ArticlePDF AvailableLiterature Review

Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation

Authors:
  • Instituto de Filosofía y Ciencias de la Complejidad

Abstract and Figures

The concept of autopoiesis was proposed 40 years ago as a definition of a living being, with the aim of providing a unifying concept for biology. The concept has also been extended to the theory of knowledge and to different areas of the social and behavioral sciences. Given some ambiguities of the original definitions of autopoiesis, the concept has been criticized and has been interpreted in diverse and even contradictory ways, which has prevented its integration into the biological sciences where it originated. Here I present a critical review and conceptual analysis of the definition of autopoiesis, and propose a new definition that is more precise, clear, and concise than the original ones. I argue that the difficulty in understanding the term lies in its refined conceptual subtlety and not, as has been claimed by some authors, because it is a vacuous, trivial or very complex concept. I also relate the concept of autopoiesis to the concepts of closed systems, boundaries, homeostasis, self-reproduction, causal circularity, organization and multicellularity. I show that under my proposed definition the concept of a molecular autopoietic system is a good demarcation criterion of a living being, allowing its general integration into the biological sciences and enhancing its interdisciplinary use.
Content may be subject to copyright.
ORIGIN OF LIFE
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review
and a Reformulation
Pablo Razeto-Barry
Received: 31 May 2012 /Accepted: 9 September 2012
#Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012
Abstract The concept of autopoiesis was proposed 40 years ago as a definition of a living
being, with the aim of providing a unifying concept for biology. The concept has also been
extended to the theory of knowledge and to different areas of the social and behavioral
sciences. Given some ambiguities of the original definitions of autopoiesis, the concept has
been criticized and has been interpreted in diverse and even contradictory ways, which has
prevented its integration into the biological sciences where it originated. Here I present a
critical review and conceptual analysis of the definition of autopoiesis, and propose a new
definition that is more precise, clear, and concise than the original ones. I argue that the
difficulty in understanding the term lies in its refined conceptual subtlety and not, as has
been claimed by some authors, because it is a vacuous, trivial or very complex concept. I
also relate the concept of autopoiesis to the concepts of closed systems, boundaries,
homeostasis, self-reproduction, causal circularity, organization and multicellularity. I show
that under my proposed definition the concept of a molecular autopoietic system is a good
demarcation criterion of a living being, allowing its general integration into the biological
sciences and enhancing its interdisciplinary use.
Keywords Autopoiesis .Definition of life .Individual identity .Physical proximity .Self-
reproduction .Circular causality
Introduction
The search for a definition of life or of a living being has been recurrent in biological
thinking, and has acquired a renovated interest due to the appearance of research programs
related to artificial life, the origin of life and astrobiology (reviewed in Popa 2004). The
Orig Life Evol Biosph
DOI 10.1007/s11084-012-9297-y
P. Razeto-Barry (*)
Instituto de Filosofía y Ciencias de la Complejidad, IFICC, Los Alerces 3024, Santiago, Chile
e-mail: prazeto@ificc.cl
P. Razeto-Barry
Universidad Diego Portales, Vicerrectoría Académica, Manuel Rodríguez Sur 415, Santiago, Chile
Chilean biologists Humberto Maturana and Francisco Varela (1973;1980) proposed that the
minimal definition of a living being may be based on only one property, which they called
autopoiesis. This contrasts sharply with other definitions, which are based on the combina-
tion of several properties (e.g., Koshland 2002; Popa 2004, pp. 67).
1
Autopoiesis also
contrasts with other definitions by being a relational property (also referred to as systemic,
functionalist, formalist or universalist). Its relational character is due to the fact that it does
not depend directly on the nature (type, intrinsic properties) of the components of those
entities which have the property, but rather depends only upon the relations between the
components. Because of this, the concept connects to more general areas of research which
have attempted to describe diverse types of systems in relational terms, such as tektology
(Bogdanov 1996 [1922], Gorelik 1975,1984;Dudley1996), general systems theory
(Bertalanffy 1950,1968; Rapoport 1972), cybernetics (Wiener 1948; Ashby 1957; Varela
and Maturana 1972), relational biology (Rashevsky 1954;Rosen1958,1959,1991),
information theory (Shannon 1948; Shannon and Weaver 1949; Avery 2003) and the recent
research areas of complex systems (Kauffman 1989,1993; Ruthen 1993; Bak 1996; Reason
and Goodwin 1999; Gisiger 2001; Wolfram 2002; Bedau 2003,2008), systems biology and
synthetic biology (Wolkenhauer 2001; Breitling 2010).
