ArticlePDF Available

Human Dignity: Functions and Meanings

Authors:

Abstract

The concept of human dignity has several possible linguistic functions, which imply different and quite distinct meanings in various contexts. As Wittgenstein notes in his Philosophical Investigations, in order to understand the meaning of a word or a concept ‘one cannot guess how a word functions. One has to look at its use and learn from that.’ By applying a Wittgensteinian methodology in this paper, I seek to identify and depict different language spheres in which the concept of human dignity has different meanings, which may, at times, be contradictory. The main reason for conflicts regarding the essence of human dignity derives from the fact that changing the context of a word may generate a misunderstanding of its meaning: ‘Of course, what confuses us is the uniform appearance of words when we hear them spoken or meet them in script and print. For their application is not presented to us so clearly. Especially when we are doing philosophy!’ Furthermore, following Nathan Rotenstreich, I contend that human dignity is a rather eclectic and ambiguous notion that cannot be precisely defined. However, I do believe that a better understanding of the meanings of this term is possible by outlining and mapping the main linguistic functions of human dignity, an undertaking that will help clarify both the ambiguity concerning human dignity and the recurrent political use of this term.
Global Jurist Topics
Volume 3, Issue 3 2003 Article 3
Human Dignity - Functions and Meanings
Doron Shultziner
The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Shultziner@gmail.com
Copyright
c
2003 by the authors. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be re-
produced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic,
mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior written permission of the
publisher, bepress, which has been given certain exclusive rights by the author. Global Jurist
Topics is produced by The Berkeley Electronic Press (bepress). http://www.bepress.com/gj
Human Dignity - Functions and Meanings
Doron Shultziner
Abstract
The concept of Human Dignity has become more and more prevalent in legal, moral and
philosophical discourses. However, as much as linguistic functions of the concept have become
widespread, its meanings have become ambiguous and blurred. This paper seeks to map and de-
pict the main functions and meanings that the concept of human dignity encompass, and, hence,
to enable both those concerned with law and its interpretation, and moral-philosophers to discern
the different linguistic-spheres and the different meanings this concept encircle. The analysis will
show that the meanings of human dignity are socially constructed in accordance with particular
cultural and historical contexts. There is no one “true” meaning of human dignity, but rather differ-
ent levels of ”thickness” and ”thinness” that are culturally determined in each society. The paper
advances insights regarding the use of human dignity in both the legal parlance - as a justification
for human rights in legal documents; and in the moral-philosophical parlance - as compared to a
worldview on the one hand, and as related to humiliation on the other.
KEYWORDS: Human Dignity, Dignity, Human Rights, Justifications for Human Rights
I wish to thank the Gilo Center for Citizenship, Democracy and Civic Education, and to the
Political Science department of the Hebrew University, for their help in sponsoring this paper and
its presentation in the inaugural conference of the American Political Theory Association (2003).
Apart from institutions, I am indebted to Esther Cohen for her important linguistic suggestions
that refined this paper (although any fault that might have occurred is totally mine); and especially
to Dan Avnon for introducing Wittgenstein and teaching me the significance of being sensitive to
words.
Introduction
The concept of human dignity has several possible linguistic functions, which imply
different and quite distinct meanings in various contexts. As Wittgenstein notes in his
Philosophical Investigations, in order to understand the meaning of a word or a concept
“one cannot guess how a word functions. One has to look at its use and learn from that”
(passage 340 – original emphasis). By applying a Wittgensteinian methodology in this
paper, I seek to identify and depict different language spheres in which the concept of
human dignity has different meanings, which may, at times, be contradictory. The main
reason for conflicts regarding the essence of human dignity derives from the fact that
changing the context of a word may generate a misunderstanding of its meaning: “Of
course, what confuses us is the uniform appearance of words when we hear them spoken or
meet them in script and print. For their application is not presented to us so clearly.
Especially when we are doing philosophy!” (Ibid, passage 11). Furthermore, following
Nathan Rotenstreich (1983), I contend that human dignity is a rather eclectic and
ambiguous notion that cannot be precisely defined. However, I do believe that a better
understanding of the meanings that pertain to this term is possible by outlining and
mapping the main linguistic functions of human dignity, an undertaking that will help
clarify both the ambiguity concerning human dignity and the recurrent political use of the
term.
Hence, this paper aims at outlining a model for the concept of human dignity in a
philosophical-linguistic analysis. I intend to specify the main functions and normative
meanings ascribed to the concept of human dignity (a) as a justification for various rights
and duties in legal instruments (b) as containing a thick meaning which can be compared to
a worldview that encapsulates the following (c) rights and duties (d) honor, and (e) a thin
meaning defined by a degrading attitude or humiliation of human worth.
1
These functions
will be analyzed below.
A: Human Dignity as a Justification for Rights and Duties
The first main function of human dignity is primarily prevalent in legal instruments,
both national and international. Put simply, this function is assigned to serve as a
justification for the specific contents detailed in the legal document. The contents obviously
vary between legal documents, but the cause for their enactment is attributed to human
dignity. Let us look at some examples for this prevalent linguistic use in international and
national legal instruments.
One of the first applications of human dignity in international documents is found in
the preamble of the Charter of the United Nations (1945), where it is stated that:
We the people of the United Nations determined to save succeeding
generations from the scourge of war, which twice in our lifetime has
1
In using the Thick and Thin concepts in this paper I have relied on Michael Walzer’s useful distinction in his
Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (1994). The strong linguistic and conceptual relations
between human dignity and humiliation are found in Daniel Statman’s articles (2001, 2002).
1
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
brought untold sorrow to mankind, and to reaffirm faith in fundamental
human rights, in the dignity and worth of the human person, in the equal
rights of men and women and of nations large and small,
A similar reference is mentioned in the preamble of the Universal Declaration of
Human Rights (1948):
Whereas recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and
inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of
freedom, justice and peace in the world, Whereas disregard and contempt
for human rights have resulted in barbarous acts which have outraged the
conscience of mankind, and the advent of a world in which human beings
shall enjoy freedom of speech and belief and freedom from fear and want
has been proclaimed as the highest aspiration of the common people…
One can discern that human dignity and human rights are two separate and
interdependent concepts, although this interdependence is not yet explained in its
hierarchical and explicit formulation. Two further conventions of the United Nations clarify
the affinity between these concepts in the following wording:
Considering that, in accordance with the principles proclaimed in the Charter
of the United Nations, recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and
inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of
freedom, justice and peace in the world,
Recognizing that these rights derive from the inherent dignity of the
human person,
2
That is to say, in these U.N documents, human dignity is regarded as a supreme value
that not only stands separated from human rights but also supercedes them. Human rights
are derived from human dignity while the later encompasses the essential characteristics of
human beings. Legal instruments do not specify what these traits are or what exactly human
dignity consists of: these are taken to be, as Teresa Iglesias puts it, “bedrock truths”.
3
The linguistic function of human dignity as a justification for rights and duties is
found in other international documents. For instance, the American Declaration of the
Rights and Duties of Man (1948) declares that “the American peoples have acknowledged
the dignity of the individual” and from this follows their recognition that “the essential
2
United Nations Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, adopted by GA Res. 2200A (XXI) of 16
December 1966; United Nations Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, adopted by GA Res. 2200A of 16
December 1966, Preamble (emphasis added). All the covenants mentioned in this paper are conveniently
collected in Brownlie (1994).
3
“To be a human being is not a status conferred upon me by anyone. Nor is this a status that I, nor anybody
else, can confer upon others. […] These are facts of recognition, of acknowledgment, constituting the very
beings we are, and that we take for granted in what we do. We are not “instructed” in these truths, they
become part of us in the process of being alive and aware as human beings. Let me acknowledge these facts
as bedrock truths(Iglesias, 2001: 114).
2
Global Jurist Topics , Vol. 3 [2003], Iss. 3, Art. 3
http://www.bepress.com/gj/topics/vol3/iss3/art3
rights of man are not derived from the fact he is a national of a certain state, but are based
upon attributes of his human personality”.
4
Similarly, the Final Act of the Helsinki
Conference acknowledges that “they [the states] will promote and encourage the effective
exercise of civil, political, economic, social, cultural and other rights and freedoms all of
which derive from the inherent dignity of the human person”.
5
To conclude this point, it is
apparent that human dignity in international instruments is the foundation and justification
for rights and duties: because of human dignity, human beings have rights and duties.
6
After the examination of some international legal documents, we shall now examine
some national constitutions. Actually, since the end of World War II and the inception of
the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, the linguistic application of human dignity in
national constitutions has increased significantly in comparison to the period before that
war.
