spin. Icon Books.
Costa, P. T. and McCrae, R. R. (1992) Revised NEO Personality Inventory (NEO-PI-R) and
NEO Five Factor Inventory (NEO-FFI) Professional Manual. Odessa, FL: Psychological
Assessment Resources.
Costello, Peter (2003) 'Building social capital'. Speech to the Sydney Institute, 16 July.
<wysiwyg://54/http://www.smh.com.au/articles/2003/07/16/1058035070852.html>
Couser, G. Thomas (1997) Recovering Bodies: Illness, Disability, and Life Writing. Madisson:
University of Wisconsin Press.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 26
Cox, Eva (2000) 'Diversity and Community: Conflict and Trust' in Ellie Vasta (ed.)
Citizenship, Community and Democracy. London: Macmillan. pp. 71-90.
Daly, Mary and Lewis, Jane (2000) 'The concept of social care and the analysis of
contemporary welfare states',
British Journal of Sociology
51(2): 281-298.
Damico, Alfonso, Conway, M. Margaret and Damico, Sandra Bowman (2000) 'Patterns
of Political Trust and Mistrust: Three Moments in the Lives of Democratic Citizens',
Polity 32(3): 377-400.
Dean, Mitchell (1997) 'Sociology after Society' in D. Owen (ed.)
Sociology after
Postmodernism. London: Sage.
Dunphy, Floyd B. (2004) 'Post Deconstructive Humanism: the "New International" as
An-Arche'. <http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory_and_event/v007/7.2dunphy.html>
Eckstein, Harry (1984) 'Civic Inclusion and Its Discontents',
Daedalus
113: 107-116.
Engster, Daniel (2004) 'Care Ethics and Natural Law Theory: Toward an Institutional
Political Theory of Caring', The Journal of Politics 66(1): 113-135.
Evers, Adalbert (2003) 'Social Capital and Civic Commitment: On Putnam's Way of
Understanding',
Social Policy & Society
2(1): 13-21.
Folbre, Nancy (2001) The Invisible Heart: Economics and Family Values. New York: New
Press.
Fukuyama, Francis (1995) Trust: The Social Virtues and the Creation of Prosperity. London:
Hamish Hamilton.
Fattore, Toby, Turnbull, Nick and Wilson, Shaun (2003) '"More Community!" Does the
Social Capital Hypothesis Offer Hope for Untrusting Societies?' The Drawing Board: An
Australian Review of Public Affairs 3(3) 165-179.
Gilligan, Carol (1982)
In a Different Voice.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Hage, G. (2003a) Against Paranoid Nationalism: searching for hope in shrinking society.
Annandale, Sydney: Pluto Press.
Hage, G. (2003b) 'On Worrying: the lost art of the well-administered national cuddle',
Borderlands
, 2.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 27
Hardin, Russell (1999) 'Do we want to trust in government?' in Mark E. Warren (ed.)
Democracy and Trust. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 22-41.
Held, Virginia (1987) 'Feminism and Moral Theory' in E. F. Kittay and D. Meyers (eds)
Women and Moral Theory
. Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield.
Held, Virginia (1993) Feminist Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Held, Virginia (2001) 'Caring Relations and Principles of Justice' in J. Sterba (ed.)
Controversies in Feminism. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
Helly, Denise (2003) 'Social cohesion and cultural plurality', Canadian Journal of Sociology
28(1): 19-44. Translated from the French by Robert F. Barsky and Patricia Foxen.
Hudson, Bob (2004) 'Trust: Towards Conceptual Clarification', Australian Journal of
Political Science 39(1): 75-87.
Inglehart, Ronald (1999) 'Postmodernization Erodes Respect for Authority, but
Increases Support for Democracy' in Pippa Norris (ed.) Critical Citizens: Global Support
for Democratic Government. Oxford: OUP.
Janoski, Thomas (1998) Citizenship and Civil Society: a framework of rights and obligations in
liberal, traditional, and social democratic regimes.
Cambridge, New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Kittay, Eva Feder (1998) 'Welfare dependency, and a public ethic of care', Social Justice
25(1): 123-146.