The heuristic value and the advantages of relational definitions and descriptions of living
beings are prominent in the research on artificial life, astrobiology and the origin of life (Dix
1983, Fleischaker and Margulis 1986;Emmeche1992; Kauffman 2001;Popa2004;
McMullin 2004; Luisi 2006). One reason for this is that a definition of a living being that
does not depend on the type of components which constitute the system would in principle
account for remote living beings close to the origin of lifewhich were possibly much
different from current forms (Reilly 2008; Wolfe-Simon et al. 2011), and for artificial life
synthesized in vitro or in silico (Langton 1989; Breitling 2010) and living beings which may
potentially exist outside Earth (Popa 2004). In all these cases the living beings may be
possibly composed of components which are very different from those of currently known
living beings (Friedman 2002; Nealson 2002). A relational definition is also attractive from a
theoretical standpoint. We normally are not willing to consider as a living being an aggregate
of components which have just any type of interrelation; for example, a paste of organic
material from a living being which has been ground or centrifuged would not usually be
considered a living being. On the other hand, it is not clear that we would in principle refuse
to consider as living beings entities which are not based on DNA, polymers or even carbon
atoms, that are the basic components of current living beings (see Reilly 2008). Thus it
seems reasonable to think that what lets us distinguish living beings as such is based more on
the nature of the relations between their components than on the nature of the components
themselves. Finally, given the amount of speculation which exists about the origin of life, the
specific pathways which originated life on Earth may be less relevant than the general
relational characteristics or family of mechanismswhich generated life (Pross 2004).
The high degree of abstraction of the concept of autopoiesis and its relational character
allowed its authors to use this property as the base for a theoretical development which
connects autopoiesis with problems of epistemology, cognitive sciences (Maturana and
Varela 1972;1980;1992 [1987], Varela et al. 1991; Bitbol and Luisi 2004; Barandiaran
and Moreno 2006) and evolutionary biology (Maturana and Varela 1992 [1987], Maturana
and Mpodozis 1992,2000; Vargas 2005). The concept has also been used in environmental
sciences (Margulis 1997; Mann 1991; Sagan and Margulis 1997; Litfin 2010) and several
areas of human sciences, including business administration (Mingers 1995), psychology
1
See Ruiz-Mirazo et al. 2004 for a criticism of this kind of descriptive, check-out listdefinition
P. Razeto-Barry
(Colapinto 1985; Simon 1985; Snyder 1999) and particularly sociology (Luhmann 1986,
1995 [1984], 2007 [1997], Geyer and van der Zouwen 2001; Magalhaes and Sanchez 2009).
The impact of the concept has increased and currently, only in ISI Web of Knowledge, the
concept appears in more than 30 articles and 300 citations by year (Fig. 1). However, even
though its central objective is to understand and delimit the object of study of biology, the
concept has not managed to become a definition of living being accepted among biologists,
nor has it been incorporated in biology texts or integrated generally into biological disci-
plines. I will argue that this is due to at least two factors: first, the original definitions are
neither clear nor easy to understand; and second, the concept appears difficult to apply in
practice. I will show that neither of those factors are actual obstacles to take autopoiesis as a
general definition of living being. To do so, I will indicate the causes of this lack of clarity,
analyze the possible interpretations of the original definition of Maturana and Varela, and
propose a new, clearer and more precise definition, which I propose is the natural result of
the analysis of this concept.
