ArticlePDF Available

Redefining the child’s right to identity

Authors:

Abstract

This article proposes redefining the child's right to identity as a right to state protection of ties meaningful to the child. Its main arguments are, in essence: (1) Such a right should protect the development of an authentic individual by seeking the child's wishes and feelings concerning their ties. (2) Protection of an individualized identity necessitates exploration of culture as a context of personal meaning which cannot be equated with cultural sensitivity as commonly perceived. (3) Consequently, preferential protection of the child's ties to a minority culture or to individuals affiliated to it is seen as violating the proposed right. (4) The UN Convention on the Rights of the Child reaffirms commitment to a dynamic child-constructed identity. (5) Protection of the proposed right reflects, protects and creates a social reality in which children's lives may be imbued with personal meaning. A discussion of two English cases demonstrates these arguments.
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0028-2 2 - 147 Rev: 01-04-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 08:53 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: JG
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 18, (2004), 147–177
International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family, Vol. 18, No. 2,
Oxford University Press, 2004; all rights reserved
* School of Social Work and Faculty of Law, Bar Ilan University, Israel. An earlier version of this
article was initially presented as part of the Research Seminar Series of the Family Studies Research
Centre at Cardiff University on 27 February 2002. The research for it began while the author was a
Research Fellow at Queen Mary College, University of London. I am very grateful to Professor
Gillian Douglas, Mr John Eekelaar, Professor Michael Freeman, Professor Nigel Lowe, Professor
Mervyn Murch, Dr Rhona Shuz, and an anonymous reviewer for their helpful comments to earlier
versions of this article. I also thank Professor Smadar Lavie for referring me to Bruch (2001).
REDEFINING THE CHILD’S RIGHT TO
IDENTITY
YA’IR RONEN*
ABSTRACT
This article proposes redefining the child’s right to identity as a right to state
protection of ties meaningful to the child. Its main arguments are, in essence:
(1) Such a right should protect the development of an authentic individual by
seeking the child’s wishes and feelings concerning their ties. (2) Protection of
an individualized identity necessitates exploration of culture as a context of
personal meaning which cannot be equated with cultural sensitivity as
commonly perceived. (3) Consequently, preferential protection of the child’s
ties to a minority culture or to individuals affiliated to it is seen as violating the
proposed right. (4) The UN Convention on the Rights of the Child reaffirms
commitment to a dynamic child-constructed identity. (5) Protection of the
proposed right reflects, protects and creates a social reality in which children’s
lives may be imbued with personal meaning. A discussion of two English cases
demonstrates these arguments.
1. INTRODUCTION
This article maintains that the state should have a positive duty to
safeguard the child’s right to identity as a right to protection of ties
meaningful to the child .1It suggests that these ties delineate the child’s
identity. These are primarily ties to the human world, but they can also
be ties to an animal, such as a dog or a horse, to an inanimate object,
such as a book or a tree, or to a geographic place such as a village or a
physical home.
It begins with an exposition of the main arguments and focus. This
introduction is followed by a discussion of authenticity, of the child’s
legally neglected need for a meaningful existence and of culture as a
context of personal meaning. This discussion forms the rationale for the
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0029-1 2 - 148 Rev: 01-04-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 08:51 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: JG
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
148
proposed definition of the right to identity. A critical discussion of the
right to identity in international law follows, clarifying and exemplifying
the need to redefine the right in positive law. There then follows the
essence of the stories of two children as told by the Lord Justices of the
English Court of Appeal in two cases which exemplify some of the
dilemmas related to identity that are discussed in the article. An analysis
of the two court cases presented follows and ends with a concluding
note exploring the key implications of the proposed redefinition of the
right.
The main arguments of this article are:
1. The child’s right to identity derivative of their human dignity
should protect the development of an authentic self-actualizing individ-
ual which maintains psychological ties, primarily ties of interdepen-
dence to significant others. The state should protect a right to an
individualized identity by seeking the child’s wishes and feelings
concerning their ties. In this way, a structured element of caution is
introduced into child law policy and practice.
2. Protection of an individualized identity necessitates exploration of
culture as a context of personal meaning and is founded on empathic
understanding of an individual child’s experience. Such respect cannot
be equated with what is commonly perceived as cultural sensitivity.
3. Consequently, preferential protection of the child’s ties to a
minority culture or to individuals affiliated to that culture is seen as
violating the right to identity. Such preferential protection signifying a
politicized selectivity of compassion is an inappropriate tool to correct
or counteract prejudices against such a minority culture.
4. Neither the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child (UNCRC)
nor the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and
Fundamental Freedoms (ECPHRFF) explicitly uphold the right to
identity as defined here. The child’s right to guidance formulated in
Article 5 of the UNCRC and their right to free expression and right to
participation formulated respectively in Articles 12 and 13 to the
UNCRC, as interrelated, implicitly reaffirm the commitment of inter-
national law to a dynamic child-constructed identity.
5. Legal protection of the proposed right not only reflects and
protects a social reality in which children’s lives may be imbued with
personal meaning. It also creates such a reality through law’s trans-
formative educational impact.
The focus of this discussion is not any national law but rather
international instruments, primarily the UNCRC. Though not incor-
porated into statute law in most jurisdictions (including England), the
UNCRC is the most authoritative legal text on children in international
law (Van Bueren, 1995:1–25). English Courts, like many other domestic
courts worldwide, have recognized that domestic administrative and
legal procedures absorb the UNCRC’s expectations (Rosenblatt, 2003)
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0030-1 2 - 149 Rev: 01-04-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 08:51 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: JG
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
149
and therefore its minimalist and sometimes implicit references to
identity are seen as deserving primary attention. The ECPHRFF, clearly
bearing on the two cases discussed here, is also discussed.
Following cultural anthropologist Clifford Geertz (1983: 218), posi-
tive law, such as these two Conventions and case law, which should be
guided by their imperatives, is seen here not only as reflecting social
norms but also as constructing them through the articulation and
enforcement of legal norms. Thus, law may influence both individual
and community identity (Lukinsky, 1987; Post, 1995) through its
transformation of local cultures (An-Na’im, 1994). Therefore, law is
seen as a tool for the promotion of social change despite the fact that
cultural values influence its implementation (Alston, 1994: 23) and
irrespective of the fact that lawmakers sometimes deny its social impact.
2. THE RATIONALE FOR REDEFINING THE RIGHT TO IDENTITY
A. Facilitating the Development of an Authentic Self-actualizing Individual
Increasingly, the child is seen as a human being worthy of the protection
of a human rights regime not only by international law but also by
societies at large (eg Van Bueren, 1995: 6). Children are now often
portrayed both in legal and in social science discourse as having a
potential for self-actualization or self-realization (eg Rogers, 1989;
Eekelaar, 1994: 49). Such a potential may be seen as enshrined within
the concept of human dignity and justifying the attribution of human
rights (eg Taylor, 1994: 41–2; Rockefeller, 1994: 87; Erbele, 2002: 256).
However, current legal protection of the child’s right to human
dignity does not guarantee protection of an individualized identity.
Taylor (1991: 32–5) explains that the notion of individualized identity
draws support from an ideal of authenticity, in the sense of being true to
oneself and to one’s particular way of being. It implies that if you are not
true to yourself you miss what being human means for yourself.
The understanding of identity proposed here departs from the
classical substantive, essentialist, conception of identity which empha-
sizes static, unchanging elements of identity (Taylor, 1991; Taylor, 1994;
Lavie and Swedenberg, 1996:11). Identity should not be seen as
developing in a vacuum, but rather always through dialogue and
sometimes struggles with significant others – those persons who matter
to the individual constructing their identity (Taylor, 1994; Eekelaar,
1994: 51; Wilson, 1997: 281; Eekelaar, 2004). Even as the individual
outgrows some of these others, the internal dialogue with them
continues throughout life and a contribution to the formation of an
evolving identity in early childhood continues indefinitely (eg Taylor,
1994). Taylor (1994) writes of two spheres of recognition of identity.
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0031-2 2 - 150 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:08 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
150
First, the intimate sphere of recognizing an identity that is formed in
dialogue and struggle with significant others, and second, a public
sphere where a politics of recognition may protect the individual’s
identity. In adopting such a conception of identity, it is not difficult to
accept the assertion of Lavie, Swedenberg and their colleagues that
there is no objective immutable link between identity and a specific
place such as, say, a place of birth (Lavie and Swedenburg, 1996: esp. 1,
2). An assumption of such a link is inherent in an abstract, decontexual-
ized, understanding of identity rejected here.
Alongside the child’s need ‘to become’, to develop and change, to
fulfil dreams and plans, the need, in An-Na’im’s words, ‘to be different
from others’ (2002: 1–2) there is another need. This is often neglected
by advocates of children’s rights, though it is well embedded in social
science literature. This is the child’s need ‘to be’, to be his/her
authentic self and to be recognized as ‘somebody’ when simply being
that self (Feuerstein, 1982: 44–5; Feuerstein, 1984; Engel and Munger,
1996: esp. 48; Bilsky, 1997: 148–9; Deng, 2002:196). This ensures the
child’s psychological survival.
A children’s rights regime should ideally be responsive to the
complementing needs ‘to be’ and the need ‘to become’. The granting
of a right to autonomy, responding to the child’s need ‘to become’ and
overcoming adult paternalism, is often perceived as the most advanced
and most problematic stage in the evolution of child law (eg Franklin,
1986: 27–38; Van Bueren, 1995: 15). A child who has not been
empowered to develop a unique personal identity may see themselves
simply in terms of their biological needs. Such a child may become
indifferent to their human rights or misuse them in a reductionist way to
satisfy only momentary desires and impulses (Feuerstein, 1982: 44–5)
totally divorced from their noble purposes as envisioned and described
in human rights theory and in case law (eg Cohn, 1991: 19–21; Eekelaar,
1994: 51).
Through an evolutionary process of choice between different identifi-
cations and values, the child constantly creates and recreates their own
identity until, hopefully, it crystallizes in adulthood (Van Praagh, 1997:
366; Van Praagh and Wilson, 1997: 282; Van Praagh, 1999b: 1348).
Classical portrayals of such evolutionary processes of changing identifi-
cations are found in the lives of Nelson Mandela and Mahatma Gandhi
(Erikson, 1970; Mandela, 1994; Gandhi, 2001). Both individuals
reached the stage of courageous commitment to a cultural identity
despised and belittled by mainstream society only through lengthy
processes of personal growth in their personal alliances and identifi-
cations. Both rejected sectarian conceptions of their identity often
imposed or suggested by social and legal norms. Both allowed them-
selves to be themselves despite pressures to conform and to adopt a
conventional identity.
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0032-1 2 - 151 Rev: 01-04-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 08:51 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: JG
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
151
B. Does Legal Recognition of an Individualized Identity Imply a Traditional
Liberal Individualist Ethos?
A politics of equal dignity leads to the recognition of the individual’s
eligibility to a uniform set of rights and immunities. This article
proposes that a politics of difference or identity is needed which would
call for the recognition of a human being’s unique individualized
identity, and which sees the suppression of individual distinctness by a
dominant or majority identity as the cardinal sin against authenticity, to
use Taylor’s (1994: 38) words. In her seminal essay, Carol Gilligan
(1982) can be understood as developing this charge in relation to
silencing a distinct, caring voice, which has been derogatorily con-
structed as a feminine voice by mainstream academic and popular
discourse. I argue, using Taylor’s wording again, that Gilligan can be
understood as showing how mainstream discourse presenting an
atomistic image of the ideal human being, ‘sins’ against both boys and
girls. Such a model of humanness, often underlying public and legal
discourse, denies or ignores a central psychological insight: human
beings are naturally interdependent rather than independent (Gilli-
gan, 1982: 2, 4, 74; Cohn, 1991: 19, 21; Freeman, 1997: 73;). Minow (eg
1986: esp. 15, 17–18, 24) utilizes this insight in articulating a theory of
children’s rights, departing from a traditional ethos of liberal individu-
alism in which she emphasizes the centrality of the child’s right to the
protection of their relationships with significant others founded on an
ethos of interdependence. Universal protection of relationships with
significant others is in fact protection of the distinctness and the
uniqueness in the individual. In this context, the universal and the
particular converge.