7
Indeed, it was the scourges of the war that yielded the increase of the linguistic
application of human dignity (Arieli, 2002). For instance, in the Basic Law of Spain it is
said: “The Spanish State proclaims as a guiding principle of its acts, respect for the dignity,
integrity and freedom of the human person”
8
. The Constitution of India seeks “to promote
among them all [India’s citizens]; Fraternity assuring the dignity of the individual and the
unity and integrity of the nation”
9
. The Constitution of Portugal establishes that “Portugal
is a sovereign Republic, based on the dignity of the human person and the will of the
people”
10
. And the first words of the Basic Law of Germany determine that “Human dignity
is inviolable. To respect and protect it is the duty of all state authority”.
11
In these examples
and many more, human dignity is mentioned alongside with other supreme values such as
“freedom”, “integrity of the nation”, “just society”, “solidarity”, “God”.
12
Namely, human
dignity is taken as a supreme value that bestows moral justification upon the concrete
instructions specified in the document. In other words, the articles in a constitution are
meant to articulate and specify the belief in human dignity and what it requires.
4
American Declaration of the Rights and Duties of Man, Final Act of the Ninth International Conference of
American States, 1948.
5
Final Act of the Helsinki Conference, Adopted on August 1975, Article VII.
6
Cf.: “human dignity is the source from which human rights and liberties are derived. […] It is human dignity
that provides the causa, as well as the ratio, for all human rights legislation (Cohn, 1981: 231-232 – original
emphasis).
7
There are about four constitutions (Mexico, Finland, Ireland and Cuba) that refer to human dignity in the
period of 1900-1945 (before the end of the war); and more than 37 from 1945-1997, see (Iglesias, 2001).
8
Basic Law of Spain, 1945, Article 24.
9
Constitution of India, 1949, Preamble.
10
The Constitution of Portugal 2 April 1976, Article 1.
11
The Basic Law of Germany, May 23
rd
, 1949, Article 1. However, that does not necessarily mean there is
judicial consent in Germany regarding what pertains to human dignity and what does not. For a review of
such difficulties and legal usages with the concept in Germany consult Kommers (1997) and Ullrich (2003).
12
In the name of the Most Holy Trinity, from Whom is all authority and to Whom, as our final end, all
actions both of men and States must be referred, We, the people of Ireland, humbly acknowledging all our
obligations to our Divine Lord, Jesus Christ, Who sustained our fathers through centuries of trial,
Gratefully remembering their heroic and unremitting struggle to regain the rightful independence of our
Nation, And seeking to promote the common good, with due observance of Prudence, Justice and Charity, so
that the dignity and freedom of the individual may be assured, true social order attained, the unity of our
country restored, and concord established with other nations, Do hereby adopt, enact, and give to ourselves
this Constitution” Constitution of Ireland, 1937, Preamble (emphasis mine).
3
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
I know of only three unusual linguistic functions in national constitutions regarding
the concept of human dignity. Their distinction lies in determining human dignity as a
discrete human right. The first, in chronological order, is to be found in the Constitution of
Hungary, where it is stated that “In the Republic of Hungary everyone has the inherent
right to life and to human dignity. No one shall be arbitrarily denied of these rights”.
13
Second is the Israeli Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty, where the right to human
dignity is implied in article 4: “Everyone is entitled to protection of his life, body and
dignity”.
14
The third unusual function is to be found in the new Constitution of South
Africa, where human dignity is mentioned as the first supreme value upon which South
Africa is founded.
15
Moreover, article 7(1) establishes a similar relation between human
dignity and human rights to the one we have observed in the international instruments, i.e.
where human rights are derived from human dignity and are affirmed by it: “This Bill of
Rights is a cornerstone of democracy in South Africa. It enshrines the rights of all people in
our country and affirms the democratic values of human dignity, equality and freedom”.
Nevertheless, article 10 declares that “everyone has inherent dignity and the right to have
their dignity respected and protected”. This assumption is strengthened in light of article
37(5), which confirms that human dignity is a right that cannot be restricted under any
circumstances.
16
However, these last three examples are the exception and do not constitute the rule.
As has been said with regard to most constitutions, human dignity is regarded as the source
or the supreme value upon which all rights and duties, and all state actions depend. Because
human beings have dignity they should be given certain treatment and human dignity must
not be degraded or humiliated.
A (1): Symbolic-Representation and the Lack of a Fixed Content
However, one is bound to inquire about the legal essence of human dignity, and
wonder about what exactly it means by required treatment (the should) and by humiliating
actions (the must not). This leads to observing a twofold feature of human dignity as it is
used as a justification for rights and duties in legal documents: symbolic-representation and
a lack of a fixed content.
First, let us examine what is meant by symbolic-representation. In the preambles of
documents that specify rights and duties, there seems to be some sort of an a-priori
bedrock-truth justification, which is usually articulated as human dignity. This approach
enables an accepted starting point for legislation, because as for itself, human dignity does
13
The Constitution of Hungary, 20 Aug 1949, Article 54(1).
14
Israeli Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty. 25.3.1992 (revised at 10.3.1994).
15
“The Republic of South Africa is one, sovereign, democratic state founded on the following values: a.
Human dignity, the achievement of equality and the advancement of human rights and freedoms” The
Constitution of South Africa, 1993, Article 1.
16
It is worth noting that Supreme Justice of South Africa, Arthur Chaskalson, realizes that such a linguistic
usage is rare and explains this in the following way: “The reluctance to give dignity the status of a discrete
right in human rights instruments may be due to the breadth of its meanings and the difficulty of defining its
limits… where this has been done, the entrenchment or implication of a residual right of dignity might be
thought to have an open-ended quality which would be unmanageable” (Chaskalson, 2002: 135-136).
4
Global Jurist Topics , Vol. 3 [2003], Iss. 3, Art. 3
http://www.bepress.com/gj/topics/vol3/iss3/art3
not determine what the reason or rationale among possible reasons and rationales for the
existence and protection of certain norms in a legal document is, but, rather, leaves the
philosophical debate undecided.
17
There is a major advantage to this approach, for the
abstention from a philosophical decision regarding the source and cause for rights and
duties paves the way for a political consent concerning the specific rights and duties that
ought to be legislated and enforced in practice without waiving or compromising basic
principles of belief.
18
Thus, the different parties that take part in a constitutive act can
conceive human dignity as representing their particular set of values and worldview. In
other words, human dignity is used as a linguistic-symbol that can represent different
outlooks, thereby justifying a concrete political agreement on a seemingly shared ground.
This leads to the second aspect: the lack of a fixed content. The very fact that
various worldviews and ideologies are strongly related to the concept of human dignity
produces a paradoxical situation in that human dignity as for itself does not contain any
concrete content or meaning. Because human dignity anchors different worldviews, it
cannot represent any particular set of values or meaning that “naturally” stem out of it.
There is no fixed and universal content that spouts out of human dignity and, hence, its
content and meanings are determined separately in each legal document in accordance
with the political agreement achieved at that time. This is mainly why recognition in
human dignity yields different legal documents, as is evident when comparing the
overarching duties in the African Charter on Human and People’s Rights
19
and the
American Declaration of the Rights and Duties of Man
20
to the liberal rights emphasis in
the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights
21
and to the limited scope of rights
enumerated in the Israeli Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty
22
, all of which recognize
human dignity as a supreme value. Therefore, the content of human dignity is a corollary of
a political agreement and compromise set in each legal document by the cultural, political,
constitutional and other conditions, which can evolve and change in the course of history.
23
17
Cf.: The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, striving for a pronouncement that would appeal to
diverse political systems governing diverse peoples, built on that faith and eschewed philosophical
exploration […] There is no agreed theory justifying ‘human dignity’ as the source of right, and we are not
told how the needs of human dignity are determined” (Henkin, 1989: 134-135).
18
This was, in fact, the approach taken by the drafters of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. See:
“Maritain restated the question before the committee. Instead of, How can such disparate intellectual positions
be reconciled?, he asked, How much agreement can we reach regarding practices even while remaining
incurably divided regarding the underlying theory for such practices? […] This distinction—taken over from
the UNESCO experience by those working on the Universal Declaration—allows people to stand firm on all
points of principle, avoiding the trap of moral indifferentism or relativism. A Muslim need not surrender one
iota of Muslim faith, or a Christian of Christian faith. Nor need a Communist abandon Communist theory.
Maritain’s approach was to ask one question only: Do you agree that the support of this practice and the
prohibition of that other practice is a worthy criterion for the world community? Do you agree to declare that
your nation will live under this code of practices?” (Novak, 1999 – original emphasis).
19
African Charter on Human and People’s Rights, 17 June 1981, Chapter II (Duties), Articles 27-29.
20
American Declaration of the Rights and Duties of Man, 1948, Chapter II (Duties).
21
Cf. footnote no. 2.
22
Cf. footnote no. 14.
23
Cf.: Developments in the idea and jurisprudence of rights during two hundred years under the Constitution
suggest continuing refinement of our society’s sense of human dignity and an evolving appreciation of what
human dignity requires” (Henkin, 1992: 227).