Kittay, Eva Feder (1999)
Love's Labor: Essays on Women, Equality, and Dependency
. New
York: Routledge.
Kryger, Martin (1996) 'The Sources of Civil Society', Background Briefing, Radio
National, 15 September. <http://www.abc.net.au/m/talks/bbing/stories/s10754.htm>
Latham, Mark (1998)
Civilising Global Capital: New Thinking for Australian Labor
. Sydney:
Allen and Unwin.
Larner, Wendy (2000) 'Neo-liberalism: Policy, Ideology, Governmentality', Studies in
Political Economy 63: 5-25.
Levitas, Ruth (1996) 'The concept of social exclusion and the new Durkheimian
hegemony', Critical Social Policy 16: 5-20.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 28
Levitas, Ruth (1998) The inclusive society? social inclusion and New Labour. Basingtoke:
Macmillan.
McKay, Sue (2000) The Politics of Trust. Honours Thesis, Department of Politics,
University of Adelaide.
Macken, Julie (2004) 'Left right, left right ... Old ideas march on', The Weekend Australian
Financial Review, May 22-23, p.25.
Major, William (2002) 'Audre Lorde's The Cancer Journals: Autopathology as Resistance',
Mosaic
35(2): 39-56.
Marcus, G. E., Sullivan, J. L., Theis-Morse, E., Wood, S. L. (1995) With Malice Toward
Some: How People Make Civil Liberties Judgments. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Merlin, Lara (2003) 'Perverse ethics: The body, gender and intersubjectivity',
Feminist
Theory 4(2): 165-178.
Metlay, Daniel (1999) 'Institutional Trust and Confidence: A Journey into a Conceptual
Quagmire', in George Cvetkovick & Ragnar E. Lofstedt (eds) Social Trust and the
Management of Risk. London: Earthscan. pp. 100 -116.
Minow, Martha (1990) Making All the Difference: Inclusion, Exclusion and American Law.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Misra, Joya (2003) 'Caring about care', Feminist Studies 29(2): 387 - 403.
Misztal, Barbara A. (1996)
Trust in Modern Societies: The Search for the Bases of Social
Order. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Newton, K. (1999) 'Social and political trust in established democracies' in R. K.
Fullinwider (ed.) Civil Society, Democracy, and Civic Renewal. NY: Rowman & Littlefield.
Newton, K. (2001) 'Trust, social capital, civil society, and democracy',
International
Political Science Review 22(2): 201-214.
Noddings, Nel (2002) Starting at Home: Caring and Social Policy. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Pixley, Jocelyn (1998) 'Social Movements, Democracy and Conflicts over Institutional
Reform' in Paul Symth & Bettina Cass (eds) Contesting the Australian Way: States, Markets
and Civil Society. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 138-153.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 29
Productivity Commission (2003) Social Capital: Reviewing the Concept and its Policy
Implications. Canberra: AusInfo.
Putnam, Robert D. (1993)
Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy.
Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Putnam, Robert D. (2000) Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community.
New York: Simon and Schuster.
Robinson, Paul (2004) 'Violence at work: all the rage',
Melbourne Age,
29 May.
Rose, Nikolas (1999) Powers of Freedom: Reframing Political Thought. Cambridge, New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Ruddick, S. (1990) Maternal Thinking. London: The Women's Press.
Sennett, R. (1977) The Fall of Public Man. New York: Knopf.
Sennett, R. (2004) Respect: The Formation of Character in an Age of Inequality. Allen Lane.
Sevenhuijsen, Selma (1997) 'Feminist Ethics and Public Health Care Policies: A Case
Study on the Netherlands' in P. DiQuinzio and I. M. Young (eds)
Feminist Ethics and
Social Policy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Sevenhuijsen, Selma (1998a) Citizenship and the Ethics of Care. London: Routledge.
Sevenhuijsen, Selma (1998b) 'Too Good to be True? Feminist considerations about trust
and social cohesion',
IWM Working Paper
No. 3. Vienna: Institute for Human Sciences.