Protecting the child’s definition of their identity, ie protecting a
child-constructed identity, may be construed as derivative of a commit-
ment to their human dignity (Taylor, 1994; Raz, 1998: 200) despite the
fact that human dignity politics has not yet been utilized for this
purpose: As Taylor (1994: 39) explains this is an instance of a shift
‘where a new understanding of the human social condition imparts a
radically new meaning to an old principle’. To conclude, legal
recognition of an individualized identity does not imply endorsement of
a traditional liberal individualist ethos, as one might initially assume. It
is founded on an alternative ethos of interdependence.2
C. Is Public Recognition of the Child’s Individualized Identity Necessary in the
Children’s Rights Era?
Society often tends to see the child as property of the state or parents, to
be moulded in another’s image (eg Slaughter, 2000). Our recognition
of the child as an individual, whose authentic identity is worthy of
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0033-2 2 - 152 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:09 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
152
respect, is meant to reaffirm our commitment to their unique human-
ness and counteracts such a tendency. One may doubt whether such
commitment needs reaffirmation in an era in which – from the
perspective of international law – children are seen as eligible for
human rights. However, it is suggested here that law is only gradually
moving away from serving those in positions of political and economic
power as opposed to others, such as children and ethnic minorities, to
universally safeguarding humane treatment and human rights for all
(Nandy, 1990: 32–3; Minow, 1990a: 7–10, 297). Historically, one can
observe a sad human propensity to allow exclusion, stigmatization and
even victimization of the other and then to deny, rationalize, repress or
disassociate the painful experiences of the other (Nandy, 1990: 32–3;
Minow, 1990a: 4, 5–7; Minow, 1990b: 1673–4, 1684; Herman, 1992:1–4).
Society continues to withhold eligibility for rights and protection for
self-actualization from those it sees as deviant, morally impaired or
simply less than fully human. Communities, families and adults
meaningful to the child may be seen in this way and therefore the child’s
ties to them are liable to be disregarded. Furthermore, though children
are seen by international law as bearers of rights, in practice, they are
very vulnerable and their participation in the determination of their
futures through rights discourse is typically partial and unrelated to
their actual competencies (Minow, 1990a: 285, 303–4). Tendencies to
see the child as not fully human and as property of the state or parents to
be moulded in another’s image may be subtle, implicit, and even
preconscious. Oppression, stigmatization, and social exclusion are
seldom purposeful acts (Minow, 1990a: 62–5). Thus, children affiliated
to minorities are in special jeopardy of social exclusion and silencing.
Admittedly, our moral commitment towards the child has grown
since the Second World War through the assimilation of human rights
norms into mainstream democratic culture (Alston, 1994; Van Bueren,
1995: 1–25); this has also served to improve the general level of
tolerance to difference guaranteed by law. However, tolerance as
understood in liberal theory does not necessarily entail a commitment
to viewing different cultures, which children perceive as their own, as
fundamentally equal in worth to mainstream culture: Not all that is
tolerable is seen as of equal worth to ours (Raz, 1998: 204–5). Such a
commitment, which may be seen as a commitment to multiculturalism
(Raz, 1998) encourages us to see children as of equal worth despite their
different cultural identities and because of their common humanity. It
necessitates strengthening our capacity to identify and combat biases
against the other embedded in our upbringing and in professional
training (Minow, 1990b; Schon, 1991) and to publicly expose and
overcome them. It is contended here that one such potential bias is the
bias against culture as a context of personal meaning to the child.
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0034-1 2 - 153 Rev: 01-04-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 08:51 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: JG
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
153
A traditional ethos of liberal individualism commits us to avoid
silencing minority opinion simply because it may be detrimental to the
public good. In the same vein, when we protect a child’s ties with both
their social family and their community in as much as they relate to
them with a sense of belonging, we may have to compromise the
protection of conformity to values that mainstream or minority
communities see as worthy. This is because the families and communi-
ties of such children may not conform to socially accepted values.
Failing to respect difference in this arena may be seen as effectively
treating children as objects and as inconsistent with regarding them as
rights holders (see by inference Eekelaar, 1994: 51). For example, a
child’s family may promote middle class ‘bourgeois’ values in a socialist
or Marxist society; it may promote pacifism or universalism in a patriotic
or militaristic society. Similarly, it may advocate moral superiority of
religious law or community law over state law.
It is suggested that, if our aim is to ensure that individual children are
not, in effect, silenced, we must positively protect those elements that
contribute to the moulding of an authentic self. It is not enough for law
to ensure that a child is able to express preferences freely and that they
are taken into account as Article 12 mandates (Eekelaar, 1994: 60, note
10). Law must positively ensure that the child’s wishes and feelings are
sought. Only if the law encourages the child’s participation in defining
who they are, can the child develop into an adult capable of expressing
themselves authentically. A commitment by the state to an ideal of
authenticity would introduce a structured element of caution into state
intervention in the field of child law. The benefits of such intervention
can be more lucidly balanced with its drawbacks made apparent
through recognition of an individualized identity.
It is argued here that child law should challenge both mainstream and
minority cultures to transform themselves by shouldering a commit-
ment to the ideal of authenticity in relation to child rearing. This does
not envision an abrupt, violent process of transformation, but rather an
evolutionary one. Thus, for example the connotation of belonging may
gradually change: As stated earlier, children are often perceived as
belonging to their parents. Nevertheless, it is not suggested that we
abandon the term ‘belonging’. Rather, one can hope for the transform-
ation of both the legal and common usage of the word belonging. Law’s
focus on protecting the child’s sense of belonging may gradually modify
social norms towards a greater commitment to the development of an
authentic self.
To summarize: it is argued here that, despite wide de jure recognition
of the child’s eligibility to human rights, the legal recognition of an
individualized identity is necessary to reaffirm society’s commitment to
the child as a human being in their own right.
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0035-2 2 - 154 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:09 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
154
D. How Can Law Protect Not Only the Child’s Right ‘To Become’ but also
Their Right ‘To Be’?
I have introduced the child’s needs ‘to be’ and ‘to become’. The
question remains how both can be practically protected. Self-definition
can never take place in a vacuum. A child knows who they are only within
a specific familial and community context (Wilson, 1997:281), however
dull at times. Besides being cared for, a child needs a familial and
communal environment, which they feel is theirs and which affords
them a clear understanding of who they are and helps to give meaning
to their life (Hassall, 1994). The child’s family and community are their
starting points in life. Ideally, these are their family of origin and
community of origin. From within a family and a community a child
naturally begins to create meaningful ties and develop an identity that
evolves over time. Their experiences are gradually applied to new and
widening fields beyond their family and community of origin as they
mature biologically and emotionally.
The legal definition of family, however well informed by social
science literature, is ultimately a cultural construction. Nevertheless,
legal rhetoric sometimes erroneously gives us the impression that such a
legal definition captures some eternal truths (Minow, 1987: 959–60).
Thus, neither ‘blood ties’ nor ‘legal ties’ of parenthood necessarily
signify psychological ties with a child, and in order to discover who fills
the role of mother or father for the child, it is essential that recourse be
made to the child’s subjective perceptions. In practical terms, protect-
ing the child’s right ‘to be’ primarily means ensuring that they will not
be forced to disown their authentic familial and communal identity, to
the detriment of their sense of self and of their human dignity in order
to gain recognition of their normalcy by mainstream society (Hassall,
1994: 2–3; Bilsky, 1997: 144–5).
An example of the need for such protection arises in cases of
adoption. ‘Closed’ adoption, breaking all ties with biological kin, was
regarded in the not too distant past as the ideal way to guarantee secure
and uninterrupted parenting and family life. Nowadays, the child’s loss
of earlier relationships along with all traces of their pre-adoption
identity is widely recognized as potentially damaging to some children
and a movement to greater openness in adoption is drawing growing
support (eg Eekelaar, 1994: 48; Hoelgaard, 1998: 232).
A helpful illustration of the unmet need ‘to be’ comes from recently
conducted research into the long-term experiences of adopted adults
(Howe and Feast, 2000). The research shows that having a name or
maintaining stable ties with one’s psychological parents, guaranteed
under the UNCRC, is not enough. Adopted adults who were not seeking
substitute psychological parents still wanted to meet their birth parents
(Feast, 2000). Many reported that in this way they satisfied important
concerns about their personal identity and filled a void that they felt
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0036-2 2 - 155 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:09 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
155
(Feast, 2000: 387). It is suggested that such searches express the adults’
unmet need ‘to be’ in childhood and adolescence.
Feeling protected in being who they are, a child can then allow
themselves to ‘recreate’ themselves in fantasy and in real life: to dream
their own dreams, wish their own wishes and even implement their own
plans, however small-scale they may be, at first. Through interdepen-
dent relationships with their environment they grow to be increasingly
autonomous yet, as explained above, never fully independent (Gilligan,
1982: 74; Minow, 1990a: 301–3; Freeman, 1997: 73).
The strength and significance of children’s ties to a family and
community they define as theirs can vary. Some children are alienated
from both their extended and nuclear families. These children often
develop unique relationships, which may seem peculiar to the
untrained eye. These may be ties to carers, teachers or therapists. These
ties give us the opportunity to question the validity of rigid conventional
boundaries defining who is considered as family and what is considered
professional behaviour. They prod us to challenge the above-men-
tioned assumption that the legal definition of family captures some
eternal truths. It is only possible to understand these relationships in
light of the problematics of the children’s upbringing and develop-
ment. Atypical responses to abnormal circumstances are often the wisest
and most creative. Thus, the law should respond cautiously to these
relationships and avoid attempts to rigidly dictate that only precon-
ceived relationships serve the child’s best interests.
The definition of the right to identity should enable the decision-
maker to understand that the little the child sees as their identity,
should, in principle, be protected. This understanding of the child’s
circumstances will enable the decision to ensure that not only does the
child maintain existing ties, but also that they can develop new ones
arising from their personal world. The experience gained through
approximately a century of state intervention in the name of the Welfare
Principle teaches a lesson of caution. Fantasies of saving children may
turn out to be painful for the children involved if they are not heard and
understood as human beings possessing a unique identity. Ties to
imperfect blameworthy carers were too often neglected (Kufeldt, 1993:
9–10; Hassall, 1994: 9–10; Van Praagh, 1999a: 156; Van Praagh, 1999b:
1348). The imposition of well-intentioned adult-minded plans brought
about the result that children sometimes grow up to become alienated
adults incapable of relationships of trust and care (eg Kufeldt, 1993).
If professionals and jurists listen attentively to children and under-
stand what they consider meaningful in their personal world, children
may succeed in challenging their exclusion and may thus grow up to
trust future representatives of normative society and to identify with its
norms (Minow, 1990a: 297–9). Respecting the child’s sense of belong-
ing may promote identification with society (Raz, 1998: 203–4).
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0037-2 2 - 156 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:10 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
156
Clearly, though the overall outcome of this approach would be
greater legal protection to the child’s ties to their family and community
of origin, in certain cases law may protect significant ties a child has
developed to a family and community which they were not born into,
thus overriding the interests of biological parents and minority
communities.
A classical example of such cases would be a situation in which foster
parents who took into their home a neglected child through child
protection proceedings are allowed to adopt that child despite rehabili-
tation of the biological parents. These biological parents may have had a
history of drug abuse, criminality and homelessness. Their rehabili-
tation in such a case is undoubtedly morally admirable. Nevertheless,
the parents’ objections to the adoption may be outweighed by a child’s
clear cut wishes and feelings if the child is accorded a right to an
individualized identity and law becomes responsive to their sense of
belonging.
The new meaning of the right to identity proposed here offers the
child state intervention that is not systematically available at present. It
seeks to ensure that, by protecting ties that they hold valuable, children
see themselves as neither the property of their parents nor of any other
person or organ, such as a state welfare agency.
However, the legal system lacks the tools to fully safeguard the child’s
sense of belonging in each and every case. Law cannot accommodate all
human sensitivities and is inevitably based on no more that an
approximation of what the child experiences (eg Eekelaar, 1994: 46–7).