5
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
B: The Thick Meaning of Human Dignity
So far, we have observed the linguistic usages of human dignity functioning as a
justification for rights and duties in legal instruments. Yet, human dignity is not merely a
legal concept that is expressed by specified norms. Rather, it is primarily a moral-
philosophical term, which, like other moral concepts, has different levels of meanings
pending on its context and linguistic functions. Michael Walzer, on whom I have relied in
using the thick and thin terminology, states this argument clearly: “Moral terms have
minimal and maximal meanings; we can standardly give thick and thin accounts of them,
and the two accounts are appropriate to different contexts, serve different purposes” (1994,
2). Namely, the main difference between the linguistic functions that will be analyzed
hereafter reflect discrete moral meanings intertwined with the concept of human dignity.
As a moral concept taken in the thick meaning, human dignity embraces two
fundamental and interrelated premises: human and dignity. In fact, our understanding of
human dignity is deeply inherent in our way of perceiving the world and its dwellers. The
word human relates to basic assumptions in our consciousness, or rather sub-consciousness,
about human nature, worth, place in the cosmos, attributes and character. And inseparably
of human, we have a strong understanding of dignity: human dignified or natural existence,
human normative behavior that best reflects their good nature, and human positive and
negative attributes. Put differently, the thick meaning of human dignity encapsulates a
whole moral worldview.
Our worldviews are “a complex, often unarticulated (and perhaps not fully
articulable) set of deeply held and highly cherished beliefs about the nature and
organization of the universe and one’s place in it” (Benjamin, 1990: 88). A worldview is
formulated (and changes) in the course of our lives together with the process of forming our
consciousnesses. Each worldview encapsulates the recognition about the “nature and
organization of the universe” and “one’s place in it”.
24
Therefore, the extensive meanings
associated with human dignity overlap those inherent in a worldview, a moral worldview to
say the least. Both are composed of general principles that are not lucid or fully verbalized.
Namely, the thick meaning of human dignity is a maximal moral meaning that encapsulates
both the convictions in human moral worth and the variety of desirable moral conducts that
are commensurable with human essential worth, as also their reverse.
The thick meaning of human dignity is brought up in diverse contexts of moral
parlance: when an attitude is taken regarding the issue of whether certain conduct towards
children – like compulsory education or their lack of freedom in various issues – is
commensurate with their human dignity or opposes it; when establishing a principle (or
principles) of distributive justice that embody the dignity of a the human being and the
24
Compare Benjamin’s definition to Herbert Spiegelberg’s saying: The search for grounds of human dignity
presupposes a full pledged philosophical anthropology, showing not only man’s essential nature, its
ingredients, its structure and its place in the cosmos, but also his values, rights and responsibilities. Only on
such basis will it be adequate survey of the possible grounds for his dignity” (Spiegelberg, 1970: 61). See also
(Rotenstreich, 1983: chapter III).
6
Global Jurist Topics , Vol. 3 [2003], Iss. 3, Art. 3
http://www.bepress.com/gj/topics/vol3/iss3/art3
values of a just society
25
; when debating a policy that encroaches on citizens’ privacy in
favor of national security; when establishing a military moral code towards soldiers in the
military apparatus, and determining a proper conduct of soldiers towards civilians in times
of conflict – namely, codes of behavior that are becoming of human dignity
26
; when
debating important issues such as the death penalty or abortions on the grounds of
respecting or degrading human dignity. The linguistic function of human dignity in these
linguistic spheres is embedded in a particular cultural or ideological understanding of what
human dignity is and what it entails, which is a thick, stratified and all-embracing
understanding, and which is not confined to only one area of human action or to one form
of life. To put it in Wittgenstein’s words: “to imagine a language means to imagine a form
of life” (passage 19). In our context, one can say that the different linguistic functions of
human dignity reflect our diverse forms of life.
Moreover, albeit the thick meaning of human dignity is discernible in a particular
culture, it is even more apparent in a cross-cultural perspective. It is a well-known fact that
there are quite heterogeneous premises about human nature and human dignified conduct
towards his fellow human beings. Therefore, human dignity has various thick meanings
based on cultural and subcultural contexts (see also: Bryder, 1994). Our thick perception of
human dignity is shaped in a particular social and cultural climate, which dictates the way
we learn to recognize and evaluate other human beings.
27
Nevertheless, it goes (almost)
without saying that our particular thick conception of human dignity is far from being
objective or universal.
A citizen of a liberal-democracy, for instance, will find traditional Islamic
conceptions of human dignity to be different and even incompatible with his own. “The
Islamic tradition”, says Abdul Aziz Said, “does not provide an explicit model for growth as
understood in the West. Islam views materialism as detrimental to human dignity,
undermining the nobility of the human species” (1979, 90). Furthermore, the notion of
freedom in traditional Islam might also seem to be in conflict with a thick liberal
conception of human dignity that is identified with rights and lack of restraints. In Islam,
“human rights exist only in relation to human obligations. Individuals possess certain
obligations toward God, fellow humans, and nature, all of which are defined by the
Shariah” and “those who do accept these obligations have no rights, and any claims of
freedom that they make upon society lack justification” (Ibid, 92). In addition, the dignified
existence of man in traditional Islam and his appropriate posture in the social order is
remarkably different from that of a (or “his”) woman. In Islam, this difference between man
and woman within the thick meaning of human dignity is due to the basic assumptions
regarding their appropriate place in the cosmic and social order, which are considerably
different from Western assumptions and practices.
25
For conceptions of distributive justice as reflecting a thick meaning of morality, see the second chapter in
Thick and Thin (Walzer, 1994); and on the historical and conceptual connection between human dignity,
economics and religion see (Novak, 1998).
26
See “Human Dignity in the Israel Defence Forces” (Israel Democracy Institute, 2001).
27
Yuval Luria explains that “concepts of dignity, by which we perceive our life and others around us, are like
psychological-glue through which social values that guide our life are attached to us and shape our conduct.
They are the initial and fundamental dress that embody humane cultural values” (1994, 179).
7
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
In a similar manner, there are other thick traditional-cultural worldviews of human
dignity that express human dignity in a way not parallel or committed to human rights.
These thick meanings of human dignity emphasize the entitlements of society over those of
the individual and the duties of the latter to his or her community which imparts one’s
human value (Donnelly, 1982). These cultural differences also project on the way in which
political relations and regimes are organized. Societies whose historical and cultural
heritage is founded upon the centrality of the individual have regimes and constitutive
arrangements that emphasize and assure the rights of individuals counter to state power and
society, while societies whose heritage is founded upon conformity, uniformity and
adherence to a (more or less) defined set of values and norms have regimes and constitutive
arrangements that emphasize the duties of the individual to his or her community (Howard
& Donnelly, 1986).
To conclude this point, the thick meaning of human dignity is a particular cultural
understanding of what it means to be human and have a dignified life with fellow human
beings. In the thick meaning of human dignity, the emphasis is on the particular and
subjective, not on the universal and objective. For this reason, Rhoda Howard’s definition
is very precise for the thick meaning: “I define human dignity as the particular cultural
understandings of the inner moral worth of the human person and his or her proper
political relations with society” (1992, 83 – original emphasis). Howard’s definition
enables the inclusion of a variety of existing particular cultural understandings of human
dignity and, hence, to recognize that there is more than one true meaning of human dignity,
and by so to fit the cultural heterogeneous reality.
28
So far, we have seen the similarity between the thick meaning of human dignity and
that of a moral worldview, and further argued that various cultural understandings of
human dignity exist. We shall now turn to examine three main components of the thick
meaning of human dignity. These additional components are not alternative moral
conceptions with lesser moral significance in comparison to the thick meaning of human
dignity. Rather, they are contained and encircled within the thick meaning. The three other
components of human dignity consist of a twofold function: first, they embody three
distinct moral language spheres in which human dignity plays a central role and where its
meanings are formed; and second, each of these meanings corresponds to a distinct moral
echelon that is part and parcel of the thick meaning.
C: Rights and Duties
The first component is rights and duties that are integral to a thick conception of
human dignity. Actually, many people, especially in the West, use the term human rights as
a synonym for human dignity
29
, and when they speak of human dignity, they refer to a
certain list of rights. But human dignity is not expressed and assured in every worldview by
human rights alone, and there are worldviews that dictate more duties than rights or rights
only in subjection to duties. For while the Western world identifies human dignity
especially with human rights, other cultural and ideological worldviews depict human
28
Consult also (Pollis & Schwab, 1979).
29
For a similar claim see (Howard & Donnelly, 1986: 801).
8
Global Jurist Topics , Vol. 3 [2003], Iss. 3, Art. 3
http://www.bepress.com/gj/topics/vol3/iss3/art3
dignity in regard to individual duties to his society, state, God, constitution, the duties of
women to their husbands and the like (Donnelly, 1982).
