ArticlePDF Available

Reasoning by Contradiction in Dynamic Geometry

Authors:

Abstract

This paper addresses contributions that dynamic geometry systems (DGSs) may give in reasoning by contradiction in geometry. We present analyses of three excerpts of students’ work and use the notion of pseudo object, elaborated from previous research, to show some specificities of DGS in constructing proof by contradiction. In particular, we support the claim that a DGS can offer “guidance” in the solver’s development of an indirect argument thanks to the potential it offers of both constructing certain properties robustly, and of helping the solver perceive pseudo objects.
Baccaglini-Frank, A., Antonini, S., Leung, A., & Mariotti, M. A. (2013). Reasoning by contra-
diction in dynamic geometry. PNA, 7(2), 63-73.
REASONING BY CONTRADICTION IN
DYNAMIC GEOMETRY
Anna Baccaglini-Frank, Samuele Antonini, Allen Leung, and Maria Alessandra
Mariotti
This paper addresses contributions that dynamic geometry systems
(DGSs) may give in reasoning by contradiction in geometry. We present
analyses of three excerpts of students’ work and use the notion of pseudo
object, elaborated from previous research, to show some specificities of
DGS in constructing proof by contradiction. In particular, we support
the claim that a DGS can offer guidance in the solver’s development of
an indirect argument thanks to the potential it offers of both constructing
certain properties robustly, and of helping the solver perceive pseudo
objects.
Keywords: Dynamic geometry; Indirect argument; Proof; Proof by contradiction;
Pseudo object
Razonamiento por contradicción en geometría dinámica
Este artículo aborda las contribuciones que los sistemas de geometría
dinámica (DGSs) pueden dar al razonamiento por contradicción en
geometría. Presentamos un análisis de tres extractos del trabajo de es-
tudiantes y el uso de la noción de pseudo-objeto, elaborado a partir de
investigaciones anteriores, para mostrar algunas especificidades del
DGS en la construcción de pruebas por contradicción. En particular,
afirmamos que un DGS puede orientar en el desarrollo de un argumento
indirecto gracias a las posibilidades que ofrece tanto para construir só-
lidamente algunas propiedades como para ayudar a percibir los pseudo-
objetos.
Términos clave: Argumento indirecto; Geometría dinámica; Prueba; Prueba por
contradicción; Pseudo-objeto
Literature shows that although much research has been conducted on the themes
of proof and argumentation in mathematics education, rarely do the studies focus
on particular proof structures, such as proof by contradiction. The research cen-
A. Baccaglini-Frank, S. Antonini, A. Leung, and M. A. Mariotti
PNA 7(2)
64
tered on proof by contradiction has pointed to various difficulties it presents for
students (see for example, Antonini & Mariotti, 2007, 2008; Leron, 1985; Mar-
iotti & Antonini, 2006; Wu Yu, Lin, & Lee, 2003) especially the difficulties re-
lated to the formulation and interpretation of negation, to the managing of impos-
sible mathematical objects, to the gap between contradiction and the proved
statement.
Some literature takes into consideration contributions that DGSs may give to
students’ production of indirect arguments. Within the very little literature in this
area, there is a study conducted by Leung and Lopez-Real that describes a proof
by contradiction produced by two students working in a DGS. This case study
triggered the development of a framework on theorem acquisition and justifica-
tion in a DGS that the authors used to put together a scheme for “seeing” proof
by contradiction in a DGS (Leung & Lopez-Real, 2002). We will illustrate as-
pects of this framework that we will make use of and develop further in the fol-
lowing section.
With the present paper we intend to contribute to better describe roles that a
DGS can have in reasoning by contradiction. We will further elaborate and make
use of notions from Leung and Lopez-Real’s theoretical framework, in particular
that of pseudo object, to analyze such roles. Moreover, we will provide analyses
of three excerpts of students’ work to show particular construction choices in a
DGS can guide/promote significantly solvers’ development of indirect argu-
ments/reasoning by contradiction.
METHODOLOGY
The data presented was collected during two different studies on the role of a
DGS in processes of conjecture-generation and proof in the context of open prob-
lems in geometry. One study (Leung & Lopez-Real, 2002) was conducted with
Form 4 (Grade 10) students in a band one secondary school in Hong Kong. Hong
Kong’s secondary schools are streamed according to students’ ability. A band
one school is for the most able students. The second study (Baccaglini-Frank,
2010; Baccaglini-Frank & Mariotti, 2010) was conducted with Italian high
school students (16-18 years old) from three different licei scientifici. The partic-
ipants of both studies had been working with dynamic geometry for at least a
year prior to when the studies were carried out. Data was collected in the forms
of audio and video tapes and transcriptions of the introductory lessons, Cabri-
files worked on by the instructor and the students during the classroom activities,
audio and video tapes, screenshots of the students’ explorations, transcriptions of
the task-based interviews, and the students’ work on paper that was produced
during the interviews.
Reasoning by Contradiction in Dynamic Geometry
PNA 7(2)
65
THE NOTION OF PSEUDO OBJECT
When working with paper and pencil and reasoning by contradiction, slight inac-
curacies in the drawing allow the figure to represent properties, which a proper
construction would not permit. For example, on paper, with no trouble one can
assume to have drawn a triangle, of which two bisectors intersect at a right angle.