This notwithstanding, the proposed definition of a child’s right to
identity offers reinforcement for the safeguards protecting the child’s
human dignity. It rejects the notion of a ‘normal’ identity, which it does
not replace with the endorsement of ethnocentrism, connoting the
position that only black or white or brown is beautiful, a position
regrettably associated with identity politics (Minow, 1996). Rejecting
ethnocentrism while respecting the relevance of ethnicity in the
construction and reconstruction of an individualized identity may
minimize the exploitation of identity politics to promote community
interests at the individual’s expense (Alston and Gilmour-Walsh, 1996:
39; Deng, 2002:188–9). Indeed, for every ‘we’ there is ‘them’. We are
habituated to boundaries between friends and strangers and without
these and other boundaries it is questionable whether we would have an
identity (Sacks, 2002: 46). But the boundaries do not have to be static.
We may, as individuals and as a society, see these boundaries as an
invitation to continually expand our awareness of inequity to the other
and to overcome a sense of threat when encountering difference.
Identity and a sense of belonging do not have to exclude any specific
unchangeable other from eligibility to rights (Nandy, 1990: 32, Sacks,
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0038-1 2 - 157 Rev: 01-04-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 08:51 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: JG
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
157
2002: 46–66). If we see otherness as an invitation to care for the other
and thus respect their human rights, for example through the
universally recognized Golden Rule (eg An-Na’im, 1994: 68; Cohn,
1991: 42), we become less alienated from them (Erikson, 1963). Identity
– ‘mine’ and ‘his’, ‘ours’ and ‘theirs’ – can be dynamic and can become
more inclusive. Ethnic distinctions may thus lose their significance as
rigid personal boundaries that define identity (eg Eekelaar, 2004).
The child’s right to identity, informed by an understanding of
authenticity, offers to exchange the imagery of universal uniformity
with an imagery of difference and uniqueness in the way children relate
to their personal worlds (Minow, 1996; Van Praagh, 1999a: 203). A right
to a cultural identity, relying on the child’s definition of who they are,
assumes the dialectic of change described above (Cooper et al, 1995:
136–9; Van Praagh, 1997: 366; Van Praagh, 1999b: 1348). What the child
defines presently as their identity may change in the future, as it
continues to evolve. The state’s commitment to upholding the child’s
human dignity, a commitment to their identity as a person developing
towards autonomous adulthood, should ‘accompany’ the child in their
personal journey. A possible derivative of the evolution in the child’s
identity is a change in commitment to different cultures including
minority cultures.
To conclude, under ideal conditions, a child’s nuclear and extended
family, their culture, language and nationality are their ‘birth right’
(Hassall, 1994), which they enjoy without any intervention from the law.
Thus their need ‘to be’ more than their need ‘to become’ is naturally
protected. Family law should aspire to draw children’s lives closer to the
ideal, while recognizing its inherent incapacity, ever fully to achieve this
aim. Having said that, the legal protection of the right to identity as
outlined here, does have the capacity to safeguard a critical factor
relating to the child’s well being, namely personal ties that are
significant to them.
E. Culture as a Context of Personal Meaning: Beyond Cultural Sensitivity
Which culture should a child be allowed to enjoy (for example
according to Article 30 of the UNCRC)? which is their culture, say in the
case of a child with multiple minority affiliations; biological parents
from one minority, foster-parents with whom he/she lived from age two
to six or adoptive parents? Is it the biological family’s minority culture,
ie, the culture into which the child was born, or is it the minority culture
of the foster family, which raised him/her from ages two to eight?
Perhaps, it is the minority culture of the adoptive family from which
he/she is separated when he/she leaves for boarding school? Perhaps
the peer culture at the boarding school?
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0039-2 2 - 158 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:10 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
158
The conception suggested here is that from a child-centred perspec-
tive, the culture that the child should be allowed to enjoy, whether
mainstream or minority, is not an abstract derivative of the decision-
maker’s theoretical knowledge. From the perspective of the individual
child, it is irrelevant how the tenets and lifestyle of Orthodox Judaism or
Shiite Islam are described in any textbook. The child’s lived experience
may be very different from those descriptions. The child’s culture as
uniquely experienced by the individual child is defined here as a set of
related meanings by which the child interprets the reality of their life
and its unique circumstances (eg Kline, 1992). This uniqueness is a
universal human condition: that as he/she grows, each child develops a
unique cultural identity which brings into focus the commonality of
children’s experience of identity formation rather than the ‘otherness’
of the child’s unique excluded culture or experience (Minow, 1999:
24).
Although it is important to understand the different stages of
childhood development and children’s psychological needs derivative
of them, such understanding is, in itself, not enough to enable society to
respond to children’s needs. It may even serve to disempower the child
(eg Eekelaar, 1994). Such understanding reflects only an approxi-
mation of the child’s experience. Already from the first months of their
lives, children have both the capacity and interest in giving meaning to
events, although admittedly they are often immature decision-makers.
We are therefore called upon to explore the relationship between the
meaning the child gives to events in their life which influence their
preferences and the legal decisions pertaining to those preferences. It is
not suggested that the right to identity should guarantee the child a
power of veto in decisions pertaining to them. However, ignoring the
meanings the child gives to their personal world by imposing different
meanings regarding what is good and valuable for the child, and by not
offering protection for culture as a construct of the child, can be
detrimental to the child’s quality of life. Not only can this reduce the
efficacy of our efforts on the child’s behalf, but it can also cause them to
experience life generally as duller and society as alienating (see also
Eekelaar, 1994: 54).
The present proposal has not been advocated in the traditional
manner by recourse to a commitment to cultural sensitivity. Further-
more, in light of the above discussion it is not difficult for us to accept
the assertion that in conceptualizing culture as unchanging and
timeless, one may in the name of cultural sensitivity re-incarcerate an
individual (child) in ‘their’ culture (Lavie and Swedenburg, 1996: 3;
Koptiuch, 1996, 215–33). The present approach calls for an empathic
understanding of the individual child’s experience, an understanding
that is difficult to achieve within a legal setting, though not beyond the
capacities of legal professionals.3
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0040-2 2 - 159 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:11 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
159
3. INTERNATIONAL LAW
A. Specific References to Identity in the UN Convention on the Rights of the
Child
In Articles 7, 8 and 9, the UNCRC guarantees respectively the child’s
rights to a name, to citizenship, to know their parents and not to be
separated from them. Article 8 leaves the impression that identity is an
open-ended concept: the attributes of identity, viz., nationality, name
and family relations, are mentioned illustratively (implied by the word
‘including’) (Hodgson, 1993: 265). The next article in which we find
explicit referral to the child’s identity is Article 29. This article states the
aims of children’s education, ie, that it should encourage the child to
respect their own cultural identity and that of others from different
cultures. Article 30 guarantees the right of the minority and indigenous
child ‘to enjoy his or her own culture’. Nothing in the UNCRC defines
culture or what makes one a minority or indigenous child. No article in
the UNCRC or the different sets of guidelines deriving from the
UNCRC explicitly guarantees the child a right to preserve what they see
as their cultural identity or to preserve ties that are meaningful to them
as such, to respect their individualized identity or to ensure specifically
their involvement in defining their identity.
Questions such as these arise. Do only minority children need law’s
protection? What of undemocratic regimes in which most of the
political and economic power is in the hands of an elite belonging to an
ethnic minority? Is the child born to a Jewish father and a Christian
mother and descended from seven generations of Londoners to be
considered a minority child whose right to enjoy their culture should be
protected in England? Which culture is that? Their father’s? Their
mother’s? Is a child born to a Jewish Mother and a Moslem Arab father
in Israel to be considered a minority child in Israel, where Moslems are a
minority? Both Judaism and Islam consider the child as ‘theirs’ and
expect alliance from the child; the child is both Moslem and Jewish
according to traditional religious laws but may have grown up feeling no
sense of belonging to either of the traditional cultures. There is no
explicit answer to such questions in the text of the UNCRC.
B. The European Convention on Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms
The ECPHRFF contributes little to the definition of identity, beyond
adopting a proactive approach to the duty of the state to protect family
life (Bainham, 2000: 483–4). It does not explicitly mention the child’s
right to identity. There is an implied reference to safeguarding the
child’s right to identity in Article 8, which positively obliges ratifying
states to uphold the individual’s right to respect for family life. But, as
Bainham (2000: 483–4) maintains, it is unclear what the child’s right to
family life implies. The European Court of Human Rights ruled that the
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0041-2 2 - 160 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:11 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
160
interest of knowing one’s origins is protected by Article 8 (Frowein,
2002: 130–14). However, much remains unclear. If knowledge of one’s
origins destabilizes the child’s family life, which of the child’s interests
takes precedence and must be protected? How is the interest to be
balanced with other interests protected by rights such as the right to
state intervention on the child’s behalf or the right to parental
guidance, both of which may safeguard the child’s emotional wellbeing?
To what extent will the interest of knowing one’s parents be protected?
No answer is given in either the wording of the ECPHRFF or in the
interpretation of the UNCRC offered by the jurisprudence of the
European Court. To conclude, explicit referrals to identity in these key
international legal documents do not provide a legal framework which
may protect a child-constructed identity.
The next section examines the relationship between Articles 5, 12
and 13 of the UNCRC and suggests how the implicit references to
identity-related rights that they contain can help us to develop a
conceptual framework beyond the explicit references to identity in the
UNCRC .
C. The UN Convention: The Overall Picture
As noted earlier, the provisions of the UNCRC relating specifically to
the child’s identity do not explicitly protect the child’s individualized
identity. One cannot however understand the UNCRC’s position fully
by relating solely to these provisions. It is suggested that the UNCRC as a
whole shows that conceptually, it supports the meaning of the right to
identity proposed here. The preamble states:
. . . (the parties to the convention are) convinced that the family, as the
fundamental group of society and the natural environment for the growth and
well-being of all its members and particularly children, should be afforded the
necessary protection and assistance so that it can fully assume its responsibil-
ities within the community.
It should be noted that the preamble does not stop with a commitment
to respecting family life, but goes further: it adopts a clearly proactive
approach in advocating a positive duty by the state to support family life.
The family the preamble envisages is clearly a social family, which
nurtures the child’s psychological wellbeing. It may well not be the
biological family, but rather a foster family or an adoptive family. The
preamble also ascribes positive value to cultural plurality, stating that
member states have accepted the obligations in the UNCRC to take ‘due
account of the importance of the traditions and cultural values of each
people for the protection and harmonious development of the child’.
Article 18. 2, for its part, enjoins the state to protect and support family
life:
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0042-1 2 - 161 Rev: 01-04-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 08:51 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: JG
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
161
For the purpose of guaranteeing and promoting the rights set forth in the
present convention, State parties shall render appropriate assistance to parents
and legal guardians in the performance of their child-rearing responsibilities
and shall ensure the development of institutions, facilities and for the care of
children.
Article 20, like the preamble, can be seen as seeking to protect the
child’s ties to a personal world. However, there is no mention of identity
in the article:
When considering solutions (for children temporarily or permanently
deprived of their family environment, or in whose best interests cannot be
allowed to remain in that environment) due regard shall be paid to the
desirability of continuity in a child’s upbringing and to the child’s ethnic,
Religious, cultural and linguistic background.
Article 5 of the UNCRC, while also not mentioning the word identity,
offers an important key to understanding its intended de facto
protection of the child’s identity. It reads as follows:
State parties shall respect the responsibilities, and duties of parents or, where
applicable, the members of the extended family or community as provided for
by local custom, legal guardians or other persons legally responsible for the
child, to provide, in a manner consistent with the evolving capacities of the
child, appropriate direction and guidance in the exercise by the child of the
rights recognised in the present convention.
This article clearly frames a broad general principle, and also has a key
role to play in the interpretation of the provisions of the convention.
Importantly, it creates a new basis for the relationship between the
child, the family and state that supports the psychological rationale for
the definition of the right to identity proposed here, namely that the
state’s primary responsibility towards the child is to respect the role of
the nuclear and extended family and of the community in the child’s
life, rather than to intervene in order to protect the child from them.