Rights and duties are the main echelon in creating an affinity between a human’s
basic worth and his dignified existence, and they stem from the basic premises regarding
human essential worth according to a particular cultural understanding. Rights and duties
are enumerated in constitutional documents, which usually give voice to the central (or
mainstream) values of society. For instance, the constitutions of Germany, Greece,
Portugal, Spain, Belgium, Sweden, Switzerland and other liberal-democratic states voice a
strong affinity between human dignity and human rights, since the former is taken to be the
justification of the latter, as has been shown previously. But one can notice that human
dignity is defined in a special way within societies and cultures that are not liberal in
character.
For example, the preamble of the constitution of China establishes that the people,
organizations and political parties of China “must take the Constitution as the basic norm of
conduct, and they have the duty to uphold the dignity of the Constitution and ensure its
implementation” and on top of that, it is said that “the state upholds the uniformity and
dignity of the socialist legal system” [Article 5(1)].
30
A similar duty to uphold and dignify
the constitution of the state, as part of society’s goals, is to be found in the constitution of
Iran, which is founded on the belief in Allah and Shiite Islam: “It is incumbent on all to
adhere to the principles of this Constitution, for it regards as its highest aim the freedom
and dignity of the human race and provides for the growth and development of the human
being” [Mass-Communication Media (Article)].
31
Moreover, it is worth mentioning that the
Iranian Constitution emphasizes the special elements of woman’s essential worth, and in
accordance with this special worth, she is destined and honored to be responsible for the
basic unit of society, namely, the family, while helping to foster and promote her man
[Woman in the Constitution (Article)]. A different cultural emphasis can be found in the
constitution of Thailand, which recognizes the dignity and rights of the individual, but first
and foremost, recognizes the duty of every citizen to dignify the King, who is the first
among citizens
32
and who must not be exposed to an accusation of any sort.
33
To sum up this aspect, human dignity in the meaning of rights and duties is defined
upon concepts that pertain to the rights and duties’ parlance and sometimes as a synonym
30
And compare: “The personal dignity of citizens of the People's Republic of China is inviolable. Insult, libel,
false charge, or frame-up directed against citizens by any means is prohibited” Article 38. Constitution of
China, adopted 4 Dec 1982. [I have relied on the translation of the constitutions mentioned hereinafter found
in: http://www.oefre.unibe.ch/law/icl/home.html].
31
See also: “The Islamic Republic is a system based on belief in: … 6) the exalted dignity and value of man,
and his freedom coupled with responsibility before God; in which equity, justice, political, economic, social,
and cultural independence, and national solidarity are secured by recourse to: a) continuous leadership of the
holy persons, possessing necessary qualifications, exercised on the basis of the Koran and the Sunnah, upon
all of whom be peace…” Article 2 [Foundational Principles]. Constitution of Iran adopted 24 Oct 1979.
32
“May the Thai people unite in observing, protecting and upholding the Constitution of the Kingdom of
Thailand in order to maintain the democratic regime of government and the sovereign power derived from the
Thai people, and to bring about happiness, prosperity, and dignity to His Majesty's subjects throughout the
Kingdom according to the will of His Majesty in every respect” Constitution of Thailand, 1997, Preamble.
33
“No person shall expose the King to any sort of accusation or action” Article 8, Ibid.
9
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
for rights and duties themselves. Yet, the precise balance between them is a consequence of
cultural and ideological factors.
D: Honor and Dignity
Apart from rights and duties, other norms that are related to human dignified
existence are derived from the basic premises about human moral worth and are grasped
within a wide moral view. Among these norms, honor is included. In Hebrew, for instance,
the word Kavod entails three meanings: dignity, honor and respect.
34
But English also has
the connotation of dignity in the meaning of respect and honor, as when using the
expression to dignify or dignified to describe certain acts and practices. This linguistic
semblance stresses the strong connection between honor and dignity and it can be traced
back as to the word Dignitas in ancient Rome, where and when it “connotes a certain
position in the social context”, worthiness for an office of counsel (dignitas consularis),
suitability or fame (Rotenstreich, 1983: 11-12). With the downfall of the old social
hierarchies, a linguistic change occurred in the linguistic application of the concept of
dignity and it was separated from its old hierarchical meanings in favor of more
universalistic meanings (Taylor, 1992: 25-51).
Honor is a social-appreciation given to moral conducts, achievements and
characteristics that are considered worthy by the relevant group, and this appreciation is
expressed and conditioned by a certain attitude of society.
35
For example, a young man or
woman that makes room for an old person in a public bus will probably gain recognition
(whether explicit or implicit) from other passengers on that bus; otherwise, they might be
condemned for refusing to do so themselves. A successful firm manager will gain
appreciation (in different possible ways) for his traits and achievements that have brought
him to this social status; an excellent sportswoman will earn appreciation on sports
achievements in her field by granting her medals and trophies; an artist will be appreciated
when her works of art are displayed in public; and a minister or parliament member will be
admired for holding a high social and political rank.
36
In other words, honor is another
echelon that dictates what is a dignified and undignified, a moral and immoral conduct
within the thick meaning of human dignity. Honor is constructed upon the rights and duties
34
See also Orit Kamir’s (2002) recent linguistic and conceptual analysis.
35
Honor requires social relations between humans, because without the attitude of the public towards the
honorable man or woman, without this honor demonstrated in some way, honor does not exist – namely,
honor is fully conditioned by appraisals of others to the honorable (Luria, 1994: 166); and compare: “The
Value, or Worth of a man is, as of all other things, his Price; that is to say, so much as would be given for the
use of his Power: and therefore is not absolute; but a thing dependent on the need and judgement of another.
An able conductor of Souldiers, is of great Price in time of War present, or imminent; but in Peace not so. A
learned and uncorrupt Judge, is much Worth in time of Peace, but not so much in war. And as in other things,
so in men, not the seller, but the buyer determines the Price. For let a man (as most men do,) rate themselves
at the highest Value they can; yet their true Value is no more than it is esteemed by others” (Hobbes, 1996: 63
original emphasis).
36
Also Compare: “The publique worth of a man, which is the Value set on him by the Common-wealth, is
that which men commonly call DIGNITY. And this Value of him by the Common-wealth is understood, by
offices of Command, Judicature, publike Employment; or by Names and Titles, introduced for distinction of
such Value” (Hobbes, 1996: 63-64).
10
Global Jurist Topics , Vol. 3 [2003], Iss. 3, Art. 3
http://www.bepress.com/gj/topics/vol3/iss3/art3
echelon by the latter being more fundamental to human existence than the former.
However, this distinction is not meant to separate sharply between the two interrelated
echelons, since an affront to one’s honor is usually expressed in the rights and duties’
parlance. For example, insulting a person in public has been compared in Judaism to the
spilling of one’s blood. Rather, it marks two distinct areas of morals that are contained
within the thick meaning of human dignity.
Honor is comprehended differently in a cross-cultural or chronological perspective,
just as we have seen in the case of rights and duties. A person married to several women in
a particular culture and takes care of their needs might gain great honor in a society that
recognizes and values polygamy, but not necessarily (and sometimes necessarily not) in
other societies and cultures. Alternatively, a society that once valued polygamy or approved
of the slavery-institution might very well condemn them in some other point in time.
Furthermore, a society that esteems the value of individual autonomy will honor certain
actions that promote this value: material aid, education for one’s rights and fighting for
them. Yet in another aspect, religious and traditional societies might think that certain
material aids (such as television), education for woman’s rights and boisterously
demanding religious freedom, are actions without honor and even as a real insult to human
dignity according to their worldview.
37
In other words, honor is culturally relative since it is
defined by the thick meaning of human dignity, which stems from different cultural
contexts.
The Wide Moral View
The two meanings of human dignity just described, rights and duties, and honor, are
contained in a wide moral view that is destined to create harmony between the particular
cultural understanding regarding human inherent moral worth and one’s proper social
relations with fellow humans.
38
This is an upward ambitious moral view (metaphorically
and positively speaking), for its end (telos), to use an Aristotelian manner of speaking, is to
create harmony between the essential characteristics entailed in fact that the human being is
a social animal in nature, and the social-political order that would assist in epitomizing the
good human virtue in an optimal way – just as physical and climatic conditions are required
for the end of making a seed become a blossoming and fruitful tree.
39
Put differently, the
37
For the possible contradiction between claiming rights and human dignity see: “However, every time a
person claims his rights this activity is not expressive of his dignity. Claiming one’s rights might be unrelated
to expressing dignity or even, in extreme cases, antithetical to the expression of human dignity. Someone
might conceivably claim his rights in a very undignified way. He might be too pushy about his rights or he
might claim some rights insincerely, not really believing that they were his but still hoping to get the benefit
of the display” (Meyer, 1989: 524).
38
Daniel Statman defines the wide moral outlook as “dignity as a moral attitude”. According to Statman,
every immoral behavior is contained within dignity as a moral attitude (2001, 544).