In this case, one may easily be unaware of his/her assumption of contradictory
properties, and it is completely up to him/her to become aware of a contradiction.
In a DGS a similar situation to that described in paper and pencil occurs
when the solver constructs a figure with a robust property (Healy, 2000) while
mentally imposing on it a contradictory property without a robust construction.
By robust construction in a DGS, we mean a construction that can keep the de-
sired properties of a figure invariant under dragging. What happens if, instead,
the solver attempts to construct both properties robustly? However, the solver
may be uncertain whether such a construction is possible or not, or s/he may real-
ize the impossibility when interpreting the DGS feedback. Such feedback in-
cludes the making explicit, robustly, of all properties that are derived from the
properties constructed robustly during the construction steps of the figure. This is
the case we find particularly interesting. In this paper we report on ways of rea-
soning that seem to be induced by the feedback provided by the DGS.
As mentioned above, in a DGS no constructible figure can be realized by ro-
bust contradictory properties. So to represent a geometrical object with contradic-
tory properties (at least) one property must not be constructed robustly, but only
conceived (or projected onto the figure) by the solver. Therefore, the solver is
completely in charge of conceiving any contradiction. In this paper, we will pre-
sent three DGS cases of (attempts of) reasoning by contradiction by students that
involve solvers projected non-constructible properties onto geometrical figures.
To analyze these cases, we further elaborated Leung and Lopez-Real’s (2002)
notion of pseudo object in a dynamic geometry environment as follows: A pseu-
do object is a geometrical figure associated to another geometrical figure either
by construction or by projected-perception in such a way that it contains proper-
ties that are contradictory in the Euclidean theory.
We stress that the notion of pseudo object is solver-centered. Thus, the same
dynamic figure can be a pseudo object for one solver, but not for another, de-
pending on whether the solver has projected upon the geometrical objects contra-
dictory properties. In this sense, any dynamic figure defined through a construc-
tion has the potential of becoming a pseudo object for any given solver. In DGS,
this potentiality can be realized through a cognitive process of dragging in which
conceiving a pseudo object is critical in reasoning by contradiction. To facilitate
the analyses of this process, we introduce a notion of proto-pseudo object: A pro-
to-pseudo object is a geometrical object that has the potential of becoming a
pseudo objectsuch potential is exploited when the solver perceives a property
of such object as being contradictory with respect to another of its properties.
A. Baccaglini-Frank, S. Antonini, A. Leung, and M. A. Mariotti
PNA 7(2)
66
Thus a proto-pseudo object can become an actual pseudo object once (and if)
the solver consciously projects a property upon it that s/he is aware of as contra-
dictory. We will use the notions of pseudo object and proto-pseudo object to
show how DGSs seem to provide cognitive support in (a) offering the potential
of constructing certain properties robustly, (b) generating feedback in the form of
robustness of all properties that are consequences of the constructed ones, and (c)
the possibility of dragging parts of the dynamic figure to explore compatibility
between the robust properties and those the solver has projected upon it. As we
shall see in the following cases, these features seem to guide solvers to conceiv-
ing pseudo objects in processes of reasoning by contradiction.
THE ROLE OF DYNAMIC GEOMETRY IN THREE SOLUTION
PROCESSES
Consider the following task from Leung and Lopez-Real’s (2002) study.
Given a quadrilateral in which the sum of the pairs of opposite angles is
180°, prove that it’s cyclic.
This task was given to the participants in Leung and Lopez-Real’s study. We re-
port on Hilda and Jane’s solution.
Excerpt 1. The Case of Hilda and Jane
Hilda and Jane constructed a quadrilateral ABCD of which the vertices A, B, D
lie on the same circle with center E, while C, D, B lie on a distinct circle with
center F. Then they marked the measures of the angle in A and in C as
a
and
a-°180
, respectively, and proceeded to construct the quadrilateral BEDF (Figure
1).
If the labeling were Euclidean-correct this construction would not be possi-
ble since the circles would coincide, thus ABCD is biased and it leads to the ex-
istence of a non-degenerate quadrilateral BEDF, which Hilda and Jane conceive
as a pseudo object. This can be seen both in Jane and Hilda’s proof, and in an ex-
cerpt of the transcript of a follow-up interview the researchers had with the girls.
Reasoning by Contradiction in Dynamic Geometry
PNA 7(2)
67
Figure 1. Diagram of the proof
Statement in the proof: “From the diagram we see that it has a contradiction as
the sum of the opposite angles of the blue quadrilateral (EBFD) is 360° which is
impossible.” We present an excerpt of the interview.
7
Interviewer:
So before you did that presumably you first of all drew a circle
through three of the points and then you did the same for these three
points.
8
Hilda:
Yes.
9
Interviewer:
So then you marked these two centers. What did you say after that?
10
Hilda:
Because the angle sum of a quadrilateral is 360 and these two [refer-
ring to E and F] already add up to 360 so this is not possible.