A tension exists between Article 5 and Articles 12 and 13, which grant
the child a right to be heard, a right to participate in decisions relating
to them and a right to free expression — rights that can override
parents’ wishes. It is not difficult to contemplate situations in which
parents entrusted to guide the child in the exercise of their rights would
be tempted to obstruct the child from exercising their rights because of
the parents’ selfish interests (Freeman, 1997: 68; Fortin, 1998: 42).
However, it is suggested that Article 5, through its moderation,
generality and relative ambiguity, can, when understood in combi-
nation with Articles 12 and 13, contribute to an evolutionary process,
which will advance the child’s legal status. It is suggested that the
UNCRC thus encourages adults with whom the child maintains
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0043-2 2 - 162 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:12 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
162
meaningful ties to find culturally appropriate ways to respect the rights
of the child including their right to participation in decisions relating to
them.
As An-Na’im explains, delegates from the Southern hemisphere who
took part in the drafting, adoption and implementation of human
rights norms did not operate with concepts and mechanisms from their
own political, cultural and ideological history and thus the universal
human rights consensus reached is elusive (An-Na’im, 1994: 65).
It is suggested that, by trusting families and communities to respect
children’s rights and by not derogating from their cultures and
traditions, the UNCRC (primarily through Article 5) offers families and
communities a challenge which cannot easily be dismissed as patroniz-
ing, alien, imperialistic or Eurocentric, despite the fact that the
terminology of human rights originated in Europe and was mainly
developed by the West.5
It is contended here that the tension between Articles 5, 12 and 13,
and the legal complexity it produces, is to be welcomed since it reflects
the real-life complexity of responding to the child’s conflicting needs
‘to be’ and ‘to become’. Essentially, through this tension the UNCRC
overcomes the temptation to entertain a crude atomistic vision of the
child’s interests. Our discussion illustrates that by endeavouring to
reach a balance between protection rights and participation rights, the
UNCRC is not a children’s liberation manifesto. Clearly, it does not
purport to free children subjugated by adults. I suggest that it does not
abandon children to some of their rights. Children who exercise
participation rights and civil rights and also enjoy protected adult
guidance have a greater chance to develop into more rounded adults,
who can not only exercise autonomy, but also function within relation-
ships of commitment and responsibility (Freeman, 1997: 37–40; Smith,
1997:103).
This scenario, in which the child’s evolving capacities are recognized
within the guidance and protection of adults, may be threatened
because of the inadequate protection offered to the child’s right to
identity. Adults are often tempted to dismiss what a child says. For
example, they may describe their input as immature and an expression
of ignorance, ‘programming’ or ‘brainwashing’ (Ronen, 1998). Thus,
for example, through diagnosis of the controversial ‘Parental Alien-
ation Syndrome’, some courts have been persuaded to order a child who
is functioning well both emotionally and intellectually to live with a
parent whom he/she hates, or in a state institution. This may happen
even if the hated parent had been abusive towards the child and there
are objective reasons for the child’s aversion to him, as long as
brainwashing against the hated parent by the other parent is proven (eg
Bala, 1999: 194–5; Bruch, 2001). Thus, there is a real risk that Article 12
will be emptied of meaning through paternalistic notions of protecting
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0044-2 2 - 163 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:14 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
163
children from influence and coercion (Eekelaar, 1994: 56–7; Ronen,
1998: 257–9;).
If a child has legal recourse to a claim for consideration of their wishes
or feelings because, beyond allowing them self-determination as
proposed by Eekelaar (1994: esp. 52), these wishes or feelings indicate
ties that are meaningful to them, their participation in decisions
relating to them may become more visible and influential. In such
circumstances, recognizing a child’s right to be heard and to participate
in decisions pertaining to them and to express themselves freely, may
enhance the weight given to the child’s definition of family, community
and culture and may allow meaningful implementation of Article 12 in a
manner that overcomes the prima facie tension with Article 5. If a
child-constructed right to identity is recognized, the tension between
Articles 5, 12, 13 may serve the development of the child’s identity.
4. IDENTITY IN TWO CASES: THE STORIES AS TOLD BY THE COURTS
Two English Court of Appeal cases are now examined, introduced at the
outset of this article, attempting to implement the proposed redefini-
tion of the right to identity.
A. Re M (Section 94 Appeals)6
This case concerned a seven-year-old girl, whom the court called S. The
girl’s parentage was of mixed race, her mother being white and her
father black. The parents never married and upon the breakdown of
their relationship the father had unsupervised contact with the child,
which was stopped by the mother from time to time. Proceedings before
the Family Proceeding Courts ended in the magistrates granting the
mother’s application to terminate the contact between the child and the
father. The father appealed under section 94 of the Children Act 1989
and Ewbank J. dismissed the appeal. The father then appealed against
the decision to the Court of Appeal. The decision in the Appeal was
written by Butler-Sloss LJ, Kennedy LJ concurring.
Butler-Sloss LJ explained that the appeal was remitted for rehearing
because the judge did not advert at all in his judgement to the ‘major’
issue of race and to the failure of the magistrates to deal with it.7The
Judge linked the failure to deal with the question of race to other
factors:8
The mother and her new husband are white and the father is black. The child
whose photograph I have seen is clearly of mixed race. The court welfare officer
was troubled by the ending of the contact when she felt that the child would
wonder why she did not see her father, especially since she is a mixed race child.
She had said she was getting a new white daddy. The court welfare officer felt
the child was confused about her racial identity, and on my reading of the
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0045-2 2 - 164 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:15 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
164
reports and the oral evidence there was at least a hint of the mother and
grandmother shutting their eyes to this important issue. The welfare officer
asked for an adjournment for six months to enable contact at a contact center
to continue and be monitored. The magistrates made findings adverse to the
father in that he showed little interest in the child’s schooling, had little insight
in the child’s emotional or developmental needs and did not meet his financial
obligations. Although some of these findings were against the views of the court
welfare officer, the magistrates were entitled to make their own findings...The
child had said she did not want to see her father but the court welfare officer did
not believe that such was the child’s underlying view and gave reasons. The
magistrates ought in my view at least to have indicated their disagreement with
the court welfare officer on the issues of the child’s behaviour and her wishes,
which they clearly thought significant. The magistrates decided that the
contact had not added anything positive to S’s upbringing and the father had
not shown sufficient commitment and dedication to deal with the complex
situation, in particular the degree of hostility by the mother and grandmother
towards him.
The reasoning of the decision given by Butler-Sloss LJ offers some
substantive guidance to the judge re-hearing the case:9
Whether in the future this father will have any contact at all, frequent contact,
infrequent contact or indirect contact, will be a matter for the judge rehearing
the application. He or she will have to consider the significance of race and the
hostility of the maternal family towards the father and place those and all the
other factors for and against the father having contact to the child in the
balance in coming to the decision on contact. But the child’s racial origins and
the concerns of the court welfare officer have to be carefully considered and it
is for those reasons that I felt this appeal has to be allowed.
Below, I shall critically examine this reasoning leading to an outcome
I consider as highly questionable from a children’s rights perspective.
B. Re M (Child’s Upbringing)10
In this case the care and adoption of a ten-year-old black African boy of
Zulu parentage was contested between his biological parents and a
white foster mother. The boy, called P by the court, was born in South
Africa to a mother who worked as a nanny and cook/housekeeper in the
house of the foster mother who had three daughters. The mother was
not married to the father who also worked for the foster mother for a
while. From the age of 18 months the boy lived with the foster mother in
her home in a way that would enable him to remain there with his
mother instead of being sent back to his mother’s village according to
apartheid regulations. The boy and the white employer became closely
attached to each other. The father had only sporadic contacts with the
child and his mother. It appears that at some stage during P’s early years
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0046-2 2 - 165 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:17 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
165
the father had a relationship with another woman who bore him a child.
In 1992, when P was six, the foster mother decided to leave South Africa
for London because she regarded the political situation as unstable and
was worried about possible violence. When the foster mother decided to
leave, P’s parents agreed that he move with her. It is noteworthy that,
according to Thorpe J, who heard the case at first instance:11
the appellant’s first preference would have been to take both the mother and P
with her to London, but the mother made it plain that she would not leave her
homeland. . .the easiest course. . .in practical terms would have been to have left
(P) behind with (the mother). But. ..she had by then a strong...attachment to
the child. Those attachments led her to offer to continue to take care of (P) and
to provide for him as though he were her own child. . .The only issue between
the parties is as to the duration of the arrangement. (The appellant) asserts that
it was an indefinite arrangement that would endure until the completion of
(P’s) education. (The father and the mother) assert that the arrangement was
for five years precisely. It seems to me that reality lies somewhere between those
poles.
On arrival in the UK in March 1992 the foster mother told the
immigration authorities that she wished to adopt P and P was given leave
to remain in the UK for three months. By May 1992 the foster mother
had already reached a firm decision, unknown to the parents, that she
wished to adopt P. In October 1992 she wrote to the mother the
following:12
To keep (P) in this country I have to adopt him. If there is another way to do it, I
will. I will never take him away from you, so that you won’t be able to see him
again. You are his mother.
Soon after that, the parents were visited by a social worker at the foster
mother’s request in order to establish their wishes as to P’s adoption.
The parents initially objected to the adoption and the mother spoke of
not hearing from the child since July. A few days later the social worker
wrote again to say that the mother’s position appeared to have changed.
She was proposing that if P stayed in England he should visit his
biological parents each year for a month. Later, both parents expressed
the opinion that if the foster mother wanted to take the child for ever –
breaking the agreement with them – the child should return to them as
soon as possible.
Between June and August 1993 the mother wrote ten letters, some of
them dispatched within days of each other, in which the mother
pleaded for the child’s return to South Africa for a visit. In July 1993 the
foster mother wrote a letter telling the mother that she could not send P
to South Africa at that stage. The Judge described the letter as ‘a
surprisingly dispassionate response to what were moving appeals’.13 He
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0047-2 2 - 166 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:19 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
166
concluded that the father was an insubstantial figure in the child’s life,
as the only communication between him and the child was one
Christmas card.14 His appraisal of the relationship between the biologi-
cal mother and the foster mother, quoted by the Court of Appeal, is
particularly noteworthy:15
The correspondence shows the closeness of the relationship between (the
mother) and (the appellant’s) family. It further shows the tragic evaporation of
trust and affection, gradual but steady . . . it is significant that the correspon-
dence peters from frequent and intense . . .. to non-existent after the
commencement of litigation.
In 1996, four years after the initial separation from his biological
parents, the court gave its judgement. It could have chosen between
three options deriving from the parties’ contentions: adoption (as
sought by the foster mother), immediate return to South Africa (as
sought by the parents) and a return to South Africa at the end of the
period agreed upon, whatever that period might be.
The court in fact decided to adopt a fourth option. It laid down a
master plan for the child’s return to South Africa after a period of two
years in which the child would be reintroduced to ‘his’ family and ‘his’
country, to use the court’s words. In two years’ time the court would
determine the dates and the circumstances of the child’s permanent
return to South Africa. The white foster mother was to pay for the travel
expenses of the parents to England and of the child to South Africa. She
could not afford most of her undertakings, as she became unemployed.
She appealed against the order of the judge on the basis that the review
should reopen the issue of the child’s residence and upbringing during
adolescence. The child’s biological parents appealed contending that
the child’s return should not be further delayed.
An expert psychiatrist appointed by the court explained the danger-
ous consequences of forcefully and prematurely removing the child
from the foster mother and her family:16
To remove him in the middle of turmoil of disagreement would be very
profoundly damaging, to such an extent that the boy might never recover his
poise and psychological well-being and confidence.
Although it was clear from the expert opinion that the child’s mind was
set very strongly against return, the court allowed the appeal of the
parents. Ward LJ, quoting from another case, implied that allowing the
child to remain in the UK would create a great danger of slipping into
social engineering. The boy was returned to South Africa.17 The child
‘was so unhappy’ in South Africa that he was later returned to England,
into the foster mother’s care (Fortin, 1998: 357 note10). In this case,
too, I shall re-examine judicial reasoning leading to an outcome I
consider as highly questionable from a children’s rights perspective.