39
Aristotle in the Nicomachean Ethics distinguishes between the ultimate end (telos) which is happiness, and
honor. Aristotle posits that some people confuse honor (which is what politicians strive for and is conditioned
by those honoring the honored) with the quality of the person whose virtue is not conditioned by others, but is
inherent in him. Compare: “People of quality, for their part, those who tend towards a life of action, go for
honour; for pretty much this is the end of the political life. But it appears more superficial than what we are
looking for, as it seems to be located in those doing the honouring rather than in the person receiving it, and
11
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
wide moral view stems from basic premises about human moral worth, and aims at
promoting humans towards a state of harmony between these basic premises and the proper
social-political relations that ought to exist. Yet, as the wide moral view is directed
upwards, there is a third element within the thick meaning of human dignity that is included
in a narrow moral view that is directed downwards, and this aspect will be discussed in the
following analysis.
E: The Thin Meaning of Human Dignity
The thin meaning of human dignity is a third discrete component of the thick
meaning of human dignity. This component corresponds to a prevalent linguistic function
with the concept of human dignity that connotes a meaning related to humiliation and
diminution of human worth. The use of human dignity within the thin linguistic sphere
indicates a behavior that is not in line with the premises about human worth. Such behavior
is comprehended in terms of humiliation and as a conduct that is blatantly incommensurate
with the basic assumption about human moral worth.
40
Whereas rights and duties, and
honor, are contained within the upward wide moral view that is meant to harmonize human
moral worth and one’s proper social-political relation with other human beings, the thin
meaning is contained within a thin moral view that is focused on the crude violation of that
basic moral worth. In other words, with regard to behavior that is not honorable or that
hinders rights and duties, the thin meaning of human dignity is revealed in behavior and
situations that embody a breach and debasement of the very human moral foundations.
The thin meaning of human dignity is not susceptible to a precise definition by a list
of concrete immoral conducts; yet, when such a humiliating or degrading conduct occurs, it
is intuitively perceived by the humiliated person and those who share his feelings.
41
In this
way, for example, Victor Frankl in his Man’s Search for Meaning describes the
humiliations that he has endured in the concentration camps during the Holocaust:
The pain he caused me was not from any insults or any blows. That guard did
not think it worth his while to say anything, not even a swear word, to the
ragged, emaciated figure standing before him, which probably reminded him
only vaguely of a human form. Instead, he playfully picked up a stone and
threw it at me. That, to me, seemed the way to attract the attention of a beast,
to call a domestic animal back to its job, a creature with which you have so
little in common that you do not even punish it (1984, 36).
our hunch is that the good is something that belongs to a person and is difficult to take away from him…So it
is clear, at any rate according to them, that excellence is of greater value. In fact, perhaps one might suppose
that this is even more the end of the political life than honour is” (1095b21-1095b31).
40
The thin meaning of human dignity with relation to humiliation is demonstrated both linguistically and
conceptually in Statman’s articles (2001, 2002).
41
Its [human dignity] intrinsic meaning has been left to intuitive understanding, conditioned in large
measures by cultural factors. When it has been evoked in concrete situations, it has been generally assumed
that a violation of human dignity can be recognized even if the abstract term cannot be defined. ‘I know it
when I see it even if I cannot tell you what it is’ ” (Schachter, 1983: 849 – emphasis mine).
12
Global Jurist Topics , Vol. 3 [2003], Iss. 3, Art. 3
http://www.bepress.com/gj/topics/vol3/iss3/art3
The majority of prisoners suffered from a kind of inferiority complexes. We
had all once been or had fancied ourselves to be “somebody.” Now we were
treated like complete nonentities. (The consciousness of one’s inner value is
anchored in higher, more spiritual things, and cannot be shaken by camp life.
But how many free man, let alone prisoners, posses it?) Without consciously
thinking about it, the average prisoner felt himself utterly degraded (Ibid, 72).
We grasp the humiliating and degrading situations that Frankl suffered intuitively
and, hence, immediately understand the blatant lack of morality they are imbedded-in due
to the sharp contradiction between the humiliating situation and the most fundamental
human values on which we were educated and brought up. Not in every event that a person
throws a stone on another person do we perceive this to be an offence to the latter’s most
basic human existence; yet, when this action is accompanied by an attitude that is not even
appropriate towards animals, we regard this as an offence to human dignity, as we refer to
the thin meaning of the term.
42
Similarly to the thick meaning of human dignity, the thin meaning is neither static
nor universal. Certain behavior and conducts that were customary in the past are subjected
to historical and cultural changes and, therefore, are weighted differently in different places
and points in time. The slavery institution, to take a salient example, was widespread
throughout the centuries, starting with the ancient civilizations of Mesopotamia, India,
China, Greece, through the black slaves in Africa and the white slaves (Mamluks) in
medieval Islam and ending with the slaves brought to North and South America. Only in
the 19
th
century was there a substantial effective resistance to the established slavery
institution and it was gradually perceived as immoral. This understanding culminated in the
20
th
century to be regarded as a severe breach of human dignity, and concrete national and
international measures were taken for its abolition (Frowein, 2002: 122).
43
42
Frankl’s feelings that he has been treated like an animal lacking human dignity is a recurring theme in his
book: “A man’s character became involved to the point that he was caught in a mental turmoil which
threatened all the values he held and threw them into doubt. Under the influence of a world which no longer
recognized the value of human life and human dignity, which had robbed man of his will and had made him
an object to be exterminated (having planned, however, to make full use of him first – to the last ounce of his
physical resources) – under this influence the personal ego finally suffered a loss of values. If the man in the
concentration camp did not struggle against this in the last effort to save his self-respect, he lost the feeling of
being an individual, a being with a mind, with inner freedom and personal value. He thought of himself then
as only a part of an enormous mass of people; his existence descended to the level of animal life. The men
were herded – sometimes to one place then to another; sometimes driven together, then apart – like a flock of
sheep without thought or a will of their own” (Frankl, 1984: 60).
43
Unfortunately, slavery still exists in some parts of the world (like in parts of Africa). Compare: “Mindful
that the peoples of the United Nations reaffirmed in the Charter their faith in the dignity and worth of the
human person; Considering that the Universal Declaration of Human Rightsstates that no one shall be held
in slavery or servitude and that slavery and the slave trade shall be prohibited in all their forms; … Being
aware, however, that slavery, the slave trade and institutions and practices similar to slavery have not yet been
eliminated in all parts of the world; Having decided, therefore, that the Convention of 1926, which remains
operative, should now be augmented by the conclusion of a supplementary convention designed to intensify
national as well as international efforts towards the abolition of slavery, the slave trade and institutions and
practices similar to slaverySupplementary Convention on the Abolition of Slavery, the Slave Trade and
Institutions and Practices Similar to Slavery, adopted on 7 September 1956, Preamble (emphasis mine).
13
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
A further moral development can be seen in the case of suffrage. Despite the lack of
an equal and general democratic voting right in most places in the world until the mid 20
th
century, this was not necessarily perceived as a humiliation or degrading conduct of the
citizens lacking this right such as women, blacks in America and minorities; yet nowadays,
in liberal-democratic states at least, the denial of equal suffrage on the basis of sex, race,
religion or any other distinction not based on good enough reasons is considered a profound
offence to human dignity.
The reason that the thin meaning of human dignity is subjected to change or, put
differently, that humiliation is not static or universal, is due to the fact that the thin meaning
is dictated and encapsulated by the thick meaning of human dignity.
44
Hence, changes in
the thick meaning will probably entail changes in our understanding of the thin meaning as
well, namely, our conception of what humiliation means. The social and historical
developments emphasize how worldviews have gradually changed from a point in which a
certain norm, to take slavery again, that was considered permitted and even perceived as a
sign of honor by slave owners, has become a conduct without honor, until it was finally
regarded as an immoral, degrading and humiliating conduct forbidden by national and
international law.
As a result of the changes in the moral outlook of people in particular and societies
in large concerning the acceptable and desirable moral behavior that stem from human
dignity, social-political conflicts arise between societies or between different groups that
comprise the same society. Such conflicts occur when changes in the moral consciousness
of one group generate tensions with the moral consciousness of another group. This change
can be formed, for instance, when social and historical processes cause one group to
perceive (or to strengthen their perception of) the existing social order as a blatant injustice
lacking moral justification, until the point they perceive this social order as inflicting severe
humiliation on their most basic human worth.
A significant example for the last point can be seen in the struggle of the Civil
Rights Movement in the United States under the leadership of Martin Luther King. The
blacks in America were probably never satisfied with their political, social and economic
status, yet only in the mid-twentieth century did a critical mass of black citizens start seeing
this status as intolerable and as an insult to their equal worth and dignity as humans. Their
rights prescribed by law were not respected and they suffered severe daily humiliations
upon their dignity, as described in Martin Luther King’s Letter from Birmingham City Jail.