Our analysis suggests that the quadrilateral ABCD is initially a proto-pseudo ob-
ject, and it becomes a pseudo object for the solvers once EFBD is perceived as
“not possible” (Line 10). EFBD possesses two contradictory properties which the
solvers perceive simultaneously as (a) a quadrilateral with 4 angles whose sum is
360 degrees (as all convex quadrilaterals), and (b) a quadrilateral in which the
sum of only two angles is 360 degrees statement in proof and Line 10. This
pseudo object EFBD contains the contradiction necessary for a proof by contra-
diction. The proof is completed by noticing that when EFBD is being dragged to
degenerate (disappear) the two circles, C1 and C2 in Figure 1, coincide. In other
words, the presence of the pseudo object implies the negation of the conclusion
of the statement to prove. By arriving at the proof, the solvers are aware that their
original quadrilateral ABCD also possess contradictory properties; that is, (a) its
four vertices are on different circles and (b) the sum of two opposite angles is
180°. Hence the proto-pseudo object ABCD becomes a pseudo object.
C1
C2
a
180 - a
E
A
D
B
C
F
A. Baccaglini-Frank, S. Antonini, A. Leung, and M. A. Mariotti
PNA 7(2)
68
The support offered by the DGS (in this case, Cabri) consisted in guiding the
solvers’ transition of ABCD from its status of proto-pseudo object to a genuine
pseudo object. In this case the transition occurred through the perception of a
pseudo object (EFBD) associated with ABCD. Finally, it seems quite remarkable
that Hilda and Jane decided to construct two distinct circles (Line 7) through two
sets of thee points of the original quadrilateral, showing the case in which ABCD
is cyclical in terms of coincidence of the two circles via dragging in DGS. In par-
ticular, they transform the problem, which does not contain any impossibility in
its original statement, into a problem of constructing something impossible. This
is the type of problem that Stefano and Giulio, and Tommaso and Simone were
given in Baccaglini-Frank and Mariotti (2010).
Excerpt 2. The Case of Stefano and Giulio
Similarly to what we described above, in the following cases, awareness of the
presence of a pseudo object determines the impossibility of a construction, thus
validating a statement such as “this construction is impossible.” In the following
two cases, we encounter similar solution processes to those described by Mariotti
and Antonini (2009). The solvers conceive a (or various) “new” object(s) that is
(are) used to “show” a contradiction. However, having the DGS at their disposal,
the solvers make use of it in significant ways that we will describe. The task was
as follows.
Answer the following question: Is it possible to construct a triangle with
two perpendicular angle bisectors? If so, provide steps for a construc-
tion. If not, explain why.
Giulio and Stefano immediately advance the hypothesis that the construction is
not possible, but quickly transit to constructing a figure in Cabri to try to explain
their intuition.
Stefano:
No, the only way is to have 90 degree angles… [unclear which these
may be, as Ste was not constructing the figure nor looking at the screen.]
Giulio:
That for a triangle is a bit difficult! [giggling]… So… they have to be.
Stefano:
If triangles have 4 angles…
Giulio:
No, I was about to say something silly…
Immediately Giulio starts constructing two perpendicular lines and refers to them
as the bisectors of the triangle (Figure 2).
Reasoning by Contradiction in Dynamic Geometry
PNA 7(2)
69
Figure 2. Bisectors of a triangle drawn by Giulio
5
Stefano:
Yes, these are bisectors, right?
6
Interviewer:
Yes.
7
Giulio:
So, now we need to get… bisectors… how can we have an angle
from the bisector?
8
Giulio:
the symmetric image?… It's enough to do the symmetric of this one.
So the solvers have constructed a figure with two robust angle bisec-
tors that intersect perpendicularly [Figure 3].
9
Stefano:
The only thing is that this [Figure 3] isn’t a triangle!
10
Giulio:
Therefore now we could do like this here [drawing the lines through
the symmetric points and the two drawn vertices of the triangle].
11
Interviewer:
Yes.
12
Stefano:
It’s that something atrocious comes out!
13
Giulio:
And here… theoretically the point of intersection should be .the
points… very small detail… hmmm
14
Stefano:
No, we proved that this is equal to this [pointing to angles], and this
is equal to this because they are bisectors… these two are equal so
these are parallel.
15
Stefano:
These two [referring to the two parallel lines] have a hole so it is not
a triangle.
A. Baccaglini-Frank, S. Antonini, A. Leung, and M. A. Mariotti
PNA 7(2)
70
Figure 3. Solvers’ figure
We interpret this episode as follows. The solvers use the DGS to construct two
perpendicular lines and the symmetric image to construct the property of them
being bisectors. Once the construction is completed, they discern properties that
are consequences of these two robustly constructed properties, and consequently
notice that “the figure must have two adjacent angles with two parallel sides”
(Lines 9-15). As soon as they recognize “a hole” in the triangle-to-be (Line 15)
the pseudo object exists: that is, a figure that has a “base” and two parallel sides,
and that has the property “triangle” projected onto it. The appearance of this
pseudo object reveals to the solvers the impossibility of accomplishing a correct
robust construction and thus allows them to solve the problem.
Excerpt 3. The Case of Tommaso and Simone
Tommaso and Simone proceeded by constructing a proper triangle and two of its
bisectors. Then they marked an angle formed by the bisectors and start dragging
one vertex of the triangle in the attempt to get the measure to say “90°” (Figure
4).
Figure 4. Tommaso and Simone’ construction
1
Simone:
It’s endless!
2
Simone:
91.2 [reading the measure of the angle between the bisectors.]
91.8°
Reasoning by Contradiction in Dynamic Geometry
PNA 7(2)
71
3
Simone:
Well, yes, in any case it will come out!