Sevenhuijsen, Selma (2003) 'The place of care: The relevance of the feminist ethic of care
for social policy', Feminist Theory 4(2): 179-197.
Shakespeare, Tom (2000) 'The Social Relations of Care' in Gail Lewis, Sharon Gewirtz
and John Clarke (eds)
Rethinking Social Policy
. London: Sage.
Shildrick, Margrit (2001) 'Reappraising feminist ethics: Developments and debates',
Feminist Theory 2(2): 233-244.
Shildrick, Margrit (2002) Embodying the Monsters: Encounters with the Vulnerable Self.
London: Sage.
Carol Bacchi & Chris Beasley: Moving Beyond Care and/or Trust
Page 30
Silver, Allan (1985) '"Trust" in social and political theory' in Morris Janowitz, Gerald D.
Suttles and Mayer N. Zald (eds) The Challenge of Social Control. Norwood, NJ: Ablex Pub.
Sullivan, J. L. and Transue, J. E. (1999) 'The Psychological Underpinnings of Democracy:
A Selective Review of Research on Political Tolerance, Interpersonal Trust, and Social
Capital', Annual Review of Psychology 625-650.
Sybylla, Roe (2001) 'Hearing whose voice? The ethics of care and the practices of liberty:
a critique', Economy and Society 30(1): 66-84.
Szreter, Simon (2002) 'The state of social capital: Bringing back in power, politics and
history', Theory and Society 31: 573-621.
Thomas, Carol (1993) 'De-constructing concepts of care', Sociology 27(4): 649 - 670.
Tronto, J. (1993)
Moral Boundaries.
New York: Routledge.
Tronto, J. (2001) 'Who Cares? Public and Private Caring and the Rethinking of
Citizenship' in N. Hirschmann and U. Liebert (eds) Women and Welfare. New Brunswick:
Rutgers University Press.
Verba, S. K., Schlozman, K. L. and Brady, H. E. (1995) Voice and Equality: Civic
Voluntarism in American Politics. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Wallach, John R. (2000) 'Can Liberalism Be Virtuous?'
Polity
23: 163 -174.
Wyschogrod, Edith (2003) 'Towards a Postmodern Ethics: Corporeality and Alterity' in
Edith Wyschogrod and Gerald P. McKenny (eds) The Ethical. Oxford: Blackwell
Publishing. pp. 54-65.
Young, Iris Marion (1997)
Intersecting Voices: Dilemmas of Gender, Political Philosophy, and
Policy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Young, Iris Marion (2002) 'Lived Body vs Gender: Reflections on Social Structure and
Subjectivity', Ratio 15(4): 410-428.
Young, Iris Marion (2003) 'The logic of masculinist protection: reflections on the current
security state', Signs 29(1): 1-26.
... culture, gender, socio-economic status, etc.) may influence and shape the everyday emotional experience. While considering caregiving as a complex, relational, reciprocal, embodied and emotional act (Bacchi & Beasley, 2004), we aim in this secondary analysis to geographically explore the emotion discourse of a diverse group of men (n = 19) through a thematic analysis of interview data drawn from a larger mixed-methods study. In the following sub-sections, we introduce the field of emotional geographies and the context of family caregiver men in Canada. ...
... For example, gendered forces are instilled within 'ethics of care' theory (practice or virtue), which is traditionally associated with the 'feminine duty' to affirm caring motivation, emotion and the body in moral deliberation (Sander-Staudt, 2016). Our findings echo what others have previously argued, that there is a need to move away from ideals of women and men as homogenous groups who share common perspectives rooted in their biological capacity for emotion and character traits (Bacchi & Beasley, 2004;Hankivsky, 2005;Sander-Staudt, 2016). Rather, it is important to acknowledge the diversity that exist within these gendered groups of men and women, as well as those who identify along the spectrum of gender, that is, being a man, women, both, neither or something in between or beyond. ...