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0048-2 2 - 167 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:20 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
167
5. ANALYSIS OF THE TWO CASES
A. Re M (Section 94 Appeals)
Although Butler-Sloss LJ says that the magistrates thought that the
child’s wishes were significant and that they disagreed with the court
welfare officer as to the child’s underlying views, we learn very little
about how the girl saw her father or how they related to each other. The
Court of Appeal does not instruct the judge rehearing the case to look
into questions, which are fundamental to the child’ psychological
wellbeing. Does she love her father? Does she care about him at all?
Does she feel sorry for him? Is she proud of him? Does she ever dream of
living in her father’s home or of her father looking after her? Without
answers to these or similar questions, which relate to the meaning of the
parent-child tie, we know very little of this facet of the child’s
individualized identity.
The judges are morally judgemental towards the father, disparaging
his parental capacities, for apparently valid reasons. However, when
deciding on parental contact, the child’s sense of belonging and even
the concept of psychological parenthood remain unmentioned.
Nothing in the UNCRC or the ECPHRFF dictates a different outcome.
Nevertheless, the analysis offered here suggests that it is less
significant that the child says she has a ‘white’ ‘daddy’ than that she says
she has a ‘new’ ‘daddy’ (see also Eekelaar, 2004). Supported both by
recognition of the child’s need ‘to be’ underlying the child’s right to
identity and by psycholegal literature (eg Eekelaar, 1994: 48), the court
should have asked – sceptically – how a seven-year-old child who has
known her father from birth can be reconciled with the fact that she
suddenly has a ‘new father’. The Court should have explicitly assumed
that a non-racially mixed child, a child who is not confused about her
racial identity, would also be inclined to wonder why her father had
disappeared.
The magistrates’ choice of words is troubling, We learn that they
terminated contact primarily because the father had not added
anything to the child’s upbringing. However, a father is part of the
child’s being. A child may see her father as emotionally belonging to her
even if he does nothing intentional for her and even if one cannot point
to anything specific, which he added to her upbringing. As an
interdependent human being the child’s needs her father and not a
father even when he adds nothing visible to her upbringing.
Rosenblatt (1996), who is generally supportive of the Court of
Appeal’s decision, rightly points out that the nurturance of the ‘ethnic
child’ toward sound psychological development could be more prob-
lematic than that of the white child, as the latter does not have to face a
society which rejects their ‘ethnic’ parent. It is suggested that we go
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0049-1 2 - 168 Rev: 01-04-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 08:51 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: JG
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
168
beyond Rosenblatt’s championing of the court’s ‘racial and ethnic
awareness’ (1996: 641). The court’s reasoning reflects a colour con-
scious yet vague and impersonal image of the child’s identity. It is
suggested that this image is unsatisfactory from a child-centred
perspective.
If the father has no significance in his daughter’s life, if she perceives
him as not caring about her emotional needs, then being entitled to an
individualized identity, she should not be forced to see him only
because of a similarity in skin colour. If this is her perception of him, and
she is forced to see him, it seems doubtful that such meetings would
bolster her self-esteem concerning her racial identity. If, on the other
hand, the child’s father is significant to her and she wishes to be in touch
with him despite her mother’s hostility towards him, it is not the
similarity of their skin colour that should be the deciding factor. In the
latter case, the court must strike a difficult balance between the child’s
right to participation and self-constructed identity and her right to a
stable psychologically nurturing family life.
The mother and grandmother are hostile to the father and may be
shutting their eyes to the child’s confusion about her racial identity.
Their hostility may be only to the father as an individual or it may
amount to racial prejudice. The court could have made this distinction
and suggested that in both cases the child’s wishes and feelings may be
harmfully influenced by their attitudes and that they have a right and
duty to guide the child in the implementation of her rights, being loyal
to her interests in this task.
The court’s judgement misses the opportunity to draw attention to
the fine line between the sphere of imperfect yet legitimate adult
guidance and influence and what lies beyond such a sphere and
amounts to violation of the child’s rights through programming. It also
does not clarify that, whether or not intervention is the least detrimental
alternative from the individual child’s perspective, it can also be
deduced from the child’s wishes and feelings.
To summarize, the Court of Appeal addresses the question of race in
the abstract. Butler Sloss LJ does not direct our attention to the child’s
individualized identity, as perceived and constructed by the child, and
does not see the court as duty bound to protect such an identity. Thus,
the court’s decision — I assume, unintentionally – serves ethnocen-
trism. The child’s right to be in touch with the person she considers her
father is overshadowed by efforts to ensure that the break of relation-
ship with a black father will not adversely influence her feelings about
being dark skinned. The Court’s instructions to the Judge rehearing the
case can be easily justified if one resorts to the common perception of
cultural sensitivity or to the interests of the black community or black
children at large. However, from the individual child’s perspective, the
pivotal question, which was neglected, was not that of ‘the child’s racial
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0050-2 2 - 169 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:21 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
169
origins’ as such, but rather what the child sees as emotionally belonging
to him. In practice, the difference between the two may be subtle, yet it is
important to make the distinction.
B. Re M (Child’s Upbringing)
Both Neill LJ and Ward LJ wrote detailed judgements. The concluding
passage written by Neill LJ is revealing. In it he explains why the child
must be returned:18
Anyone who has studied this case cannot fail to have great admiration for the
appellant and for the love and affection, which she and her family have given to
P since he was a baby. But he has the right to be reunited with his Zulu parents
and with his extended family in South Africa.
The ‘yes, but’ dynamic of the above dicta of Neil LJ is interesting; it is
similar to a passage in an American child abuse case (the DeShaney
Case) discussed by Minow (1990b: 1674–5). The passage starts with an
empathic response, deriving from an almost instinctual sense of human
interconnectedness, and ends with what seems to be an inevitable
rational decision, which must overcome the initial empathic response.
It is suggested that, because we are conditioned, as jurists, to dichoto-
mize reason and emotion, to ignore our common interdependence and
to delegitimize empathy as a decision-making tool, the legal conclusion,
in opposition to the judges’ empathic response may seem even more
inevitable. But we should carefully explore whether the solution is as
inevitable as it seems. It is suggested that the answer is negative.
Neill LJ’s seemingly straightforward implementation of the child’s
‘right’ to be reunited with ‘his’ family may be questioned. His decision
may be seen as an implicit unrecognized determination in a conflict of
rights; between the right to be unified with one’s biological nuclear and
extended family and the right to remain with one’s foster mother who is
a psychological mother and with her family (Freeman, 1997: 13–14,
note 87). It is suggested that by denying paramountcy to the psychologi-
cal parenthood, the court may be denying the child the opportunity to
grow psychologically towards adulthood through dynamically defining
and constructing an authentic identity. Consequently the duty to give
due weight to the child’s wishes under Article 12 may be practically
emptied of meaning. Jane Fortin accurately identifies the ‘undercur-
rent’ of the court’s rationale (with which she apparently agrees) when
she writes (1998: 357):
In Re M (Child’s Upbringing) the Court of Appeal was effectively asked to redress
the perpetration of racial iinjustice by a white South African woman who had
produced a situation whereby P, a ten-year-old boy of Zulu parents, had
stronger ties of affection for her and her family than he did for his own parents.
The case was a complex one. In particular, there was the slightly unsavoury
background which suggested that the white foster mother had deceived P’s
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0051-2 2 - 170 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:22 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
170
birth parents over her true intentions when gaining their consent to her taking
P with her when she came to England.
One can see no reason to doubt that Neil LJ sincerely attempted to be
culturally sensitive. Furthermore, his decision is, strictly speaking, in
accordance with both the UNCRC and the ECPHRFF, as analysed
above. Nevertheless, one may well ask: does the ‘official story’ of a white
woman perpetrating racial injustice against her black former employee
reflect the authentic experience of the individuals involved? Was the
resulting situation unilaterally or predominantly ‘produced’ by one
individual? Does the official storyteller, namely the judge, go beyond
trying to act in a way that is commonly perceived as culturally sensitive
and seek to relate empathetically to the individuals involved? The
answer suggested here to these questions is negative.
By highlighting and reinterpreting certain facts, I would like to offer a
counter story, as lawyers often do in courtrooms (eg Ferguson, 1996:
86). In this counter story I attempt to expose and counteract an
unintentionally politicized selectivity of compassion. Let me (re)start by
pointing out that the child was raised in a Zulu environment only up to
the age of 18 months. Since that age, the foster mother, with the
biological mother’s consent and approval, had brought the child up.
This was in order to tackle an apartheid regulation mandating that the
child return to his mother’s village. The foster mother’s family objected
to her close ties with the blacks. She may have had to deceive both her
family of origin, which was supportive of apartheid regulations and
apartheid authorities in order to maintain de facto guardianship of the
child. Deceit may have been a necessary ingredient for survival in the
foster mother’s world. If we find fault with the foster mother’s
deceitfulness, why not also consider her more politically correct
deceitfulness? Could it be that deceitfulness becomes a coping strategy
too easily sought once used by necessity? It was also not contested that
the foster mother suggested that the boy’s biological mother
accompany her to England and that the mother refused because she
would not leave her homeland. There was no clear agreement as to the
duration of the child’s stay in England. Even after the foster mother
asked for the biological parents’ consent to adoption, at one stage the
biological mother was prepared to agree that the child ‘live’ in England
if he would visit her every year for a month. The most remarkable fact to
be emphasized in such a counter story would be the child’s return to
England with the consent of his biological parents after they gained full
guardianship of him.
The efforts of this counter story to reach an empathic understanding
of the individuals involved identifies no villain, but only imperfect
human beings, not always fully cognisant of their interdependence,
trying to act decently and even lovingly in a difficult social reality, and
sometimes failing. The foster mother was not implementing a master
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0052-2 2 - 171 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:23 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
171
plan to break the ties between the child and the biological parents
through her initially secret efforts to adopt the child. It was the mother’s
choice to remain in South Africa. However, at some stages, the foster
mother’s attachment to the child did not bring out the best in her – as
noted by the court, her dispassionate response to the mother’s painful
letters indicates a blatantly insensitive attitude towards the child’s
biological mother. Nor did the parents have a master plan to first use the
foster mother, a widow with three girls of her own, to raise their child
and then turn their backs on the foster mother and betray her trust by
demanding her separation from the child for good when it suited their
personal marital plans.
They initially enjoyed the love and generosity the foster mother
offered the child, but it was also her behaviour which manoeuvred them
into a position of opposition. All parties seem to be struggling with
difficult life situations. Human frailties seem to explain better than any
other reason the breakdown of relations primarily between the two
women who initially cared both about each other and for the child and
were struggling to do their best in difficult circumstances.
What is remarkable in this case is what was created and not what was
later ruined. Subtly, the case exemplifies how clear-cut racist definitions
of otherness are challenged and overcome through care and trust
between two women attached to the same child. For a while, familial,
communal and ethnic boundaries are ignored. Bitterness and distrust
between the two women could have surfaced only after alienation was
initially overcome.
It is suggested that, as in Solomon’s dilemma, the court must identify
the solution that holds most compassion for the child. I suggest that
Solomon attempting to identify the psychological mother was aided by
the fact that one of the women was ready to give up the child to save his
life. Through her decision she demonstrated her greater compassion
for the child.20 The English Court was aided by the biological parents,
especially the more involved mother, who gave several hints that the
child’s best interests lay with the foster mother. Though her pain at
being torn away from her son moved her to disagree in the hearing to
his adoption, her compassion for him is mirrored in her ambivalence.
After voicing her objection, she is, at one stage, before any litigation,
ready to concede to adoption if the child visits her for a month each
year. If the foster mother had acted in a more caring and trust-inspiring
way towards her, the litigation might have been avoided. The child
finally returned to England, not because of a court order, but probably
due to the recognition by the ‘victorious’ biological parents that he was
very unhappy in South Africa with them and with his community of
origin.