4
Tommaso:
How do you know? maybe…
5
Simone:
Well, of course! It's not like it can go on forever! At the end it will
make it to be 90!
6
Tommaso:
I don’t think it is possible. The solvers seem unsure about the possi-
bility of constructing such a triangle, but now seems to think it is not
possible. They start reasoning differently.
7
Simone:
Eh, it is impossible to construct it! Because… I only have these two
bisectors.
8
Interviewer:
Hmm.
9
Simone:
How can I…
10
Simone:
Since… the perpendicular bisectors… it means here there is a rhom-
bus… or a square
11
Simone:
If like here… [he draws a segment]… Here… there were… a rhom-
bus… this would be 90, 90… or a square. And therefore… then…
Eh, I mean, if this is like a rhombus, no? here there is 90 and here
there is 90, and these are the bisectors.
12
Simone:
And then… and then I bring these up [pointing to the vertical-
looking sides of the triangle] and I find their point of… of intersec-
tion.
With respect to Stefano and Giulio, here the solvers choose a different pair of
properties to construct robustly: (a) the triangle, and (b) the bisectors. They do
not construct but (we assume) project the property perpendicular bisectors onto
the figure. Nevertheless, they are not able to conceive a contradiction in it or in
the new object they conceive the rhombus. Hence this rhombus is a proto-
pseudo object, and the solvers do not seem to make the transition to conceiving it
as a pseudo object. It is significant that the solvers say “it has 4 right angles”
(Line 11) pointing to the figure that even has a marked measure of one of the an-
gles, and the measure says “91°!”. No contradiction among the properties of the
“rhombus” is perceived and the solvers are not able to reach a conclusion. We
advance the hypothesis that if they had been able to conceive the rhombus as a
pseudo object, they would have been able to solve the problem geometrically.
Instead, they resort to an algebraic explanation that they cannot coordinate with
what they see on the screen. They seem to keep on believing that the triangle al-
ways has a third vertex “somewhere up high”.
When we compare Excerpt 2 and Excerpt 3, a determining difference, from a
cognitive point of view, is that, in one case, the solvers conceive a pseudo object,
and, in the other, they do not. This can be explained by the solvers’ different
A. Baccaglini-Frank, S. Antonini, A. Leung, and M. A. Mariotti
PNA 7(2)
72
choice of the properties to construct robustly. The choice determines the type of
guidance that the DGS can provide to reasoning by contradiction. In Excerpt 3,
starting from the triangle and trying to obtain perpendicularity of the bisectors
through dragging allows the solvers to use the DGS (only) as a sort of “amplified
paper-and-pencil drawing” in that it allowed the exploration of many cases with-
out having to redraw the figure. On the other hand, in Excerpt 2 the DGS gener-
ates two robust parallel lines as a consequence of the constructed properties, thus
“guiding” the solvers in perceiving “a hole” in the triangle-to-be and thus such
object as a pseudo object.
CONCLUSION
We have introduced the concept of pseudo object and illustrated how it can con-
tribute significantly to reasoning by contradiction in Euclidean geometry. In par-
ticular, in a DGS environment, construction and dragging strategies leading to
degeneration of a pseudo object could guide to ascertainment of a geometric the-
orem or property. The hybrid nature of a pseudo object seems to be conducive to
formulating an exchange of meaning between dynamic visual reasoning in DGS
and theoretical reasoning in the Euclidean axiomatic system (in this case proof
by contradiction). We have shown that there can be a strong subjective element
in the process of producing a geometrical proof (or a convincing argument) via
the solver’s conscious choices of construction and dragging in a DGS. We hope
this paper will open up a window of discussion to view proof in dynamic geome-
try environment in ways that can enrich the formal deductive reasoning ap-
proach.
REFERENCES
Antonini, S., & Mariotti, M. A. (2007). Indirect proof: an interpreting model. In
D. Pitta-Pantazi & G. Philippou (Eds.), Proceedings of the Fifth Congress of
the European Society for Research in Mathematics Education (pp. 541-550).
Larnaca, Cyprus: University of Cyprus.
Antonini, S., & Mariotti, M. A. (2008). Indirect proof: What is specific to this
way of proving? Zentralblatt für Didaktik der Mathematik, 40(3), 401-412.
Baccaglini-Frank, A. (2010). The maintaining dragging scheme and the notion of
instrumented abduction. In P. Brosnan, D. Erchick, & L. Flevares (Eds.), Pro-
ceedings of the 10th Conference of the PME-NA (Vol. 6, pp. 607-615). Co-
lumbus, OH: The Ohio State University.
Baccaglini-Frank, A., & Mariotti, M. A. (2010). Generating conjectures through
dragging in dynamic geometry: the Maintaining Dragging Model. Interna-
tional Journal of Computers for Mathematical Learning, 15(3), 225-253.
Reasoning by Contradiction in Dynamic Geometry
PNA 7(2)
73
Healy, L. (2000). Identifying and explaining geometric relationship: interactions
with robust and soft Cabri constructions. In T. Nakahara & M. Koyama
(Eds.), Proceedings of the 24th conference of the IGPME (Vol. 1, pp. 103-
117). Hiroshima, Japan: University of Melbourne.
Leron, U. (1985). A direct approach to indirect proofs. Educational Studies in
Mathematics, 16(3), 321-325.