Autopoiesis: A Variety of Interpretations
The interpretation of the concept of autopoiesis has been controversial (Fleischacker 1988;
Zolo 1990, Swenson 1992a,1992b; Scheper and Scheper 1996; Morán et al. 1999; Escobar
2011). To begin with, the difficult rhetoric of the authors together with their persistent
allusions to self-reference and circularity have produced skepticism and have made some
authors suspect that the concept could mean just about anything, have no meaning, be
tautological, trivial or not very scientific, which would also apply to its derivations (Zolo
1990; Munch 1992; Scheper and Scheper 1996, Swenson 1992a,1992b, Manriquez and
Fig. 1 Number of articles and citations by year published in ISI Web of Knowledge in which appear the terms
autopoiesis,autopoietic,autopoyesis,orautopoyetic.a. Articles in Science Citation Index Expanded
(SCI-EXPANDED), Social Sciences Citation Index (SSCI), and Arts and Humanities Citation Index
(AandHCI). b. Articles only in SCI-EXPANDED. c. Citations in SCI-EXPANDED, SSCI, and AandHCI.
d. Citations only in SCI-EXPANDED
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
Rothhammer 1997; Gallardo 1997; Nespolo 2003; Valenzuela 2007,2010). Others have
considered the concept to be nothing but a fancy synonym for both self-organization and
self-maintenance(Mahner and Bunge 1997, p. 144) and thus immediately discountable as a
definition of a living being, since self-organization is a property shared by many types of
non-living systems (Mahner and Bunge 1997; Pross 2004, Swenson 1992b).
At the other extreme, autopoiesis has been treated as a highly complex property, which
would explain the manifest difficulty in the attempts to formalize it and in the search for
concrete examples to illustrate the concept, even in purely formal terms. The attempts to
formalize the concept of autopoiesis have achieved highly sophisticated results, but it is not
clear in what sense these could be considered successful. A first model based on cellular
automata (Varela et al. 1974) was later corrected and invalidated by one of its authors
(McMullin and Varela 1997; McMullin 2000). A first attempt at a general formalization of
an autopoietic system using Spencer-Browns very complex calculus of indications (Varela
1979) has not produced satisfactory results (Letelier et al. 2003). Later formalizations based
in the very abstract theory of categories and Rosens (M,R) systems (Letelier et al. 2003,
2006; Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007) only recently have found a first concrete example of (M,
R) system what might be considered a formal autopoietic system (Letelier et al. 2006). This
line of investigation has gone to the extreme of claiming that autopoiesis is not computable,
that is that autopoietic systems cannot be calculated by Turing machines (Letelier et al.
2003). All this has managed to surround the concept of autopoiesis with an air of mystery, in
which it is not clear whether it is a trivial concept (which includes everything or almost
everything) or empty (which includes nothing or almost nothing), whether it is useful
scientifically, whether it is an extremely sophisticated property or is really very simple.
How can we explain such a wide range of interpretations of the concept? Here I will argue
that it is because autopoiesis is characterized by a delicate conceptual subtlety which has not
been sufficiently clear. I will show that (i) the concept has not been subject to sufficient
conceptual analysis before looking for examples or formalizations, (ii) more than one
meaning can be extracted from the definition, and these alternatives have not been clearly
distinguished nor has it been determined which is correct, and (iii) it has not been system-
atically made explicit using precise concepts and making clear their relations with other
relevant concepts for the understanding of the basic operation of living beings. I will then
attempt to remedy these failings, by analyzing the original definition proposed by the authors
and replacing it with a new definition which I feel is clearer and more concise. With this new
definition, I will analyze how the concept of autopoiesis is related to other concepts such as
closed system, boundary, homeostasis, self-reproduction, circular causality and organization.
This critical analysis pretends to come alive again the possibility to take autopoiesis as a
general and widely acceptable minimal definition of living being for biology.