The case illustrates the abyss between respect for the child’s culture as
a context of personal meaning and cultural sensitivity as commonly
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0053-2 2 - 172 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:23 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
172
perceived. Using abstract notions of culture and ancestry and neglect-
ing culture as a context of personal meaning, the court ignored the
significance of the biological parents’ choices. The parents identified
the child’s best interests as not growing up in the Zulu village of his
mother. They preferred him to grow up in the home of a white Afrikaner
woman and they later preferred offering him a rare opportunity to
actualize his – human – potential through an English education, first in
South Africa and than in England, to educating him in a Zulu
environment, most probably, with very meagre resources and very
limited educational opportunities. Finally, I would suggest that the
parents were forced by the outcome of the proceedings, ignoring their
hints, to take the initiative to break away from their offspring in order to
respect the child’s sense of who he is and ties that he would most like to
maintain. At the end of the day, it seems that the child’s painful struggle
and the responsiveness of his biological parents to his suffering ensured
protection of an individualized child-created identity. It is conceivable
that the parents’ implied conception of identity is not inexorably tied to
a place. Proponents of ethnocentric identity could have found fault in
the parents’ actions, especially if motivated by such a conception of
identity.
To conclude, had the court recognized the child’s right to an
individualized identity as proposed here, the child’s wishes and feelings
would have been given due weight in the first place, and would have
allowed the court to protect an authentic child-constructed identity
radically different from any clear-cut notion of Zulu or Afrikaner
identity. The court could have utilized the child’s input as to his identity
to navigate a course between the child’s wishes and the responsibilities
of the different adults in his personal world. Such a course would have
been in accordance with Articles 5 and 12 of the UNCRC. Article 5 is
significantly open-ended in its wording and would have enabled
consideration of the responsibilities of the foster mother, undoubtedly
a significant person in the child’s life.
The case is, in my eyes, a classical example of the assertion that ethnic
distinctions do not indicate the personal boundaries one sets between
oneself and others, nor how society could respond to the child’s sense of
belonging. It clearly exemplifies the distinction and tension between
cultural sensitivity as commonly perceived and respect for the child’s
individualized identity.
6. CONCLUSION
The right to a self-constructed identity may be seen as deriving from the
child’s fundamental human dignity, though it goes well beyond what
has been traditionally deduced from a legal commitment to the child’s
human dignity. The two cases examined here demonstrate how the
proposed concept of identity can radically change the outcome of
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0054-2 2 - 173 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:24 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
173
child-centred deliberations. A self-constructed identity is the product of
the child’s experience rather than an adult imposition or a general
approximation of children’s experiences, wishes and feelings. Legal
recognition of such an identity leads child law into new ground.
Children may need proactive state intervention in order to maintain
relationships meaningful to them. These needs are not guaranteed
under the UNCRC, which instead now offers an ambiguous concept of
identity. It mandates that the child be educated to respect their own
cultural identity and that of others, but not that this cultural identity be
protected by the law or that the child’s feelings be consequential to the
definition of their identity.
Proactive state protection may at times imply ensuring survival of a
distinct cultural identity through indefinite future generations, mir-
roring authentic aspirations of minority children. Traditional liberal
theory cannot justify such measures, and indeed theorists adhering to
such an ethos, such as Kymlica (1989) and Tamir (1993), did not
advocate proactive state action. The scope and substance of such state
action, not discussed here, may justify further research.
Every society that is committed to human rights should see its way to
granting clear and unequivocal recognition of the child’s right to a
self-constructed identity. For this purpose an Optional Protocol to the
UNCRC may be drafted. Once the right gains recognition, child law
jurisprudence will have to develop the judicial tools needed to ascertain
a child’s authentic identity while overcoming law’s tendency towards the
abstraction and objectification of culture and while protecting the child
from premature autonomy.
Redefining the child’s right to identity has wide implications beyond
those exemplified in the two cases discussed. For example, in a
guardianship dispute, when the court rules on a child’s disputed
exposure to different religious and cultural traditions, greater weight
would have to be given to the child’s wishes and feelings in order to
protect their sense of belonging. Choosing between the Tender Age
Test, the Primary Caretaker Test and Psychological Parenthood/
Emotional Bonding Test (eg Eekelaar, 1994: 46; Sexton, 2002), it would
be almost impossible not to give paramountcy to the child’s emotional
bonding. Greater consideration will need to be given to the preferences
of a child’s biological parents regarding the cultural, religious and
ethnic identity of the couple who adopt their offspring, since such
preferences may protect the evolving construction of an identity by the
child. Open adoption would be preferred in cases of some older
children due to the infringement of closed adoption on the child’s right
to an individualized evolving identity.20
Returning to the question of social engineering raised by Ward LJ in
Re M (Child’s Upbringing), I suggest that framing decisions concerning
individual children in line with ethnocentric identity politics and
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0055-2 2 - 174 Rev: 16-04-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 11:33 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: RB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
174
purporting to correct group wrongs through court decisions relating to
ties of individual children is a subtle yet dangerous form of well meaning
social engineering. Whereas affirmative action always aims to serve the
interests of the individual minority child, here the child pays a price for
correcting group wrongs. Such decisions while often purporting to
express cultural sensitivity, may perpetuate the re-creation of insulated
discrete identities competing with each other within a social arena
which champions group differences and silences the individual child in
their efforts to chart their own way as a creator of meaning. A static
conception of identity, tying identity to place of birth may serve such a
trend (Lavie and Swedenburg, 1996) and may thus jeopardize the ties
some children develop to their places of residence. These may be, for
example, children of asylum seekers, children of foreign workers or
children abducted by a parent from their place of birth because of abuse
unrecognized in the country of origin.
Recognition of the child’s experiences through the right to identity
leads to legal responses to child law dilemmas that may be more
authentically compassionate towards the child. Protection of ties
between a marginalized parent, who has strayed from mainstream
norms of child rearing, and his child may be at odds with public
sentiment typically keen to classify, marginalize and exclude some
‘other’ and yet be authentically responsive to the child’s needs. Thus,
compassion towards the child may be less easily politicized.
Such legal responses may be less effective in serving the public
interests of retaliation and deterrence of abusive parents. However, as
exemplified through the two cases, it would be wrong to conclude that
recognition of the child’s right to an individualized identity will
necessarily strengthen the legal status of biological parents. In the
competition between biological parents and adoptive parents or
between biological parents and fosterparents, recognition of such a
right would clearly undermine the centrality of blood ‘ties’ when these
do not correspond with ties that are meaningful to the child.
NOTES
1Following the UNCRC, a child is defined here as any person from birth to the age of 18 years.
2For further critiques of an atomistic vision of the child, leading to recognition of the child’s
dependency needs see Minow, 1990: 306; Glendon, 1991: esp. 47–8, 66–75; Brooks,1996; Mutua,
2002: 80–1. For a rather pessimistic appraisal of the UNCRC’s potential to promote the rights of the
child as an interdependent human being see Freeman, 1997: 73–4.
3For detailed discussions of jurists’ ambivalence towards recourse to empathic understanding in
legal analysis see Henderson, 1987; Massaro, 1989; Minow, 1990b; Wexler, 2002.
4Citing Gaskin vUnited Kingdom (1989) 160 Eur. Ct. H.R. (ser. A.) p 25.
5For a general child-centered critical discussion of cultural relativism see Freeman, 1997:
129–35,137–40, 147.
6[1995] 1 FLR 546.
7See n 2 at 550.
8Ibid at 550.
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0056-2 2 - 175 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:25 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
175
9Ibid at 550.
10 [1996] 2 FLR 441.
11 See n 3 at 479.
12 Ibid at 492.
13 Ibid at 480.
14 Ibid at. 479.
15 Ibid at 479.
16 Ibid at 493.
17 Ibid at 454.
18 See n 3 at 454.
19 My interpretation of Solomon’s Dilemma assuming that the child’s guardianship was
determined according to responsiveness to emotional needs and not biology is certainly not
beyond dispute. See eg Woodhouse, 1994: 1526.
20 In an earlier article on the right to identity (published in Hebrew) I examined New Zealand’s
Children, Young Persons and Their Families Act of 1989 and Israeli legislation and case law. I
examined there the implementation of the right to identity in the contexts outlined in the text
focusing on Israeli case law. See Ronen, Y. (2003) ‘The child’s right to identity as a right to belong’
(Hebrew), 26 Tel Aviv University Law Review 3, 935–84.
REFERENCES
Anderer, S. J. and Glass, D. J. (2000) ‘A therapeutic jurisprudence and preventive law approach to
family law’ in D. P. Stolle, D. B. Wexler, and B. J. Winnick. Practicing Therapeutic Jurisprudence: Law
as a Helping Profession, 207–34, Durham: North Carolina Press.
Alston, P. (1994) ‘The best interests principle: Towards a reconciliation of culture and human
rights’ in P. Alston (ed) The Best Interests of the Child: Reconciling Culture and Human Rights, 1–25,
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Alston, P. and Gilmour-Walsh, B. (1996) The Best Interests of the Child: Towards a Synthesis of Children’s
Rights and Cultural Values, Sienna: UNICEF-Innocenti Studies.
An-Na’im , A. (1994) ‘Cultural transformation and normative consensus on the best interests of the
child’ in P. Alston (ed) The Best Interests of the Child: Reconciling Culture and Human Rights, 62–81,
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
An-Na’im, A. (2001) ‘Introduction’ in An-Na’im , A. (ed), Cultural Transformation and Human Rights
in Africa, London: Zed Books.
Bainham, A. (2000) ‘Family rights in the next millennium’, 53 Current Legal Problems 471–503.
Bainham, A. and Cretney, S. M. (1993) Children: The Modern Law , Bristol: Family Law.
Bala, N. (1999) ‘A Report form Canada’s “Gender War Zones”: Reforming the child related
provisions the Divorce Act’, 16 Canadian Journal of Family Law, 163–228.
Bilsky, L. (1997) ‘Naming and re-categorization in the law: Child abuse as slavery’, 5 International
Journal of Children’s Rights, 147–76.
Brooks, S. L. (1996) ‘Family systems paradigm for legal decision making affecting child custody’ 6
Cornell Journal of Law and Public Policy, 1, 1–22.
Bruch, C. S. (2001) ‘Parental alienation syndrome and parental alienation: Getting it wrong in
child custody cases’ 35 Family Law Quarterly, 527–52.
Cohn, H. H. (1991) ‘A human rights theory of law: Prolegomena to a methodology of instruction’
in A. Barak, and R. Gabizon (ed), Haim H. Cohn: Selected Essays, 17–43, Tel Aviv: Bursi Publishing
House.
Cooper, A., Hetherington, R., Bainstow, K., Pitts, J. and Spriggs, A. (1995) Positive Child Protection —
A View from Abroad, Dorset: Russell House Publishing.
Daicoff, S. (2000) ‘The role of therapeutic jurisprudence within the comprehensive law
movement’ in D. P. Stolle, D. B. Wexler and B. J. Winick, Practicing Therapeutic Jurisprudence: Law
as a Helping Profession, 465–92, Durham: North Carolina Press.
Deng, F. M. (2002) ‘Conclusion: The cause of justice behind civil wars’ in I. Amadiume, I. and A.
An-Na’im, The Politics of Memory: Truth, Healing and Social Justice, 184–200, London: Zed Books.
Eekelaar, J. (1994) ‘The interests of the child and the child’s wishes: The role of dynamic self
determination’ in P. Alston (ed), The Best Interests of the Child: Reconciling Culture and Human
Rights, 42–61, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Eekelaar, J. (2004) ‘Children between Cultures’, 18 International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family,
178–94.
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0057-2 2 - 176 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:26 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
CHILD
S RIGHT TO IDENTITY
176
Engel, D. And Munger, F. (1996) ‘Rights, remembrance and the reconciliation of difference’, 30
Law and Society Review 7–53.
Erbele, E. J. (2002) Dignity and Liberty: Constitutional Visions in Germany and the United States,
Westport: Praeger Publishers.
Erikson, E. (1963) ‘The golden rule and the cycle of life’ in R. W. White (ed), The Study of Lives:
Essays on Personality in Honour of Henry A. Murray, 413–28. New York: Atherton Press.
Erikson. E. (1970) Gandhi’s Truth. On the Origins of Militant Nonviolence, London: Faber and Faber.
Falk, Z. (1998) ‘Rights and autonomy: Or the best interests of the child?’ in G. Douglas and L.