Leung, A., & Lopez-Real, F. (2002). Theorem justification and acquisition in
dynamic geometry: a case of proof by contradiction. International Journal of
Computers for Mathematical Learning, 7(2), 145-165.
Mariotti, M. A., & Antonini, S. (2006). Reasoning in an absurd world: difficul-
ties with proof by contradiction. In J. Novotna, H. Moraova, M. Kratka, & N.
Sthlikova (Eds.), Proceedings of the 30th PME Conference (Vol. 2, pp. 65-
72). Prague, Czech Republic: Faculty of Education, Charles University in
Prague.
Mariotti, M. A., & Antonini, S. (2009). Breakdown and reconstruction of figural
concepts in proofs by contradiction in geometry. In F. L. Lin, F. J. Hsieh, G.
Hanna, & M. de Villers (Eds.), Proof and proving in mathematics education,
ICMI Study 19 Conference Proceedings (Vol. 2, pp. 82-87). Taipei, Taiwan:
National Taiwan Normal University.
Wu Yu, J., Lin, F., & Lee, Y. (2003). Students’ understanding of proof by con-
tradiction. In N. A. Pateman, B. J. Dougherty, & J. T. Zilliox (Eds.), Proceed-
ings of the 2003 Joint Meeting of PME and PMENA (Vol. 4, pp. 443-449).
Honolulu, HI: College of Education, University of Hawaii.
This paper was originally published as Baccaglini-Frank, A., Antonini, S.,
Leung, A., & Mariotti, M. A. (2011). Reasoning by contradiction in dynamic ge-
ometry. In B. Ubuz (Ed.), Proceedings of the 35th Conference of the Internation-
al Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education (Vol. 2, pp. 81-88). An-
kara, Turkey: PME.
Anna Baccaglini-Frank
Università degli Studi di Siena
anna.baccaglini@unimore.it
Samuele Antonini
Università degli Studi di Pavia
samuele.antonini@unipv.it
Allen Leung
Hong Kong Baptist University
aylleung@hkbu.edu.hk
Maria Alessandra Mariotti
Università degli Studi di Siena
marialessandra.mariotti@gmail.com
Recibido: enero de 2012. Aceptado: abril de 2012
Handle: **
... Mariotti (2006, 2008) showed that some students are unsure of what can be accepted for the sake of argument, and even whether standard logical reasoning can be applied in such "impossible worlds". Baccaglini-Frank et al. (2013) describe students' attempts to make sense of "pseudo-objects," whose assumed properties are impossible in Euclidean geometry, when applying PBC in geometric proofs. Students' prior conceptions of logic and proof may take the form of "Greek axiomatics" (Harel & Sowder, 2007), wherein axioms are self-evident truths and logical deduction preserves truth. ...
... their own work. Table 1 lists all the graded PBC problems, and one additional ungraded homework problem (#8) that we included in our analysis because of its prior appearance in the research literature (see Baccaglini-Frank et al., 2013). Table 2 provides the other problems that will be discussed in this paper. ...
... Determine whether F is one-to-one and/or onto. (Baccaglini-Frank et al., 2013). Geometry problems are otherwise rare in our course, and this one involves an "impossible object" or pseudo-object. ...
Article
Full-text available
The literature on proof by contradiction (PBC) is nearly unanimous in claiming that this proof technique is “more difficult” for students than direct proof, and offers multiple hypotheses as to why this might be the case. To examine this claim and to evaluate some of the hypotheses, we analyzed student work on proof construction problems from homework and examinations in a university “Introduction to Proof” course taught by one of the authors. We also conducted stimulated-recall interviews with student volunteers probing their thought processes while solving these problems, and their views about PBC in general. Our results suggest that the knowledge resources students bring to bear on proof problems, and how these resources are activated, explain more of their “difficulties” than does the logical structure of the proof technique, at least for this population of students.
... The first is how new this body of research is. Speaking to its infancy as a field, Baccaglini-Frank et al. (2013) wrote that "although much research has been conducted on the themes of proof and argumentation in mathematics education, rarely do the studies focus on particular proof structures, such as proof by contradiction" (p. 63). ...
... The evidence for this hypothesis mostly comes in the form of observing how students behave when faced with impossible objects. In some settings, students skirt the affective hurdle by falling back on the imprecise nature of hand-sketching (Baccaglini-Frank et al. 2013;Mariotti and Antonini 2009). This might occur if a "triangle" in a PBC is supposed to have two right angles and the student draws a figure with two nearly right angles. ...
... In other research, students will seek out new objects to bridge the impossible and possible worlds. In some cases, this is done through a process known as "abduction" (Antonini 2019;Antonini and Mariotti 2009;Mariotti and Antonini 2009), and in other cases, through a "pseudo-object" (Baccaglini-Frank et al. 2013, 2018Leung and Lopez-Real (2002). Finally, Koichu (2012) found that "definitions and axioms of geometry can be intellectually necessitated for students by means of the exploration of impossible objects" (p. ...