Autopoiesis: A Subtle Property
Autopoiesis literally means self-productionor self-creation. The concept of autopoiesis in
the book De Máquinas y Seres Vivos (On Machines and Living Beings) written in 1972
(Maturana and Varela 1994, p. xvii) was defined explicitly, as follows:
An autopoietic machine is a machine organized as a system of processes of production of
components concatenated in such a way that they produce components which:
i). generate the processes (relations) of production which produce them through their
continual interactions and transformations, and
P. Razeto-Barry
ii). constitute the machine as a unit in physical space(Maturana and Varela 1973)
2
A good exercise for the present purpose is to read the original definition several times (if
one has sufficient patience). As immediately becomes evident, this definition is relatively
difficult and ambiguous (as is the definition of 1980, see Note 1) due to the lack of a precise
reference of some of the terms utilized, which will be indicated in italics in what follows:
that they produce components which;generate the processes (relations) of production;
that produce them by means of their continual. It is not clear whether the terms in italics
refer to the system of processes, the processes of production, to the concatenated
productsthat produce, or the concatenated componentsproduced. This may well explain
the diversity of interpretations of the concept.
Although there is ambiguity in the definition, it may be inferred that autopoiesis defines a
type of system constituted by a set of types of components (which I will call X) which, by
means of concatenated processes, produces a set of types of components (which I will call
Y). Now, what defines Y? i.e., What conditions must Yfulfill in order that a system of
production of components (X) may be considered autopoietic?
The most common interpretation (and literal in almost all the paraphrases of the original
definition
3
) is that the network of production of components produces all the components of
the network, that is, X0Y. As we shall see, this interpretation is inacceptable given known
basic aspects of living beings.
In the first place, if we understand that the components of the system(X) are all the
reactants and products of the reactions which occur in the system (that is, including its
foodand waste), then if we suppose that the system generates all the components of the
system (X0Y) we must conclude that autopoietic systems are closed systems. Thus, given
that living beings are open systems, we must reject this interpretation.
In the second place, if we consider that the components of the system(X) are all the
reactants and products of the reactions which occur in the system except its foodand
waste(supposing that there is a simple way to distinguish them in relational terms), then if
we suppose that the system generates all the components of the system (X0Y) we are faced
with two other problems. First, many (and perhaps) all known living beings need for their
maintenance elements from their surroundings which form part of their metabolic network
and which may act as coenzymes or cofactors, and, above all, which could not be distin-
guished from any other intermediate metabolites produced internally by the system. Second,
2
In Maturana and Varela (1980, p. 79) the definition was: An autopoietic machine is a machine organized
(defined as a unity) as a network of processes of production (transformation and destruction) of components
that produces the components which:
(i). through their interactions and transformations continuously regenerate and realize
the network of processes (relations) that produced them; and
(ii). constitute it (the machine) as a concrete unity in the space in which they (the compo-
nents) exist by specifying the topological domain of its realization as such a network.
3
To give a few examples (italics mine): All components of an autopoietic network are produced by other
components in the network(Capra 1996, p. 167). In this way the entire network continually makes itself.It
is produced by its components and in turn produces those components(Capra 1996, p. 98). In an Autopoietic
system, the result of any given process is the production of components that eventually would be transformed
by other processes in the network into the components of the first process.(Letelier et al. 2003, p. 266). An
autopoietic unit is a system that is capable of self-sustaining owing to an inner network of reactions that re-
generate all the systems components(Luisi 2003, p. 51). Note that, unfortunately, these definitions are not
clearly differentiated from the descriptions of closed systems. There are also more ambiguous notions as:
autopoiesismeans self-renewing”’ (Skyttner 2005, p. 60)
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
if what the system produces permanently is the same set of components of the system (X0
Y); this would imply that the system cannot suffer qualitative change over time, that is, it
may not have qualitative changes during ontogenesis (such as metamorphosis in insects,
Valenzuela 2007). Thus, given that living beings do have ontogeny and may depend upon
cofactors or metabolites from their surroundings, this second interpretation must also be
rejected. As a consequence, the classical image of M. C. Escher, much used to represent the
concept of autopoiesis, of two hands each drawing the other completely (including the
pencil) is not an acceptable representation (Fig. 2).
According to the above, we are left with only one possible interpretation, that is,
that the autopoietic system produces only a subset of the components of the system
(YX). In summary, the three characteristics of living beings; (1) they are open
systems, (2) they may require coenzymes or metabolites from the environment for
their maintenance, and (3) they may change during ontogeny, restrict the possible
interpretations of the concept of autopoiesis to one. The network does not produce all
the components of the network, only some of them. That is, the network produces a
subgroup of the components which characterize the network as a unit.