[…] when you take a cross-county drive and find it necessary to sleep
night after night in the uncomfortable corners of your automobile because
no motel will accept you; when you are humiliated day in and day out by
nagging signs reading "white" and "colored"; when your first name
becomes "nigger," your middle name becomes "boy" (however old you
are) and your last name becomes "John," and your wife and mother are
44
Cf.: “minimalist meanings are embedded in the maximal morality, expressed in the same idiom, sharing the
same (historical/cultural/religious/political) orientation. Minimalism is liberated from its embeddedness and
appears independent, in varying degrees of thinness, only in the course of a personal or social crisis or a
political confrontation…” (Walzer, 1994: 3).
14
Global Jurist Topics , Vol. 3 [2003], Iss. 3, Art. 3
http://www.bepress.com/gj/topics/vol3/iss3/art3
never given the respected title "Mrs."; when you are harried by day and
haunted by night by the fact that you are a Negro, living constantly at
tiptoe stance, never quite knowing what to expect next, and are plagued
with inner fears and outer resentments; when you are forever fighting a
degenerating sense of "nobodiness", then you will understand why we
find it difficult to wait (King, 1963: 293 – emphasis added).
I had hoped that the white moderate would understand that the present
tension in the South is a necessary phase of the transition from an
obnoxious negative peace, in which the Negro passively accepted his
unjust plight, to a substantive and positive peace, in which all men will
respect the dignity and worth of human personality (Ibid, 295 –
emphasis added).
King described the humiliating attitude towards the blacks as distorting their human
personalities by instilling in them a sense of “nobodiness” similar to Frankl’s feeling that he
and his prisoner friends were treated like “nonentities”. This attitude toward the blacks was
not worse in comparison to their conditions in previous centuries in America, yet it was due
to some improvement in their conditions and social status that the blacks could now see the
salient contradiction between their wretched social conditions and the American values of
freedom, equality and justice. In other words, the blacks now saw the racial separation in
public transportation, restaurants, education (and much more) not only as a lack of due
social respect or honor, but as concrete humiliation of their human dignity. Of course, not
all Americans saw eye to eye with the blacks’ struggle for basic human recognition at that
time; and, unfortunately, there were some who probably did not see anything wrong with
that situation. But nowadays, it is perfectly clear that the sort of segregation and attitude
under which blacks were until the sixties of the 20
th
century were morally defective and
stood in contrast to human dignity in the most fundamental way. Changes in the moral
outlook in the United States (in general) have turned legitimate conducts of the past to
evidently immoral conducts at present and the very thought of them upsets our moral
conscience today.
45
Unlike the case of the Civil Rights Movement in America, other moral conflicts are
not that clear or easy to resolve. As aforesaid, the thick meaning of human dignity as a
moral worldview dictates what the thin meaning is. Hence, in a comparative perspective,
one can observe that a part of one society’s cultural heritage can seem to another as an
offence and humiliation to human dignity. For example, a female might loose her life for
violating the honor of the family in light of the high value ascribed to the honor of the
family in some Bedouin and Moslem societies. Moreover, in large parts of Africa and in
small communities in other parts of the world, a large number of little girls are circumcised
(sometimes forcefully) by their families and it is estimated that more than 135 million girls
and women around the world have had female genital mutilation.
46
These unfortunate
45
Compare also to Henkin at footnote no. 23.
46
For the different traditional and other reasons for this practice and its scope see Amnesty International’s
Female Genital Mutilation: A Human Rights Information Pack (AI Index: ACT 77/05/97) found on the
Internet: http://www.amnesty.org/ailib/intcam/femgen/fgm1.htm#a7.
15
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
examples stem first and foremost from traditional, religious and cultural worldviews that
assume hierarchal relations between woman and man. Of course, we should stick with our
moral convictions believing that these practices should be prohibited and vanished; yet, one
should acknowledge that their existence is not due to pure evil or a deliberate offence to
human dignity, but an outcome of a different cultural perspective.
Things get even more complicated once the conflict concerning human dignity is
among groups that comprise the same society. Heterogeneous societies might find
themselves in confrontation regarding different conceptions and interpretations of human
dignity and the appropriate conducts that pertain to it. Put differently, what seems to one
group as expressing human worth and dignity – like in the case of polygamy, abortion,
euthanasia and more – might seem as an affront in the eyes of the other.
Conclusion
Human dignity is a moral-philosophical term that has several levels of meanings,
which correspond to different linguistic functions. The thick meaning of human dignity is a
moral worldview that contains a particular cultural understanding of human moral worth
and of his or her proper relations with society. The kernel of the thick meaning is composed
of basic assumptions about human worth that one is brought up on and they become basic
moral premises in one’s consciousness. Out of this kernel sprouts a narrow moral view that
embraces and defines the thin meaning of human dignity, which can be compared to roots
planted deep in the soil. The parlance about conducts and attitudes that endanger these routs
of humanity are bound with terms of humiliating and degrading human worth and dignity.
Furthermore, from these very basic assumptions about human worth emerge a wide moral
view that embraces and defines two more components of human dignity: rights and duties,
and honor. Rights and duties stem from the moral kernel and unite into a solid trunk of a
tree that is the main echelon in creating harmony between a human’s basic worth and his or
her proper relations with society. Honor is like normative branches that grow parallel to the
making of the trunk and on top of it, while in the process of growing, some branches
thicken and become an integral part of the trunk.
The three parts of the tree resemble the normative hierarchy between the three
meanings of human dignity inside the thick meaning: the thick meaning is the whole tree.
This becomes clear by mapping the damage onto each echelon. When one offends one of
the tree branches, i.e. the honor, the tree is naturally hurt. Yet, this does not endanger the
existence of the whole tree. When the trunk of the tree, the rights and duties, is hurt, this
might result in a severe damage to the tree, since there is not much point in honor when
more basic elements of human existence (that support honor) are jeopardized. However,
when the roots of the tree – namely, the thin meaning of human dignity – are hurt or
threatened, the whole existence of the tree as a tree and the human as a human is in danger.
This distinction is not a dichotomic one, for rights and duties are not absolute and
they should frequently be balanced with one another and with other important values, and
also because an offence to honor in certain circumstances can be equivalent to an offence in
the thin meaning of human dignity, that is, as a humiliation to his basic human worth. In
other words, identifying an offence to human dignity by the different levels just presented
is context dependent and requires the consideration of cultural and subcultural aspects.
16
Global Jurist Topics , Vol. 3 [2003], Iss. 3, Art. 3
http://www.bepress.com/gj/topics/vol3/iss3/art3
Hence, this model is not meant to sharply separate these interrelated components. But in
any event, whereas many conflicts and offences are uttered in different language spheres as
offences to human dignity, the analysis in this paper, I believe, helps to identify and clarify
the relevant normative echelon that is referred to.
There is great beauty in the fact that human dignity has become so prevalent in
modern moral discourse. Yet, as Nathan Rotenstreich argues, “precisely because the idea
has become so current, the justification behind it and its particular meaning has become
rather blurred, vague, or even ambiguous” (1983, 9). Rotenstreich posits that the notion of
human dignity is “rather eclectic” and that it “assumes different types of justification and
presentation which have evolved in the course of philosophical thinking. But above all it is
an expression, perhaps the most prominent in the history of man’s self-reflection, of self-
evaluation” (Ibid). It is the contention of this paper to provide a conceptual map for the
eclectic idea of human dignity and to indicate that a variety of thick self-evaluation
conceptions of human dignity exists. But, following Wittgenstein’s warning of assuming
there is a “final analysis of our forms of language” and “a single completely resolved form
of every expression” (passage 91 – original emphasis), I do not argue this to be a final
model or map for this ambiguous notion, but rather a flexible one that helps one to discern
the different linguistic functions of the concept and its interrelated meanings as they have
become crystallized by this present time.
The recurrent linguistic use of human dignity in moral, political, philosophical and
other discourses stresses our refined moral sense concerning human behavior. Especially in
liberal-democracies, human dignity is inseparably understood as granting all citizens equal
rights without any sort of discrimination. However, it seems apparent at this point in time
that liberal democracies have transcended this understanding of human dignity. Charles
Taylor has observed that “with the move from honor to dignity has come a politics of
universalism, emphasizing the equal dignity of all citizens, and the contents of this politics
has been the equalization of rights and entitlements” (1992, 37). This social-historical move
has generated two tendencies in politics: the politics of equal dignity and the politics of
difference. “With the politics of equal dignity, what is established is meant to be universally
the same, an identical basket of rights and immunities; with the politics of difference, what
we are asked to recognize is the unique identity of this individual or group, their
distinctness from everyone else” (Ibid, 38). In fact, the politics of difference are themselves
part of the politics of dignity, only instead of demanding equal rights and treatment, they
demand recognition in their distinctness and unique identity. Thus, we paradoxically have a
modern Roman version of Dignitas today, whereby dignity means treating one not merely
as an equal but, rather, recognizing one’s values or group uniqueness.