Article
Full-text available
In mathematics education, the research on proof by contradiction (PBC) often claims that this activity is more difficult for students than direct proof, or simply difficult in general. Many hypotheses have been offered to support or explain this belief, yet they span a disorientingly wide swath of journal articles, conference papers, dissertations, book chapters, etc. In addition, few attempts have been made to organize these hypotheses or carefully test them. In this paper, we conduct a thorough literature review on PBC, organize existing hypotheses about challenges with PBC into a Hypothesis Framework for (Students’ Difficulty with) Proof By Contradiction (HFPBC), discuss the state of research related to each hypothesis, and offer thoughts on the future study of these hypotheses.
... In particular, we illustrate the potential of a specific type of open problem, namely tasks that require the construction of a geometrical object that cannot exist within the theory of Euclidean geometry, tasks with respect to proof by contradiction , 2017. Building on previous work (Leung and Lopez-Real 2002;Baccaglini-Frank et al. 2011), we analyse such potential through the notion of pseudoobject, Ba geometrical figure associated to another geometrical figure either by construction or by projected-perception in such a way that it contains properties that are contradictory in the Euclidean theory^ (Baccaglini-Frank et al. 2013, p. 65). We further elaborate on such a notion to illustrate better a DGE's potential to help students perceive and deal with contradictions as they engage in the exploration of a nonconstructability problem. ...
... Over the last decade, we have conducted a number of studies to investigate processes of conjecture generation, argumentation and proof, within a DGE: in particular, we have collected data in Italy and in Hong Kong on students' solution processes when working on non-constructability problems. (Results have been published in: Leung and Lopez-Real 2002;Baccaglini-Frank 2010;Baccaglini-Frank and Mariotti 2010;Baccaglini-Frank et al. 2011Leung et al. 2013;Baccaglini-Frank et al. 2017.) The research presented in this article stems from revisiting the part of this data regarding students' solution processes mobilised to solve non-constructability problems, one of which we will introduce in the next section. ...
Article
Full-text available
Proof by contradiction presents various difficulties for students relating especially to the formulation and interpretation of a negation, the managing of impossible mathematical objects, and the acceptability of the validity of the statement once a contradiction has been reached from its negation. This article discusses how a Dynamic Geometry Environment (DGE) can contribute to students’ argumentation processes when trying to explain contradictions. Four cases are presented and analysed, involving students from high school, as well as undergraduate and graduate students. The approach of the analyses makes use of a symbolic logical chain and the notion of pseudo-object. Such analyses lead to a hypothesis, that experiencing a pseudo-object during an exploration can foster DGE-supported processes of argumentation culminating in geometrical proofs by contradiction, while the lack of experience of a pseudo-object may hinder such processes. If this hypothesis is confirmed by further studies, we foresee important didactical implications since it sheds light on the transition from students’ DGE-based argumentations to proofs by contradiction. http://rdcu.be/IzTQ
... Considérons maintenant le deuxième cas, tiré également de notre étude (Baccaglini-Frank et al., 2013). La structure du problème est encore un problème ouvert de conjecture, mais le texte demande explicitement de produire une construction géométrique, ou une explication dans le cas d'une réponse négative. ...
Article
Full-text available
This contribution discusses the use of a dynamic geometry environment to promote students’ introduction to mathematical proof. Within the framework of semiotic mediation theory, I explore, on the one hand, the link between available computer tools and the personal meanings emerging from their use in classroom activities and, on the other hand, the mathematical notions that are the subject of teaching. The discussion uses three interrelated perspectives – epistemological, cognitive and didactic – to elaborate the outcomes of a number of long-term teaching experiences in secondary classrooms. Illustrative examples are presented, drawn from research studies conducted in previous years and still ongoing. Cette contribution traite de l’utilisation d’un environnement de géométrie dynamique pour favoriser l’introduction des élèves à la preuve mathématique. Dans le cadre de la théorie de la médiation sémiotique, j’explore, d’une part, le lien entre les outils informatiques disponibles et les significations personnelles émergeant de leur utilisation dans les activités en classe et, d’autre part, les notions mathématiques qui font l’objet de l’enseignement. La discussion utilise trois perspectives interdépendantes – épistémologique, cognitive et didactique – pour élaborer les résultats d’un certain nombre d’expériences d’enseignement sur le long terme dans des salles de classe du secondaire. Des exemples illustratifs sont présentés, tirés des études de recherche conduites au cours des années précédentes et toujours en cours.
... Dynamic properties increase the ability to examine mathematical concepts and relationships (e.g. Baccaglini-Frank et al., 2013;Nagle & Moore-Russo, 2013;Olive et al., 2010) and improve 'the reasoning, understanding, and conceptualization of mathematical objects' (Villa-Ochoa & Suárez-Téllez, 2021, p. 5). Dynamic behaviour presents a dilemma, as, on the one hand, it allows students to create and transform graphic representation through algebraic notation, which can otherwise be a challenging task, making algebraic manipulation and transformation more accessible to students (Hohenwarter & Jones, 2007), and, on the other hand, the outsourcing of translation between representations can be problematic. ...