... Rather, it is important to acknowledge the diversity that exist within these gendered groups of men and women, as well as those who identify along the spectrum of gender, that is, being a man, women, both, neither or something in between or beyond. Furthermore, care is often viewed as something that is the motivated by strong, moral and altruistic people who 'care for' the weak, vulnerable and dependent (Bacchi & Beasley, 2004). Although this analysis focuses on the perspectives of caregivers, it is important to acknowledge that the men's relationship to care recipients is not simply unidirectional (e.g. a 'caregiver' providing for a 'care receiver'). ...
Article
Full-text available
Care exchanges are imbued with emotion, yet few geography of caregiving researchers have explored how emotions shape such experiences. Furthermore, the emotions of caregiver men have been largely overlooked. As such, this secondary analysis aims to geographically explore the emotion discourse of a diverse group of men caregiving for family members with multiple chronic conditions. Drawing on semi-structured interviews with nineteen men caregivers in Canada, our thematic findings reveal that the men’s discourse portrayed emotions experienced relationally at three levels: Between the caregivers and their own selves, others and the wider community. It was also found that the men commonly expressed their emotional experiences using geographic notions of distance (e.g. feeling far, isolated) and proximity (e.g. feeling close, connected) and that these emotions were further complicated by the participants’ diversity or situated ‘place-in-the-world’. Overall, our findings demonstrate the importance of emotional geographies in caregiver men’s lived realities and how they move between distance and proximity in order to manage their emotions as caregivers. By considering caregiver diversity and the role emotions play in shaping caregiver experiences, programs, services and best practice can become better informed on ways to enhance the provision of more context sensitive and equitable caregiver support.
... Algunas feministas (Sevenhuijsen, 1998) y otras investigadoras que analizan los trabajos de cuidado, por ejemplo Martín (2008b), critican los alcances de la idea de una "ética del cuidado". Desde su punto de vista, este enfoque idealiza el cuidado y esencializa el trabajo de las mujeres que se emplean como cuidadoras al reforzar los estereotipos tradicionales de la "buena mujer" ( Bacchi y Beasley, 2004); mientras su contraparte, la "mala mujer", donde el estigma social ubica a las trabajadoras sexuales (Hurtado, 2011). También señalan que esta perspectiva obvia cuestiones importantes como las relaciones de poder que se establecen entre quienes cuidan y quienes reciben los cuidados; por ejemplo, el control, el maltrato, la coacción o el abuso por parte de las cuidadoras y, a la inversa, el chantaje moral, emocional y económico que ejercen los que reciben hacia quienes les prestan los cuidados (Martín, 2008b). ...
... En algunos trabajos, como el del Colectivo IOÉ (2001), el de Arango (2010) y el de Hurtado (2011), los autores establecen que, en condiciones de asimetría y marginalidad, lo que acontece es que las mujeres, en particular las inmigrantes, se enfrentan a la naturalización de la servidumbre y de la sumisión, lo cual se contrapone a los principios que profesa "la ética del cuidado", que apelan a que las mujeres asumen voluntariamente dicha ética. Por lo regular, quienes realizan tareas de cuidado son mujeres que se ven forzadas a responder a las exigencias de este tipo de trabajo y no asumen de manera autónoma la responsabilidad de cuidar a otros (Colec- tivo IOÉ, 2001) como si se tratara de una supuesta condición natural de las mujeres (Sevenhuijsen, 1998;Bacchi y Beasley, 2004;Hurtado, 2011). ...
Book
Full-text available
En un escenario de encuentros globales de mercados económicos regulados por el capital, resulta imprescindible pensar articuladamente sobre el conjunto de contextos, políticas y agentes que subyacen y dinamizan los complejos entramados que articulan las desigualdades de género (De Oliveira, 2007). Desde el enfoque de género que sostiene este trabajo, es de nuestro interés resaltar y complejizar los variados y cruciales procesos de empoderamiento y autonomía que los sectores económicos femeninos subalternizados construyen para conseguir, y en su caso, mantener una autonomía económica de cara a su sustentabilidad como colectivo social.