It is interesting to note that nowadays it is simply not enough to give an identical
treatment and the same parcel of rights to all people. Not recognizing someone’s particular
identity or culture might be regarded as “a form of oppression, imprisoning someone in a
false, distorted, and reduced mode of being” (Ibid, 25). Remarkably, this type of
misrecognition of others is voiced today similarly to the way Martin Luther King talked
about his sense of “nobodiness” and Victor Frankl’s sense of “nonentity”. Of course, these
situations differ considerably and cannot be compared; nevertheless, one can observe that
nowadays, a lack of due recognition is also seen and uttered in the thin meaning of human
dignity.
17
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
In most cases, these demands are probably not just empty words: they reflect
authentic feelings of underprivileged groups; but it should be noted that not every lack of
recognition is an insult or humiliation to human dignity in its thin meaning. Most of the
conflicts inside liberal-democratic societies today are indeed between equal people who
consider each other as such. Yet, it seems that too many conflicts in politics, which find
their way into the justice halls, are actually about (social) honor – although what some
contenders seem to argue for is an offence to their basic (thin) dignity. People and
representatives of minority groups want not only to be symbolically recognized as equal in
dignity and worth by the dead letter of written law; they want to be actually and vividly
recognized as special humans with a particular worth by their fellow human beings,
especially those who speak their language and share their history. I hope this paper helps to
clarify the vagueness surrounding the concept of human dignity and the recurrent appeals to
it, and by so to enable human dignity to remain a unifying concept rather than letting it
become a controversial one.
18
Global Jurist Topics , Vol. 3 [2003], Iss. 3, Art. 3
http://www.bepress.com/gj/topics/vol3/iss3/art3
Bibliography
Abdul, Aziz Said. 1979. “Human Rights in Islamic Perspectives.” in Human Rights:
Cultural and Ideological Perspectives, edited by A. Pollis and P. Schwab. New York:
Praeger.
Amnesty International. Female Genital Mutilation: A human rights information pack (AI
Index: ACT 77/05/97).
<Internet source: http://www.amnesty.org/ailib/intcam/femgen/fgm1.htm#a7>
Arieli, Yehoshua. 2002. “On the Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for the Emergence of
the Dignity of Man and His Rights.” in The Concept of Human Dignity in Human Rights
Discourse, edited by D. Kretzmer and E. Klein. Hague: Kluwer Law International.
Aristotle. 2002. Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Benjamin, Martin. 1990. Splitting the Difference: Compromise and Integrity in Ethics and
Politics. Kansas: University Press of Kansas.
Brownlie, Ian, ed. 1994. Basic Documents on Human Rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Bryder, Tom. 1994. “Patterns for Future Research on Self-Esteem and Human Dignity in
Mass Society.” Political Psychology 15(3): 401-414.
Chaskalson, Arthur. 2002. “Human Dignity as a Constitutional Value.” in The Concept of
Human Dignity in Human Rights Discourse, edited by D. Kretzmer and E. Klein. Hague:
Kluwer Law International.
Cohn, H. Haim. 1983. “On the Meaning of Human Dignity.Israel Yearbook on Human
Rights 13: 226-251.
Donnelly, Jack. 1982. “Human Rights and Human Dignity: An Analytic Critique of Non-
Western Conceptions of Human Rights.” American Political Science Review 76(2): 303-16.
Frankl, Victor. 1984. Man's Search for Meaning. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Frowein, Jochen. 2002. “Human Dignity in International Law.” in The Concept of Human
Dignity in Human Rights Discourse, edited by D. Kretzmer and E. Klein. Hague: Kluwer
Law International.
Henkin, Louis. 1989. “International Human Rights as "Rights".” in The Philosophy of
Human Rights, edited by M. Winston. Belmont: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
Henkin, Louis. 1992. “Human Dignity and Constitutional Rights.” in The Constitution of
Rights: Human Dignity and American Values, edited by M. J. Meyer and W. A. Parent.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
19
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
Hobbes, Thomas. 1996. Leviathan. (Edited by Richard Tuck). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Howard, Rhoda. 1992. “Dignity, Community, and Human Rights.” in Human Rights in
Cross-Cultural Perspective: A Request for Consensus, edited by A. A. An-Na'im.
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Howard, Rhoda and Jack Donnelly. 1986. “Human Dignity, Human Rights and Political
Regimes.” American Political Science Review 80(3): 801-817.
Iglesias, Teresa. 2001. “Bedrock Truths and the Dignity of the Individual.” Logos: 114-134.
Israel Democracy Institute. 2001. Dignity of Man in the Israel Defense Forces. Israel
Democracy Institute, Jerusalem. [in Hebrew].
Kamir, Orit. 2002. “Honor and Dignity Cultures: The Case of Kavod and Kvod Ha-Adam in
Israeli Society and Law.” in The Concept of Human Dignity in Human Rights Discourse,
edited by D. Kretzmer and E. Klein. Hague: Kluwer Law International.
King, Martin Luther. 1963. “Letter from Birmingham City Jail.” in A Testament of Hope:
The Essential Writings of Martin Luther King, Jr., edited by J. M. Washington. San
Francisco: Harper & Row. [pp. 289-302].
Kommers, Donald P. 1997. The Constitutional Jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of
Germany. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press. [chapter. 7].
Luria, Yoval. 1994. “A Matter of Dignity.” in Virtues and Feelings, edited by A. Nemdar.
Ramat Gan: Hoshen LeMishpat. [in Hebrew].
Meyer, Michael J. 1989. “Dignity, Rights, and Self-Control.” Ethics 99: 520-534.
Novak, Michael. 1998. “The Judeo-Christian Foundation of Human Dignity, Personal
Liberty, and the Concept of the Person.” Markets&Morality 1(2).
Novak, Michael. 1999. “Human Dignity, Human Rights.” First Things 97, November.
Pollis, Adamantia and Peter Schwab. 1979. Human Rights: Cultural and Ideological
Perspectives. New York: Praeger.
Rotenstreich, Nathan. 1983. Man and His Dignity. Jerusalem: Magnes Press.
Schachter, Oscar. 1983. “Human Dignity as a Normative Concept.” American Journal of
International Law 77(4): 848-854.
20
Global Jurist Topics , Vol. 3 [2003], Iss. 3, Art. 3
http://www.bepress.com/gj/topics/vol3/iss3/art3
Spiegelberg, Herbert. 1970. “Human Dignity: A Challenge to Contemporary Philosophy.
in Human Dignity: This Century and the Next, edited by R. Gotesky and E. Laszlo. New
York: Gordon and Breach.
Statman, Daniel. 2001. “Two Concepts of Dignity.” Iyyuney Mishpat 24(3): 541-603 [in
Hebrew]
Statman, Daniel. 2002. “Humiliation, Dignity and Self-Respect.” in The Concept of Human
Dignity in Human Rights Discourse, edited by D. Kretzmer and E. Klein. Hague: Kluwer
Law International.
Taylor, Charles. 1992. “The Politics of Recognition.” in Multiculturalism and "the Politics
of Recognition": An Essay, edited by A. Gutmann. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University
Press.
Ullrich, Dierk. 2003. “Concurring Visions: Human Dignity in the Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms and the Basic Law of the Federal Republic of Germany.” Global
Jurist Frontiers 3(1).
Walzer, Michael. 1994. Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad. Notre
Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1996. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.
21
Shultziner: Human Dignity
Published by The Berkeley Electronic Press, 2003
... 3 For a recent example of highly loose and unhelpful usages of human dignity to the point that the term becomes almost meaningless see Megret and Hoffmann (2009). For further discussions, critical review and illustrations of the multiple and often contradictory meanings and applications of dignity see Shultziner (2003); Bagaric and Allen (2006); Fyfe (2007); McCrudden (2008). dignity" protects individuals from humiliation and explains this overarching agreement according to social-psychological research. ...
... The drafters of the United Nation's Charter and of the different human rights instruments which have relied on "human dignity" could not have articulated a concept of dignity that was based on an agreed understanding of the term. The doctrine of human dignity was then in its infancy, and the term was employed as a compromise for varying ideologies and worldviews that had to be reconciled without compromising basic principles of belief and political interests (McCrudden, 2008;Novak, 1999;Shultziner, 2003). ...
... According to this approach, violations of human dignity are those that injure or threaten to injure a person's or a group of people's sense of worth. This could be termed the thin (or minimal) meaning of human dignity violations (Shultziner, 2003;Statman, 2000;Walzer, 1994). Violations of dignity in terms of the thin meaning are usually acts that humiliate. ...
Article
Full-text available
The concept of human dignity is a central concept in many legal systems. Yet the increasing and sometimes excessive use of this concept has generated a number of serious problems which have only recently become clear in empirical research and court rulings showing that the meanings of dignity have become contradictory and can no longer advance human rights protections. This paper offers a way out of the deadlock. We offer an approach which is anchored in the psychology of the self, specifically in the human need for maintaining positive self-worth. We elaborate on what this conceptualization means in terms of violations of dignity, emphasizing dignity's antonym, humiliation, as well as other closely related aspects of social exclusion, lowering of social status, and denials of recognition more generally. We then demonstrate that this approach has in fact been applied in a range of important legal cases, often establishing constitutional precedents. We illustrate this through a comparative review and analysis of judgments from the United States Supreme Court, the European Court of Human Rights, and the Supreme Court of Israel. We argue that this psychological approach to human dignity can bring logic and consistency back into its meaning and usages.