Sebba (ed), Children’s Rights and Traditional Values, Geraldine Van Bueren (Series ed)
Programme on International Rights of the Child, 111–17, Aldershot: Dartmouth Publishing.
Feast, J. (2000) ‘Comment: Adoption and identity’, 30 Family Law, 387.
Ferguson, R. A. (1996) ‘Untold stories in the law’ in P. Brooks and P. Gewirtz (ed), Law’s Stories:
Narrative and Rhetoric in the Law, 84–98, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Feuerstein, R. (1984) ‘On the desirability of preserving family and communal traditions’ in A.
Zahavi, Hanegbi, R. and H. Shalom (ed), The Integration of Immigrant Adolescents: A Selection of
Articles Drawn from the Publications of Youth Aliyah, 20–30, Jerusalem: Jewish Agency–Youth Aliyah.
Feuerstein, R. and Hoffman, M. (1982) ‘Intergenerational conflict of rights: Cultural imposition
and self realization’ 58 Viewpoints in Teaching and Learning 44–63.
Fortin, J. (1998) Children’s Rights and the Developing Law, Law in Context Series, London:
Butterworths.
Franklin, B (1986) ‘Children’s political rights’ in B. Franklin (ed), The Rights of Children, 24–53
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Freeman, M., D. A. (1992) Children, Their Families and the Law: Working with the Children Act,
Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Freeman, M. (1997) The Moral Status of Children: Essays on the Rights of the Child, Hague: Kluwer Law
International.
Frowein, J. A. (2002) ‘The concept of human dignity in international law’ in D. Kretzmer and E.
Klein (ed), The Concept of Human Dignity in Human Rights Discourse, Hague: Kluwer Law
International.
Gandhi, M. (2001) An Autobiography, or the Story of my Experiments with Truth. Translated from the
original Gujarati by M. Desai with an Introduction by S. Khilnani, London: Penguin Books.
Geertz, C. (1983) Local Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpretative Anthropology, New York: Basic Books.
Gewirtz, P. (1996) ‘Narrative and rhetoric in the law’ in P. Brooks and P. Gewirtz (ed) Law’s Stories:
Narrative and Rhetoric in the Law, 2–13, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Gilligan, C. (1982) In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development, Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
Glendon, M. A. (1991) Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse, New York: Free Press.
Henderson, N. (1987) ‘Legality and empathy’ 85 Michigan Law Review 1574–1653.
Herman, J. L. (1992) Trauma and Recovery, London: Pandora.
Hodgson, D. (1993) ‘The international legal protection of the child’s right to a legal identity and
the problem of statelessness’ 7 International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family, 255–70.
Hoelgaard, S. (1998) ‘Cultural determinants of adoption policy: A Colombian case study’, 12
International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family, 202–41.
Howe, D., Feast, J. and Coster, D. (2000) Adoption, Search and Reunion: The Long Term Experience of
Adopted Adults, London: The Children’s Society.
Julius, A. (1999) ‘Introduction’ in M. Freeman and A. D. E. Lewis (ed), Law and Literature: 2 Current
Legal Issues, xi– xxv, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kline, M. (1992) ‘Child welfare law, “Best interests of the child”, ideology and first nations’, 30
Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 2, 375–425.
Kopitiuch, K. (1996) ‘“Cultural defence” and criminological displacements: Gender, race, and
(trans) nation in the legal surveillance of US diaspora Asians’ in S. Lavie and T. Swedenburg
(ed), Displacement, Diaspora, and Geographies of Identity, 215–33, Durham: Duke University Press.
Kufeldt, K. (1993) ‘Listening to children: An essential for justice’, 1 International Journal of Children’s
Rights 155–64.
Kymlicka, W. (1989) Liberalism, Community and Culture, Oxford: Calderon Press.
Lavie, S. and Swedenburg, T. (1996) ‘Introduction: Displacement, Diaspora and Geographies of
Identity’ in Lavie, S. and Swedenburg, T. (ed) Displacement, Diaspora, and Geographies of Identity,
1–25, Durham: Duke University Press.
Lukinsky, J. (1987) ‘Law in education: A reminiscence with some footnotes to Robert Cover’s
Nomos and Narrative’,96 Yale Law Journal, 1836–59.
MFK-Mendip Job ID: 10262BK-0058-2 2 - 177 Rev: 21-05-2004 PAGE: 1 TIME: 10:28 SIZE: 60,01 Area: JNLS OP: AB
OUP IJLPF: INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW, POLICY AND THE FAMILY
Manu. No. Ronen007
YA
IR RONEN
177
Mandela, N. (1994) Long Walk to Freedom: The Autobiography of Nelson Mandela, London: Little,
Brown and Company.
Massaro, T. (1989) ‘Empathy, legal storytelling, and the rule of law: New words, old wounds?’, 87
Michigan Law Review 2099–127.
Minow, M. (1986) ‘Rights for the next generation: A feminist approach to children’s rights’, 9
Harvard Women’s Law Journal 1–24.
Minow, M. (1987) ‘We the family: Constitutional rights and American families’, 74 Journal of
American History, 3, 959–83.
Minow, M. (1990a) Making all the Difference: Inclusion, Exclusion and American Law, Ithaca: Cornell
University Press.
Minow, M. (1990b) ‘Words and the door to the land of change: Law, language and family violence’,
43 Vanderbilt Law Review 1665–706.
Minow, M. (1999) Not Only for Myself: Identity, Politics and the Law, New York: New Press.
Mutua, M. (2002) ‘The Banjul charter: The case for an African cultural fingerprint’ in A. An-Na’im
(ed) Cultural Transformation and Human Rights in Africa, 68–107, London: Zed Books.
Nandy, A. (1990) At the Edge of Psychology: Essays in Politics and Culture, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Post, R. (1995) Constitutional Domains: Democracy, Community, Management 3–4, Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
Raz, J. (1998) ‘Multiculturalism’, 11 Ratio Juris, 3, 193–205.
Re M (Section 94 Appeals) [1995] 1 FLR 546.
Re M (Child’s Upbringing) [1996] 2 FLR 441.
Rockefeller, S. C. (1994) ‘Commentin A. Gutmann (ed), Multiculturalism: Examining the Policy of
Recognition, 87–98, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Rogers, C. R. (1989) Carl Rogers on Personal Power: Inner Strength and its Revolutionary Impact. London:
Constable.
Ronen, Y. (1998) ‘Protection for whom and from what?: Protection proceedings and the voice of
the child at risk’ in G. Douglas and L. Sebba (ed), Children’s Rights and Traditional Values. Van
Bueren, G. (ed) Programme on International Rights of the Child Series 249–63. Aldershot: Dartmouth
Publishing.
Ronen, Y. (2003) ‘The child’s right to identity as a right to belong’ (Hebrew), 26 Tel Aviv University
Law Review, 3, 935–84.
Rosenblatt, J. (1996) ‘The needs of black and ethnic children’s perspectives’, 26 Family Law 641.
Rosenblatt, J. (2003) ‘Letters: CAFCASS and the UN Convention on the rights of the child’ 33
Family Law Journal 440.
Sacks, J. (2002) The Dignity of Difference: How to Avoid the Clash of Civilisations, London: Continuum.
Schon, D. (1991) The Reflective Practitioner: How Professionals Think In Action, New York: Basic Books.
Sexton, S. D. (2000)‘A custody system free of gender preferences and consistent with the best
interests of the child: Suggestions for a more protective and equitable custody system’, 88
Kentucky Law Journal 761–801.
Slaughter, M. (2000) ‘Contested identities: The adoption of American Indian children and the
liberal state’, 9 Social and Legal Studies 227–48.
Smith, C. (1997) ‘Children’s rights: Judicial ambivalence and social resistance’, 11 International
Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 103–39.
Tamir, Y. (1993) Liberal Nationalism, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Taylor, C. (1991) The Ethics of Authenticity, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Taylor, C. (1994) ‘The politics of recognition’ in A. Gutmann (ed) Multiculturalism: Examining the
Politics of Recognition 73, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Van Bueren, G. (1995) ‘The international law on the rights of the child’, 35, International Studies in
Human Rights. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Van Praagh, S. (1997) ‘Religion, custody and a child’s identities’, 35 Osgode Hall Law Journal, 2,
309–78.
Van Praagh, S. (1999a) ‘Faith, belonging and the protection of “our” children’, 17 Windsor Year
Book of Access to Justice 154–203.
Van Praagh, S. (1999b) ‘The education of religious children: Families, communities and
constitutions’, 47 Buffalo Law Review, 3, 1343–96.
Wilson, S. (1997) ‘Identity, genealogy and the social family: The case of donor insemination’, 11
International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 270–97.
Woodhouse, B. (1994) ‘Afterward: Deconstructing Solomon’s dilemma’, Symposium: Solomon’s
Dilemma– Exploring Parental Rights, 26 Connecticut Law Review 1525–32.
... Gender is sustained and created by the very people who succumb to its power and are controlled by its very notion of existence furthering the reproduction of its position in believing gender is innate, biological and natural (Burr, 2003). The need for assigning gender is unnecessary and can cause as many problems for some as it is successful for others (Fawcett Society, 2019a;Fawcett Society, 2019b;Emanuel, 2019;Olsen, 2019;Markosyan and Ahmed, 2017;Miller and Grollman, 2015;Yelland and Grieshaber, 1998;Butler, 1988;Intersex Society of North America, no date), however, it is our give right to gender, identity and protection against discrimination by law (Equality Act, 2010;Ronen, 2004;The United Nations, 1990;Humanium, no date;Universal Declaration of Human Right, 1948) therefore, leaving the developmental process of sex and gender for the individual to explore from birth allows for personal growth instead of supressing a person's fluidity in expression. ...
... If Kohlberg (1966), Mischel (1966) and Bem's (1983) research is to be considered limited and afforded primacy it is due to a large 'persistent finding in past research reifies a '"gendered" cisnormative bias' (Worthen, 2016) explaining the reason as to why data findings are always dualistic in nature affording a gendered view of only male and female subjects. By fundamentally encouraging children to participate in their own definition of gender and with the freedom of exploration to be true to who they are, will this assist in the development of adults who will have the ability to express themselves authentically, and if society is committed to Human Rights, this would be a 'clear and unequivocal recognition of the child's rights to a self-constructed identity' (Ronen, 2004). Burr (2003) however, argues that society has failed to generate a child's freedom of choice as it contests their positioning because they have not arrived from an objective reality, but from the people within their surroundings, both past and present; where conceptual frameworks already exist within their cultural language, the very way a person thinks is conditioned through the language which produces the preconditioning of thought, categories and concepts which paradoxically produces the framework of one's culture, creating a problematic discourse for those living within the sex and gender dichotomy. ...
Thesis
Full-text available
Within modern society you either conform to gender normativity or you contest it, however, a person’s positioning depends largely on how well gender is performed by the interpretations of others (Butler, 1990). To successfully navigate the gender dichotomy a person will gain rewards in status, relationships and protection, those who fail, will be ostracised, marginalised and even killed (Kosciw et al., 2018; Heshmat, 2014; Celis et al., 2013; Yelland and Grieshaber, 1998). Gender is controlled and managed for the maintenance and preservation of hierarchy and patriarchy by the ruling white, male, cis-gender, heterosexual class through the division of humans at birth based on genitalia (Jakiela and Ozier, 2018; Hibbs, 2014; Selly et al., 2011; Yelland and Grieshaber, 1998; Stets and Burke, 1996; Bordo, 1996). Gender creative parenting is not without its difficulties within this androcentric driven, dualistic ideological society however, it is a political presence for change (Weedon, 1987) that highlights the power gender has over the mind within the conscious and subconscious. If there were no essence of gender it would not produce the very idea of gender to begin with (King, 2004). Gender is sustained and created by the very people who succumb to its power and are controlled by its very notion of existence furthering the reproduction of its position in believing gender is innate, biological and natural (Burr, 2003). The need for assigning gender is unnecessary and can cause as many problems for some as it is successful for others (Fawcett Society, 2019a; Fawcett Society, 2019b; Emanuel, 2019; Olsen, 2019; Markosyan and Ahmed, 2017; Miller and Grollman, 2015; Yelland and Grieshaber, 1998; Butler, 1988; Intersex Society of North America, no date), however, it is our given right to gender, identity and protection against discrimination by law (Equality Act, 2010; Ronen, 2004; The United Nations, 1990; Humanium, no date; Universal Declaration of Human Right, 1948) therefore, leaving the developmental process of sex and gender for the individual to explore from birth allows for personal growth instead of supressing a person’s fluidity in expression. If it were left to nature then freedom to explore gender comes from within the individual, based on their own innate pull to a position for themselves.