Article
Full-text available
The study advances the instrumental approach to mathematics education (Drijvers et al., 2013; Trouche, 2003), aiming to elucidate the interplay between students’ reasoning competency, conceptual knowledge and tool utilisation in dynamic digital geometry and algebra environments. The dynamic properties of these environments pose a nuanced predicament, as the outsourcing of translation between visual and algebraic representations raises concerns regarding students’ conceptual development and reasoning competency. To mitigate this issue, a prediction task is proposed, focusing on the dynamic behaviour of variable points in GeoGebra. I introduce a comprehensive framework adapting Toulmin’s argumentation model into the instrumental approach, emphasising processes of justification. This is complemented by the application of components of Vergnaud’s (1998) scheme concerning generative and epistemic ways to approach how students’ conceptual knowledge has played a part in these processes. Through a case study of a student pair solving a prediction task, I explore the links between instrumented justification, students’ mathematical reasoning competency and conceptual understanding, and how students’ use of GeoGebra tools is intertwined with their justification processes. The analysis reveals the intricate interplay between data production and interpretation, and it is grounded in inference drawn regarding students’ implied theorems about concepts, dynamic behaviour and progression in terms of techniques. The results indicate that the progression of technique is driven by the experience of the inefficiency of techniques and artefacts related to the goal of justification. Essentially, the framework links students’ reasoning competency to their use of tools and conceptual knowledge, as well as demonstrates that predicting dynamic behaviour can enhance knowledge-based justification.
... This "biased quadrilateral" was named pseudoquadrilateral which is a hybrid object between the mental world and the DG Euclidean microworld. Subsequently, Baccaglini-Frank et al. (2013; extended this idea by introducing the notion of a pseudo-object: ...
Chapter
Though a goal of curriculum and pedagogical designs in the teaching and learning of geometry is to develop students’ cognitive processes of visual-spatial thinking and geometrical reasoning, there still seems to be a gap between studies focusing on technology empowering students’ spatial reasoning, and studies on technology enhancing the learning and teaching of geometry. We address this gap by building on the model of a learning progression in Geometry introduced by Battista and colleagues, situating it in the context of technology-enhanced learning, and using it to organize and present various technology-based tasks. The adaptation of the progression we present is thought to hold for various digital resources; however, to explore its potential and provide an overview of many tasks in the literature, we study the case of dynamic geometry. The tasks discussed are organized based on the didactical functionalities they have the potential of exploiting. Some tasks, to which the authors have devoted significant attention in their research, are treated in greater depth.
... The direct invariants are determined by the geometric relations defined by the commands used to construct the figure (robust constructions) and the indirect invariants result from the consequences of the construction in the context of Euclidean geometry (Mariotti, 2019). Baccaglini-Frank et al. (2013;2018) highlighted the important role of pseudo-objects in students' reasoning during the process of proof by contradiction. Specifically, they confirmed that its occurrence in a DGE is a decisive factor that influences the development of indirect argumentation and proof. ...
Conference Paper
Full-text available
This paper reports research focusing on how pseudo-objects (i.e. geometrical figures in a dynamic geometry environment containing contradictory properties) may enhance upper secondary students' learning of proof by contradiction. Under the lens of the cognitive unity of Theorems and Theory of Semiotic Mediation we explore the semiotic potential of pseudo-objects in mediating the proving process from the conjecturing phase to the final proof. We analyzed the work of three pairs of students during their engagement with non-constructability tasks favoring the occurrence of pseudo-objects. The results show that pseudo-objects contributed differently to students' argumentation and proof. This indicates the complexity of addressing the semiotic potential of pseudo-objects in students' learning of proof by contradiction.
... Geometry Visualization Software: Software has been developed to provide learners with visualizations of geometric figures or proofs. The study of Baccaglini-Frank et al. (2013) has shown positive benefits in using software to visualize geometric concepts, especially those used in proving. Geometer's Sketchpad (http://www.dynamicgeometry.com) is a commercial software that provides its user tools to draw and create geometric shapes, objects and functions. ...
Conference Paper
Geometry is a mandatory subject for secondary school students, where they learn geometric figures and their properties, and the axioms, postulates and theorems involving them. A key topic in Geometry class is proving, where learners are required to derive and prove a certain property is true based from the given properties and by using various axioms, postulates and theorems. This is where most learners encounter difficulty. In this paper, we describe Geometry Proof Tutor, a learning environment where learners can practice Geometry proving through multiple representations-two-column proof and proof tree. With the use of a knowledge base to model Geometry concepts, the software validates the learner's proof statements and provides corrective feedback accordingly. Test results showed that the learners found the availability of the proof tree to be useful in tracking their progress. The presence of complete reasons to use for proofs also helped them understand Geometric Proving better. However, the long list of available choices and the one-proof-statement-at-a-time user interface design made it difficult for them to encode their answers.
... The first case was reported in Baccaglini-Frank, Antonini, Leung, &Mariotti (2013). The task, given to high school students in Italy, was as follows: Is it possible to construct a triangle with two perpendicular internal angle bisectors? ...
Conference Paper
Abductive inferences, which are the only types of inference that produce new ideas, are important in mathematical problem solving. Such inferences, according to Peirce, arise from surprising or unexpected situations. Therefore, one way to improve student problem solving may be to provide them with environments that are designed to evoke surprise. In this paper, we examine the potential of dynamic geometry environments (DGEs)to foster surprise. We conjecture that the ease with which students can explore configurations, along with the immediate feedback, may lead them to encounter surprising situations. We analyse three different examples of student problem solving featuring surprised-provoked abduction, and identify the specific role that the DGE played.