... The concept of human dignity is becoming more and more prevalent in legal, moral, and philosophical discourses (Shultziner, 2007). Although research on the construct of dignity is examined in health and discrimination research (Jacobson, 2007), there is less research specifically examining dignity in service and management research (Wang et al., 2021). ...
... Being treated with dignity results in outcome favorability to those who experience service failures. The concept of dignity is central to discrimination research as a key variable where dignity aligns with the equal and inalienable rights of all humans (Shultziner, 2007). A key tenant in dignity is that individuals need to feel they are treated with respect, especially when it comes to service failures and recovery (Liao, 2007). ...
Article
Not all recoveries are successful. Previous research mostly focuses on employee service-recovery actions, while limited research examines how customers evaluate the interactions of employees’ diverse appearance features and their performance in service recoveries. To build upon the research gaps, this study examines the two processes of evaluation: inference-based and recognition-based evaluations. To do so, this research examines how service employees’ diversity features (e.g., gender and race) and their organizational citizenship behavior (OCB) performance influence customer evaluations of service recovery. Using a between-subjects experimental research design, the findings contribute to the diversity, service recovery, and OCB literature by adding new evidence on how recognition-based evaluations of employees’ appearances (gender and race) and inference-based evaluations of behaviors (OCB to customers) can affect customer perceptions of employee competence, trustworthiness, and dignity in service recoveries.
... In the absence of such human reactions, human dignity measurements are likely to be subject to error (Jacob 2017). Shultziner (2007) questions whether a universal standardisation of human dignity is even possible. ...
Article
Full-text available
The relationship between the judge and the parties to judicial proceedings must entail communication, including appropriate reactions, during the proceedings and be balanced and respectful, despite different views being held. Irrespective of a judge disagreeing with the parties and any actions by the parties in breach of the law, the judge is supposed to provide the parties with a genuine sense of respect. Judges thereby help realise the human dignity of the individuals involved in judicial proceedings. However, the abstract nature of the concept of human dignity means empirical research on the realisation of human dignity remains modest at the scientific level. This article builds a research framework for researching the ways in which the human dignity of an individual (more specifically, the accused person) is realised in the vertical relationships (judicial authority–individual) during criminal proceedings. In this respect, the article opens the door for future empirical research on the realisation of human dignity.
... Одні вчені розглядають гідність як статус, інші -як внутрішню цінність людської екзистенції, ще інші -як вираження характеру, а деякі взагалі заперечують її як безпідставну вигадку (Майкл Розен [346]). Найбільш скептично зорієнтовані дослідники вважають, що неоднозначність розуміння людської гідності пояснюється її концептуальною невизначеністю, тому без певного окреслення свого змісту вона не може слугувати нормативним концептом для етичних обговорень (Стівен Пінкер [343], Дорон Шульцінер [350]). Зауважимо, що саме такий підхід підводив окремих вчених до висновку, що змістове навантаження терміна «людська гідність» визначається культурним дискурсом та політичним режимом, а тому є культурно і соціально зумовленим (Рода Говард, Джек Донелі [306; 305]). ...
Book
Full-text available
У монографії розкриваються основні тенденції розвитку ідеї гідності в історії європейської філософії від Античності до Модерну: її витоки, особливості розуміння та значення в історико-філософському процесі. Виокремлюється інваріантний та варіативний зміст цієї ідеї, ступінь її впливу на становлення європейської цивілізації. Монографія адресована фахівцям з історії філософії, етики, філософської антропології, соціальної філософії, філософії історії, філософії права, соціології; студентам, аспірантам, усім, хто цікавиться ідеєю гідності та її значенням в бутті людини та суспільства.
... Relational dignity is a normative and practical concept emphasizing that one's dignity is relational to or interdependent on the dignity of those beings (human and non-human) sharing life in the same environment. Relational dignity values dignity as an intrinsic worth inherent in human beings (Beyleveld and Brownsword 1998;Arieli 2002;Cancik 2002;Starck 2002;Shultziner 2003). It is inalienable and unconditional (Dicke 2002), but also interdependently relational to the dignity of those whom human beings relate to and share life for co-existence, co-creating, and mutual advancement. ...
Article
Full-text available
Religion and dignity are a two-sided coin for followers of Indigenous Religions in Indonesia. Dignity is the relationally inherent worth in both human and non-human beings. To give and receive dignity, one ought to be religious, which is to engage in interpersonal relationships with all beings, human and non-human. This article draws on data from two decades of engagement with followers of Indigenous Religions through extensive fieldwork, activism, and community service. It explores the distinctive worldviews and practices of Indonesian Indigenous Peoples, which many have maintained in the face of external incursions by governments, corporations, and missionaries, and internal encroachments from within their communities. Their worldviews spring from interrelational cosmology, which posits that relational dignity is a religious norm. This cosmology is institutionalized with adat (customary) systems that enact and reproduce relational dignity. The article concludes with a call to better understand and recognize Indigenous Religions by expanding the definition of religion to include the notion of relational dignity when considering how scholars and policymakers conceptualize and implement policies on freedom of religion or belief.
... J. Rawls navodi da je upravo ljudsko dostojanstvo koncept oko kojega postoji vjerojatno najveći stupanj konsenzusa unutar zapadne kulture, a vjerojatno i šire (Rawls, 1999) te se prepoznaje kao univerzalno dobro (Schachter, 1983). Druga koncepcija dostojanstvo razmatra kao vrlinu osobe koju je zavrijedila svojim osobinama i djelovanjem u socijalnom kontekstu (Shultziner, 2003). Ponekad se navode primjeri osoba koje predstavljaju uzore kao što su M. Gandhi ili M. Luther King (Meyer, 2002). ...
Chapter
Full-text available
This work derives a right to access to personality development through parenthood, taking into account aspects of sociology of law and comparative law, as well as the state of discussion in moral and legal philosophy; and thus, defines new standards for the European human rights protection scheme and the fundamental rights protection of the German constitution. This refers to the right to form and develop one's own personality through the relationship with a child - as an integral part of one's identity. Based on this, the work examines the implications for a reorganization of German law on reproductive medicine and outlines the necessary consequential changes in family law.
Article
Full-text available
The concept of equality was not mandatory. The Holy Quran, a complete guide for Muslims, provides clear protection in the areas of marriage, divorce, and inheritance. This is a significant improvement over the situation of women in pre-Islamic societies where women were the burden of the family and women were the burden. Buried alive. Nevertheless, historical circumstances have often put Muslim women at a disadvantage for centuries. Pervasive traditions of male authority and honor make it difficult for women to claim the rights guaranteed in the Quran. Numerous reforms have taken place in this century to improve educational opportunities and promote the emancipation of women in general. However, certain patterns of difficulty still dominate, such as key issues, such as employment and political activity, or issues considered divisive. Western countries viewed Muslim women as "progress" and "problem" problems, pointing to clear inequalities in the relative status of men and women. This study argues that the relationship between women and men is largely incomprehensible unless one tries to examine it from an Islamic perspective. The Quran lists men as protectors of women, and women's justice is defined by their obedience to them. A major theme of modern Islamic scriptures is that women hold power through their innate qualities and traits and have well-defined roles in any society, preserving the roles assigned to men. This is well-explained and expressed for both men and women. Owing to the
Preprint
Full-text available
The first part of the chapter will uncover the plurality of meanings of the notion of human dignity expanded after World War II in legal philosophy to sketch a typology of six notions of human dignity. Considering human dignity´s multivocal features, I outline a typology of notions of human dignity as a convenient tool for unveiling the different usages of human dignity in the jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR). This controversial term has been invoked by both parties in front of the Court, dissenting judges of the Court, third parties, or national authorities in the framework of the margin appreciation doctrine. Since analyzing the vast number of Strasbourg´s cases concerning human dignity is arduous, I have selected key cases in which human dignity has played a significant role in elucidating the current trends in the so-called “dignity cases.”
Article
It is regularly argued that human rights are not a Western discovery and that non-Western societies have long emphasized the protection of human rights. Such claims, however, are based on a confusion of human rights and human dignity. A concern for human dignity is central to non-Western cultural traditions, whereas human rights, in the sense in which Westerners understand that term—namely, rights (entitlements) held simply by virtue of being a human being—are quite foreign to, for example, Islamic, African, Chinese, and Indian approaches to human dignity. Human rights are but one way that has been devised to realize and to protect human dignity. Although the idea of human rights was first articulated in the West in modern times, it would appear to be an approach particularly suited to contemporary social, political, and economic conditions, and thus of widespread contemporary relevance both in the West and the Third World. © 1982, American Political Science Association. All rights reserved.