... The central theme of this paper is that where there is a clash of a child's rights, the tiebreaker should be which right in the particular situation will best enhance the unique identity of a particular child. The paper draws on the work of Ronen (Ronen, 2004) which argues that the purpose of a child's rights framework is so the child can construct their individualised identity which is authentic and real for that particular child. The New Zealand case studies have been chosen to exemplify particular aspects of Article 5 and see how they are played out in particular court settings and whether the outcome enhances or inhibits the child's opportunity to develop their unique identity. ...
Article
Article 5 of the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child recognises the importance of parents and wider family members in ensuring that children are given appropriate directions on their rights in the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child. This paper analyses the wording of Article 5 and four New Zealand case studies to test the possible interpretations of Article 5. The paper builds on the work of Landsdown and Kamchedzera (Landsdown, 2005; Kamchedzera, 2012) who have done previous comprehensive analyses of the ambit and significance of the wording in Article 5. Article 5, like all international instruments, is not designed to provide prescriptive answers to challenging problems where there is a clash of which rights should prevail for children in particular situations. The central theme of this paper is that where there is a clash of a child’s rights, the tiebreaker should be which right in the particular situation will best enhance the unique identity of a particular child. The paper draws on the work of Ronen (Ronen, 2004) which argues that the purpose of a child’s rights framework is so the child can construct their individualised identity which is authentic and real for that particular child. The New Zealand case studies have been chosen to exemplify particular aspects of Article 5 and see how they are played out in particular court settings and whether the outcome enhances or inhibits the child’s opportunity to develop their unique identity.
... In Marshall's (2018: 179) view, however, '[i]dentity rights pursuant to the crc … can … be interpreted differently' to the focus on genetic origin, in that '[r]ather than focusing on the past, on needing to know everything about other people's lives, including those of one's father and birth giver in a unfairly gendered world, and reducing our identity to blood or genes, it is possible to explore different ways in which we can gain a strong sense of our identity through lived existence and belonging from birth' . Her preference for 'lived existence' may derive some support from Ronen (2004), who argues that the crc does not go far enough in allowing children to maintain ties meaningful to them. Marshall (2018: 178) appears to advocate a 'more fluid idea of identity focusing on self-determination through lived experience.' ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper considers the involvement of fathers in decisions about adoption, particularly in circumstances where a mother resists such involvement. It is largely a response to the work of Jill Marshall, who has argued strongly in favour of anonymous birth and adoption for children (without involvement of their fathers) as a choice that can be validly exercised by mothers. The paper argues that Marshall’s views are not obviously consistent with the requirements of Article 5 of the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child, requiring states to ‘respect the responsibilities, rights and duties of parents … to provide … appropriate direction and guidance’ in the child’s exercise of her rights.
... 33 Regarding Article 10 Mr Gaskin's complaint proved unsuccessful as the ECtHR held that Article 10 ECHR did not embody any obligation on the State concerned to impart the information. 34 After Gaskin case, the ECtHR has ruled violation of Article 8 in sense of right to know one's origin in several other cases such as cases on minors under the guardianship of a public administration and adopted children ( In the case of Godelli v. Italy the applicant, Ms Godelli, was abandoned by her mother at birth. As her mother did not consent being named, the birth certificate of Ms Godelli did not reveal her name. ...
Conference Paper
Full-text available
The right to know one’s origins means the right to know one’s parentage, i.e. one’s biological family and ascendance and one’s conditions of birth. This right raises some of the hardest legal and ethical issues in the case of adopted children, but also in cases of abandoned or displaced children, children conceived by artificial insemination or of children born out of wedlock. This particular child’s right was increasingly debated in recent years, as it conflicts with the right of the biological parent to remain anonymous. The Article 8 of the European Convention on Human Rights, while ensuring respect and protection for private and family life, guarantees at the same time two opposing rights - the right to privacy and the protection of the personal data and the right to know one’s origins. This legal solution raises the question whether the right to know the origin in case of children who have reached a certain psycho-physical maturity should prevail when it comes into the conflict with the right of the biological parent to remain anonymous? Although the legal instruments protect both rights, in recent years there is aim to promote the child’s right to know their origin rather than the anonymity of the biological parents. To address the issue of conflict between those rights this paper aims to suggest ways in which rights can be balanced against each other to provide the principles guiding the enforcement of the child’s right to known his origin in practice.
Article
Full-text available
This article investigates the extent to which the South African Legislature and the international community recognise the right to identity of a child born through embryo donation. A distinction is drawn between embryo donation, gamete donation and surrogacy. Thereafter, the article discusses the multiple aspects which the right to identity comprises, namely: personal, biological, family and siblingship identity. An assessment is made of how these various aspects are impacted by national and cross-border embryo donation arrangements. The Children's Act 38 of 2005, the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996, the National Health Act 61 of 2003 and the Regulations Relating to Artificial Fertilisation of Persons, in addition to the Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC) and the African Charter on the Rights and Welfare of the Child (ACRWC) are critically examined to the extent that may be applicable to children born through embryo donation. The article concludes that neither the South African legislative framework, nor the CRC or the ACRWC explicitly upholds the child's right to identity
Article
Full-text available
Habitual residence is a key concept in the scheme of the Hague Child Abduction Convention because it determines the applicability of the mandatory return mechanism. However, the concept is not defined, and over the years there have developed different approaches thereto. In recent years, there has been increasing doctrinal uniformity as a result of wide adoption of the hybrid approach. However, there are real disparities in the way in which this approach is applied by different judges and the question of habitual residence remains one of the most litigated issues under the Convention. This article reviews recent case law developments and explains the disparities. It then proceeds to propose guidelines that might assist in increasing uniformity and ensuring that findings of habitual residence promote the objectives of the Convention.
Article
Full-text available
This article offers an autoethnographic reconsideration of a primary school teacher’s practice and children’s interpretation of picturebooks in multicultural primary schools in England. It considers the balance teachers strike between respecting children’s rights to freedom of thought and expression, and wielding their own power as directors of learning. It links key aspects of international human rights law on children to concepts from literacy studies and multicultural children’s literature: representation of minority groups, pictorial interpretation, critical literacy and teacher power. It brings out nuanced interpretations of the picturebook The Arrival as a ‘mirror’ for learners from migrant backgrounds. This mirror may reflect children’s experiences but also offer a frosted, distorted or blank view where young learners do not empathise with characters. We argue that children’s rights within education should include freedom of thought and expression and freedom to interpret literature; teachers should reflect on their intentions when using literature, and not pose barriers to this freedom.
Chapter
This chapter discusses what an efficient EU mechanism for obtaining cross-border enforcement of a civil judgment (‘judgment import’) could look like. It discusses how to balance the judgment creditors’ right to enforcement with safeguards that should ensure that judgment debtors’ rights are respected. To this end, refusal grounds in the State of enforcement should be combined with an effective procedure for obtaining, in the Member State of origin, permission for cross-border enforcement. This chapter begins by identifying the requirements for an effective enforcement procedure that follow from the right to a fair trial. In then discusses the various mechanisms currently in force in EU legislation to determine which most effectively addresses these requirements. It concludes that a mechanism such as the European Enforcement Order, which relies on self-examination by the court of origin, is unlikely to effectively protect creditor’s and debtor’s rights. The chapter also contains a number of suggestions for improvement of the Brussels I bis Regulation, the Maintenance Regulation and the uniform European procedures. On the Brussels II bis Regulation, it concludes that the child’s best interests, rather than the parents’ right to a fair trial, should be paramount
Chapter
Full-text available
יש הסבורים שמיותר לדון בשאלת יחסו של המשפט להתנסויות הילד, ועמדתם בעניין זה היא שהמשפט ככלל אינו יכול ואינו צריך לקדם את רווחתו הפסיכולוגית של הפרט, ולכן התשובה לשאלה אם המשפט נענה לסבלו של הילד ברורה מאליה ואינה מצדיקה דיון נוסף. לשיטתם, אין לצפות שהמשפט ייענה לסבל, שכן עומדים בפניו יעדים אחרים. החיבור הנוכחי זה דוחה עמדה נפוצה זו. בסיס תאורטי–משפטי לעמדה נגדית ניתן למצוא באסכולת תורת המשפט הטיפולית (Therapeutic ,)Jurisprudenceהמניחה שהמשפט צריך לקדם את רווחתו הפסיכולוגית של הפרט הן באמצעות הוראות החוק והפסיקה הן באמצעות ההליכים המשפטיים (ראו למשל .)Wexler, 1999אסכולה זו פרצה לתודעה המשפטית הרחבה בעיקר בעשור האחרון של המאה שעברה ( )Daicoff, 2000ובהקשר המשפטי הישראלי היא נידונה בדיון מקיף ראשוני בכינוס שנערך באוניברסיטת בר–אילן בשנת .2007גישה זו שואפת לקדם את התחכום הפסיכולוגי ואת הבין–תחומיות של החשיבה ושל העשייה המשפטית, ולעשות שהמשפט ימלא בחייהם של בני האדם תפקיד אנושי יותר, מרפא, מאחה. התהליך ההדרגתי של שינוי בתפקוד המשפט כמערכת המתרחש בשיטות משפט שונות פותח פתח לתקווה בתחום זה ( .)Daicoff, 2000להלן אבחן את מידת ההיענות של המשפט לסבלו של הילד על בסיס הנחת עבודה שיסודה באסכולת תורת המשפט הטיפולית, שכן לתפיסתי, השאלה רלוונטית למחקר משפטי ולעיצוב מדיניות משפטית. את החיבור הנוכחי אפתח בביאור ובהנמקה של עמדתי, שכאמור, תמציתה כבר הובאה בחיבורים קודמים ( ,)Ronen, 2006ועל פיה שיח זכויות מופשט דוקטרינרי וחסר בלחלוחית אינו מציע מענה ממשי לסבלם של ילדים ולתביעה לצדק שמקורה בסבל הזה. לחידוד התובנה הזאת אסתייע בהגותו של עמנואל לוינס ואציג משהו מתרומתה לעמדה זו. לאחר מכן אבחן את מקומו של המונח "סבל" בחוק ובפסיקה הישראליים. מכאן אעבור לבחינת ביטויים למחויבותו של המשפט הישראלי למניעת סבל. לאחר שאפרוס בפני הקורא היבטים שונים של הסוגיה אתווה תמונת מצב. לסיום אציע כמה תיקוני חקיקה המדגימים את ההשתמעויות היישומיות של מסקנות הדיון
Book
In this notable volume, well-known authorities from the worlds of law and literature take a probing look at how and why stories are told in the law. Such experts as Alan Dershowitz, Martha Minow, Janet Malcolm, Catharine MacKinnon, and John Hollander discuss how narratives presented at trials and in Supreme Court opinions are told and listened to, and how they affect legal thinking and judgment. "Those who are unfamiliar or untutored in narrative and rhetoric will find the contributions accessible and provocative. Those who are more experienced will enjoy sorting out the disagreements among the contributors and acquire a clearer sense of what is at stake here".-Ira L. Strauber, The Law and Politics Book Review. "Law's Stories offers an unusually rich perspective on the developing scholarship of narrative and rhetoric in the law ... The book succeeds in bringing to the forefront of 'law as literature' studies a very crucial aspect of investigation and will undoubtedly become one of the touchstones of law and literature scholarship".-Wendy Chon, New York Law Journal. "Indispensable to anyone interested in legal reasoning".-Choice. "Well edited and highly readable".-Judge Richard A. Posner, University of Chicago Law Review. "Each contribution is impressively individualistic, and the grateful reader can hardly avoid being drawn into strong-minded, largely unresolvable, controversy".-Thomas Morawetz, Connecticut Law Review.