But now the obvious following question arises, what subgroup of a production
network must the network produce in order to be considered autopoietic? Given the
functional centrality which molecular biology has given to the enzymes, we might be
tempted to define an autopoietic system as a network of processes which produces
all the catalysts of the network. However, as discussed above, there are many
exceptions (coenzymes and cofactors mentioned in point (2) above) and it does not
appear to be theoretically necessary for a system to produce all the catalysts of the
network in order to be autopoietic, since if these catalysts are available in the
environment and may enter the system constantly, the system may continue to
maintain the processes of production of the network without producing all the
catalysts internally.
4
From the above I conclude that in part (i) of the original definition of autopoiesis
(Maturana and Varela 1973,1980) there is no specification which permits to demar-
cate or characterize the subgroup Ythat allows a production network to be called
autopoietic; thus it is necessary to consider seriously part (ii) of the original defini-
tion: constitutes a machine as a unit. That is, here is the only possible specification
of the subgroup Y,viz., the subgroup of components which the system must produce
to maintain the system as a unit over time. Based on the above I propose that the
only possible interpretation of the concept of autopoiesis which is not empty or
trivial, and which is consistent with basic aspects of known living beings, may be
summarized in the following short definition of autopoiesis, which I will call D1:
4
To my knowledge, no organisms have been reported to date that directly obtain a functional enzyme from its
environment, but the requirement of cofactors and coenzymes have been widely described, which are
necessary to catalysis processes. Anyway, it seems evident that if we discover that a kind of bacteria directly
obtains some functional enzymes from its environment, that would not negate that they are living beings.
Indeed, the bacterial production of enzymes was discovered much later than the discovering of bacteria, which
were considered living beings from the very beginning (Porter 1976). Note that in the model of Varela et al.
(1974) there are catalysts that are not produced by any reaction in the network. Note also that if consider
membranes as catalytic structures in the sense that they emerge unchanged from the catalyzed reaction, while
drastically increasing the reaction rate(McMullin 2000) and that the membrane of the first living beings
probably self-assembled from simple lipids synthesized in the environment (Hargreaves and Deamer 1978;
Hanczyz et al. 2003; Budin and Szostak 2011), then the first living beings on Earth would be examples of
living systems with catalysts coming from the environment.
P. Razeto-Barry
D1: An autopoietic system is a network of processes which produces all the compo-
nents whose internal production is necessary to maintain the network operating as a
unit.
Even though this definition is more clear, precise and concise than the original, it contains
some subtleties which should be clarified. Definition D1 implies that, whatever the system
be that has to produce (Y) to maintain its production network operating, it will depend on
what is available in the environment for it. Thus we cannot impose a priori what compo-
nents or types of components the network must internally produce (to maintain its produc-
tion network operating), since this will depend upon the nature of its surroundings. This may
explain the difficulty in defining autopoietic organization mathematically, since as is natural
traditional formalizations symbolize the system only based on the components of the system
(e.g., Letelier et al. 2003,2006; Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007). Under definition D1, it may
be concluded that the autopoietic organization of a system can only be formalized mathe-
matically if components of the environment of the system are included.
Autopoiesis and Molecular Autopoiesis
The 1973 definition of Maturana and Varela suffered a small but significant change in Varela
et al. (1974), which is also included in the definition of Maturana and Varela (1980) (see
Note 1). The original definition of autopoiesis makes reference to a system as a unit in
physical space; however, the later definitions refer to a unit in the space in which the
components exist(not using the word physical). This allows the authors to distinguish
between the concept of autopoiesis, which is general and abstract and could in principle be
applied to any spaceor dominion(physical or not physical); and the concept of
molecular autopoiesis,chemical autopoiesis,orautopoiesis in physical space, which
is the definition of living being as such.
5
This generated a first differentiation between the
5
Maturana and Varela usually differentiated between autopoiesis understood as the organizing principleof
living beings, and living beings as the physical realizationof autopoiesis (see Fleischacker 1988).