... (Carrasco, 2001a: 15). Esta constatación tiene fuertes implicaciones analíticas, ya que no puede distinguirse entre actividades con sustituto de mercado y sin él -la consideración de que existe una relación de sustitución entre el trabajo no remunerado y la compra en el mercado se complejiza-y las esferas no monetizadas en ningún caso pueden entenderse en términos derivados de un paradigma mercantil -así, se complica el concepto mismo de trabajo o, incluso, del tiempo;Beasley (1994) propone hablar del sexo como uno de los trabajos que se dan en el espacio doméstico; Hewitson (1999) analiza la componente económica del embarazo y la incapacidad de captarla con las herramientas analíticas androcéntricas, incluso si median transacciones monetarias, como en el caso de las madres de alquiler. También aparecen retos políticos, porque sacar a la luz nuevas dimensiones económicas implica sacar a la luz nuevas desigualdades sociales. ...
Article
Full-text available
Este texto aborda la que se denomina crisis de los cuidados, proceso actual de reorganización de la forma de cobertura de la necesidad de cuidados de la población que implica una reestructuración del conjunto del sistema socioeconómico en el estado español. El texto e abre con un debate teórico sobre los conceptos y herramientas analíticas que, ligados a las propuestas de la economía feminista, permiten abordarla, para pasar, posteriormente, al análisis de la crisis propiamente dicho. Sin pretender realizar un examen exhaustivo, se busca desplazar las coordenadas del debate público en torno a esta cuestión: resaltando aquellos aspectos que tienden a permanecer invisibilizados y mostrando la interrelación y relevancia estructural de factores que tienden a omprenderse de forma aislada y como desajustes coyunturales. Se argumentará que la crisis de los cuidados supone una oportunidad para realizar una crítica estructural al sistema socioeconómico que integre el género como categoría analítica central, y para encontrar nexos teóricos y políticos de confluencia y enriquecimiento mutuo entre la economía feminista y otras perspectivas de pensamiento económico crítico.
Article
Full-text available
El presente texto presenta los resultados de una investigación antropológica centrada en el funcionamiento de distintos proyectos de cuidado comunitario (dos de vivienda cooperativa, uno de ellos senior, y otro de crianza colectiva). A través de una aproximación etnográfica, se comparan los discuros y las prácticas presentes en las distintas experiencias. Los resultados muestran la trascendencia de la individualidad como elemento común en el sentido que otorgan los participantes a los proyectos, y el empleo de significados situados entre el parentesco y la amistad a falta de referentes culturales de cuidado comunitario. En segundo lugar, la investigación revela el uso del concepto de cuidado para nombrar situaciones de muy diversa intensidad y compromiso, lo cual conduce a elaborar la categorización etic de cuidados gaseosos, líquidos y sólidos. Por último, partiendo de esa misma categorización, la investigación encuentra una modulación de las obligaciones morales de los participantes en función de la intensidad de los cuidados, mostrando así los límites de las experiencias a la hora de afrontar los cuidados materiales más sólidos.
Article
Full-text available
The present article argues that the main contribution of contemporary feminist theory on vulnerability stems from the distinction of two possible kinds of vulnerability: an ontological vulnerability and a vulnerability linked to various processes (social, cultural, economic and juridical) of vulnerabilisation. This contribution is not limited to the critical and deconstructive level. As a positive proposal, it advances in the direction of an individual which, recovering its own relational, embodied, "fleshy" and situated dimension, abandons the illusion of its own sovereignty, accepts its vulnerability like an opening up to others, and thus also accepts the responsibility for an open and democratic dialogue and the need for institutions inspired by an "enabling" conception of justice (cf. Young 1990).