Chapter
This chapter discusses the use of a Dynamic Geometry Environment for fostering students’ introduction to mathematical proof. Grounded in the theory of semiotic mediation, it explores, on the one hand, the link between computational tools and the personal meanings emerging from their use in classroom activities and, on the other hand, the mathematical notions that are the object of instruction. The discussion uses three interrelated perspectives—the epistemological, the cognitive, and the didactic—to elaborate on findings from a number of longstanding teaching experiments in secondary school classrooms. Some illustrative examples are presented, drawn from research studies carried out in previous years and still in progress.
Article
Full-text available
Two hundreds and two students of 17~20 years old were surveyed on their understanding of proof by contradiction. Five abilities were identified for interpreting their understanding. A two-streamed model of understanding proof by contradiction was constructed statistically. To analyze the negating of a statement with quantifier 'only have one', interviews were conducted to reveal the relationship among the language used, Chinese or English, in their thinking process and their logical judgment.
Article
Full-text available
Theorem acquisition and deductive proof have always been core elements in the study and teaching of Euclidean geometry. The introduction of dynamic geometry environments,DGE (e.g., Cabri-Géomètre, Geometer's Sketchpad), into classrooms in the past decade has posed a challenge to this praxis. Student scan experiment through different dragging modalities on geometrical objects that they construct, and consequently infer properties(generalities, theorems) about the geometrical artefacts. Because of the inductive nature of the DGE, the experimental-theoretical gap that exists in the acquisition and justification of geometrical knowledge becomes an important pedagogical and epistemological concern. In this paper, we will describe and study a ‘Cabri proof by contradiction’ of a theorem on cyclic quadrilaterals given by a pair of 16 year-old students in a Hong Kong secondary school. We will discuss how their construction motivates a visual-cognitive scheme on `seeing' proof in DGE, and how this scheme could fit into the theoretical construct of cognitive unity of theorems proposed by Boero, Garuti and Mariotti(1996). The issue of a cognitive duality and its relation to visualization will be raised and discussed. Finally, we propose a possible perspective to bridge the experimental-theoretical gap in DGE by introducing the idea of a dynamic template as a visualizer to geometrical theorem justification and acquisition.
Article
Full-text available
Research has shown that the tools provided by dynamic geometry systems (DGSs) impact students’ approach to investigating open problems in Euclidean geometry. We particularly focus on cognitive processes that might be induced by certain ways of dragging in Cabri. Building on the work of Arzarello, Olivero and other researchers, we have conceived a model describing some cognitive processes that can occur during the production of conjectures in dynamic geometry and that seem to be related to the use of specific dragging modalities. While describing such cognitive processes, our model introduces key elements and describes how these are developed during the exploratory phase and how they evolve into the basic components of the statement of the conjecture (premise, conclusion, and conditional link between them). In this paper we present our model and use it to analyze students’ explorations of open problems. The description of the model and the data presented are part of a more general qualitative study aimed at investigating cognitive processes during conjecture-generation in a DGS, in relation to specific dragging modalities. During the study the participants were introduced to certain ways of dragging and then interviewed while working on open problem activities. KeywordsConjecturing–Dragging schemes–Dynamic geometry–Invariant–Instrumented argument–Maintaining dragging–Path
Article
The study presented in this paper is part of a wide research project concerning indirect proofs. Starting from the notion of mathematical theorem as the unity of a statement, a proof and a theory, a structural analysis of indirect proofs has been carried out. Such analysis leads to the production of a model to be used in the observation, analysis and interpretation of cognitive and didactical issues related to indirect proofs and indirect argumentations. Through the analysis of exemplar protocols, the paper discusses cognitive processes, outlining cognitive and didactical aspects of students’ difficulties with this way of proving.
Breakdown and reconstruction of figural concepts in proofs by contradiction in geometry
  • M A Mariotti
  • S Antonini
Mariotti, M. A., & Antonini, S. (2009). Breakdown and reconstruction of figural concepts in proofs by contradiction in geometry. In F. L. Lin, F. J. Hsieh, G. Hanna, & M. de Villers (Eds.), Proof and proving in mathematics education, ICMI Study 19 Conference Proceedings (Vol. 2, pp. 82-87). Taipei, Taiwan: National Taiwan Normal University.
Indirect proof: an interpreting model
  • S Antonini
  • M A Mariotti
Antonini, S., & Mariotti, M. A. (2007). Indirect proof: an interpreting model. In D. Pitta-Pantazi & G. Philippou (Eds.), Proceedings of the Fifth Congress of the European Society for Research in Mathematics Education (pp. 541-550). Larnaca, Cyprus: University of Cyprus.
Reasoning in an absurd world: difficulties with proof by contradiction
  • M A Mariotti
  • S Antonini
Mariotti, M. A., & Antonini, S. (2006). Reasoning in an absurd world: difficulties with proof by contradiction. In J. Novotna, H. Moraova, M. Kratka, & N. Sthlikova (Eds.), Proceedings of the 30th PME Conference (Vol. 2, pp. 6572). Prague, Czech Republic: Faculty of Education, Charles University in Prague.
Identifying and explaining geometric relationship: interactions with robust and soft Cabri constructions
  • L Healy
Healy, L. (2000). Identifying and explaining geometric relationship: interactions with robust and soft Cabri constructions. In T. Nakahara & M. Koyama (Eds.), Proceedings of the 24th conference of the IGPME (Vol. 1, pp. 103117). Hiroshima, Japan: University of Melbourne.