Fig. 2 Photograph of Drawing Hands by M. C. Escher, 1948, taken in Escher Museum, The Hague. The
usual association between autopoiesis and the drawing of two hands drawing each other is questionable as an
analogy of autopoiesis. [Photograph taken by Gabriel Razeto]
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
thinking of Maturana and Varela. For Maturana there is no restriction in the spacein which
an autopoietic system may exist (Maturana 1981), while for Varela autopoiesis applied to
non-physical domains is only metaphoric (Varela 1981).
It is the abstract (not necessarily physical) use of the concept of autopoiesis which has
been the base of its success in human sciences such as psychology and sociology, in which,
for example, the spaceof production of components is constituted by communications
(Luhmann 1986,1995 [1984], 2007 [1997], Razeto-Barry and Cienfuegos 2011; Veloz et al.
2012). For this reason I maintained the abstraction of the general concept of autopoiesis in
definition D1, without specifying the space or domain in which it is applied. Thus D1 may
also serve to make the concept more clear and precise in human sciences. However, in what
follows I will examine autopoiesis in physical space, where the concept attempts to serve as
a definition of living being, and only will comment on a few implications for extra-
biological applications of the concept (see Notes 8 and 18).
Traditionally, molecular autopoiesis has been understood as a minimal definition of a
single cell, and processes of productionsimply as chemical reactions, and thus autopoietic
systems are understood as a sub-class of collectively autocatalytic chemical reaction net-
works (McMullin 2000). As I will discuss later in this article, this is an inadequate concept of
autopoiesis for unicellular and particularly for multicellular living beings.
Autopoiesis and Boundaries
Varela followed a second line somewhat different from that of Maturana. In later works,
Varela emphasizes a particular component produced by the system, the boundary; that is, the
physical border which limits and separates the interior from the exterior of the system. The
boundary, or its cellular parallel, the external membrane of the cell, is not mentioned in the
original definitions of the concept (Maturana and Varela 1973,1980), however, appears
explicitly in the first computational examples led by Varela (Varela et al. 1974; McMullin
and Varela 1997), and are incorporated explicitly in later paraphrases and explanations of the
original definition (e.g., Varela 2000, also in Luisi et al. 1996).
Apparently for Varela the production of the boundary or external membrane from the
interior of the system is essential for autopoiesis (see also Fleischacker 1988), that is, if the
components of the membrane came from the exterior the system would not be autopoietic
(i.e., for Varela one type of element necessary for Yis the boundary component). At first
sight this makes sense; for one thing the membrane is effectively a particularly important
component which permits the maintenance of the network of component production of the
current unicellular living organisms. Also, the production of the external membrane is in
reality an important factor which allows these organisms to become established and maintain
themselves as units in space, and also in proto-cells generated in vitro (Luisi et al. 2006; Solé
et al. 2007).
Notably, this line emphasized by Varela has recently led to the artificial production of
chemical systems in the laboratory which some authors consider autopoietic. The Swiss
scientist Pier Luigi Luisi and collaborators produced synthetic membranes in the form of
spherical vessels which catalyze the production of the components of the membrane; they
grow and reproduce spontaneously as a consequence of their self-production (Zepik et al.
2001; Luisi 2006). Although self-reproductionand autopoiesis(self-production) have
been considered definitions of life in competition, the possibility of considering some kinds
of self-reproducing chemical systems as autopoietic was first suggested by Luisi and Varela
(1989, Luisi 1993). This opened the possibility of considering as autopoietic both
P. Razeto-Barry
homeostaticsystems (whose mass remains constant) and self-reproductivesystems
(whose mass grows until it spontaneously provokes reproduction) (Luisi and Varela 1989;
Luisi et al. 1996; Luisi 1993,2003,2006; Varela 2000). From the point of view of the
previous discussion, this experimental shiftwith respect to the original interpretation of
the concept (although not the definition) is acceptable and completely compatible with
definition D1.