Chapter
The book presents the ethics of care as a promising alternative to more familiar moral theories. The ethics of care is only a few decades old, yet it has become a distinct moral theory or normative approach, relevant to global and political matters as well as to the personal relations that can most clearly exemplify care. The book examines the central ideas, characteristics, and potential importance of the ethics of care. It discusses the feminist roots of this moral approach and why the ethics of care can be a morality with universal appeal. The book explores what is meant by “care” and what a caring person is like. Where such other moral theories as Kantian morality and utilitarianism demand impartiality above all, the ethics of care understands the moral import of ties to families and groups. It evaluates such ties, differing from virtue ethics by focusing on caring relations rather than the virtues of individuals. The book proposes how values such as justice, equality, and individual rights can “fit together” with values such as care, trust, mutual consideration, and solidarity. In considering the potential of the ethics of care for dealing with social issues, the book shows how the ethics of care is more promising than other moral theories for advice on how limited or expansive markets should be, showing how values other than market ones should have priority in such activities as childcare, health care, education, and in cultural activities. Finally, the book connects the ethics of care with the rising interest in civil society, and with limits on what law and rights are thought able to accomplish. It shows the promise of the ethics of care for dealing with global problems and with efforts to foster international civility.
Book
This new edition of Eva Feder Kittay's feminist classic, Love's La,bor, explores how theories of justice and morality must be reconfigured when intersecting with care and dependency, and the failure of policy towards women who engage in care work. The work is hailed as a major contribution to the development of an ethics of care. Where society is viewed as an association of equal and autonomous persons, the work of caring for dependents figures neither in political theory nor in social policy. While some women have made many gains, equality continues to elude many others, as in large measure, social institutions fail to take into account the dependency of childhood, illness, disability and frail old age and fail to adequately support those who care for dependents. Using a narrative of her experiences caring for her disabled daughter, Eva Feder Kittay discusses the relevance of her analysis of dependency to significant cognitive disability. She explores the significance of dependency work by analyzing John Rawls' influential liberal theory and two examples of public policy-welfare reform and family leave-to show how theory and policy fail women when they fail to understand the centrality of dependency to issues of justice. This second edition has updated material on care workers, her adult disabled daughter and key changes in welfare reform. Using a mix of personal reflection and political argument, this new edition of a classic text will continue to be an innovative and influential contribution to the debate on searching for greater equality and justice for women.
Book
Should a court order medical treatment for a severely disabled newborn in the face of the parents' refusal to authorize it? How does the law apply to a neighborhood that objects to a group home for developmentally disabled people? Does equality mean treating everyone the same, even if such treatment affects some people adversely? Does a state requirement of employee maternity leave serve or violate the commitment to gender equality? Martha Minow takes a hard look at the way our legal system functions in dealing with people on the basis of race, gender, age, ethnicity, religion, and disability. Minow confronts a variety of dilemmas of difference resulting from contradictory legal strategies-strategies that attempt to correct inequalities by sometimes recognizing and sometimes ignoring differences. Exploring the historical sources of ideas about difference, she offers challenging alternative ways of conceiving of traits that legal and social institutions have come to regard as "different." She argues, in effect, for a constructed jurisprudence based on the ability to recognize and work with perceptible forms of difference. Minow is passionately interested in the people-"different" people-whose lives are regularly (mis)shaped and (mis)directed by the legal system's ways of handling them. Drawing on literary and feminist theories and the insights of anthropology and social history, she identifies the unstated assumptions that tend to regenerate discrimination through the very reforms that are supposed to eliminate it. Education for handicapped children, conflicts between job and family responsibilities, bilingual education, Native American land claims-these are among the concrete problems she discusses from a fresh angle of vision. Minow firmly rejects the prevailing conception of the self that she believes underlies legal doctrine-a self seen as either separate and autonomous, or else disabled and incompetent in some way. In contrast, she regards the self as being realized through connection, capable of shaping an identity only in relationship to other people. She shifts the focus for problem solving from the "different" person to the relationships that construct that difference, and she proposes an analysis that can turn "difference" from a basis of stigma and a rationale for unequal treatment into a point of human connection. "The meanings of many differences can change when people locate and revise their relationships to difference," she asserts. "The student in a wheelchair becomes less different when the building designed without him in mind is altered to permit his access." Her book evaluates contemporary legal theories and reformulates legal rights for women, children, persons with disabilities, and others historically identified as different. Here is a powerful voice for change, speaking to issues that permeate our daily lives and form a central part of the work of law. By illuminating the many ways in which people differ from one another, this book shows how lawyers, political theorist, teachers, parents, students-every one of us-can make all the difference.