It is worth noting that, in spite of the compatibility of D1 with the shiftof Varela, the
generation of a layer forming a physical barrier as a kind of production of a boundary is not
necessarily a universal requirement in causal terms, and thus is not a requirement of definition
D1. The idea that the production of the components of a barrier is necessary for the maintenance
of the system comes from the image of life as a cell with molecules in a liquid state dissolved in
an aqueous solvent. However, the physical state of cellular cytoplasm is viscous (Schroder
2010) and under certain circumstances might maintain its unity (and therefore its border) by
cohesion and surface tension (as does a drop of water surrounded by air). It is probable that in
the origin of the first cells on Earth the production of a membrane was by the self-assembly of
simple lipids synthesized in the environment, while the internal production of membrane
components was a derived process evolved by natural selection (Hargreaves and Deamer
1978; Hanczyz et al. 2003; Budin and Szostak 2011).
6
On the other hand, it is possible that
in the origin of life the membrane was not a limitwhich separated the interior from the
exterior of the living being, but rather the membrane itself was the living being (the membrane
would be the interior of the living being, Fig. 3).
7
It is also worth noting that the requirement of the internal production of the components
of the membrane is not a requirement of the definition itself, but rather a practical condition
imposed by the known cellular forms of living beings on Earth. According to D1, if the
system did not require a membrane to maintain itself as a cohesive unit, or if the components
of the membrane came from the environment and the system continued to produce the
subgroup of components necessary for its maintenance as a spatially discreet unit, then the
system would continue to be considered autopoietic.
It is important to mention here that the aim of the concept of autopoiesis is to characterize
aminimal definition of life. That is, a definition that includes the minimal requirements
(semantically) necessary to consider that a system is a living system. Even if studies suggest
that on Earth the proposition: all current autopoietic systems on earth produce the elements
of their membranes(and equally replacing autopoietic systemsby living beings)
probably is true, the question about the definition of autopoiesis (and of life) implies
deciding whether this proposition will be a trivial tautology guaranteed by the definition
of autopoiesis (or of living being) or a synthetic empirical result due to current observations
and predictions based on current life on the Earth. The minimal life project searches for a
minimal definition of life, that is, the definition shouldbe minimal but specific enough
(i.e., it should include just those elements that are common to all forms of life not being, in
principle, restricted to life on Earth).(Ruiz-Mirazo et al. 2004, p. 326, similarly see
Emmeche 1998). In this context it is clear that it is preferable to take the mentioned
proposition as an interesting synthetic property of known nature rather than an analytical
tautology guaranteed by definition, maintaining open the door to include other kinds of life
6
It is perhaps worth mentioning that the border of viruses is formed by proteins; however, since there is no
dynamic processes of production (metabolism) within this border, viruses cannot be considered to be
autopoietic systems.
7
I owe this last observation to Carlos Medina.
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
in the definition, together with the one in the origin of life in Earth, for which it is possible
that the mentioned proposition is not true (Hargreaves and Deamer 1978; Hanczyz et al.
2003; Budin and Szostak 2011).
In this vein, as we will see below in our discussion about multicellular living beings, as a
direct consequence of D1, a multicellular organism is an autopoietic system as such (i.e., it is
afirst-orderautopoietic system), and in it the production of a border(e.g., an epidermis
in vertebrate animals) is not precisely what maintains it as a cohesive unit.
8
Autopoiesis, Homeostasis and Self-Reproduction
The vesicles generated in the laboratory by Luisi and collaborators are autopoietic according
to definition D1, however, they are essentially self-reproductive and cannot maintain
themselves dynamically in homoeostasis (without growth or permanent reproduction).
This characteristic does not agree with the usual emphasis that Maturana and Varela gave
to the concept of autopoiesis, which is based on the maintenance (homeostasis) of the
system by means of the regeneration of elements which must necessarily disintegrate
spontaneously (Varela et al. 1974; McMullin and Varela 1997; Varela 2000; McMullin
2004). Thus from my point of view it is not necessary to include the disintegrationand
regenerationof components as an essential element in the formalization of autopoiesis, in
contrast to the original emphasis of its authors and the formal models of autopoiesis (e.g.,
Varela et al. 1974; McMullin and Varela 1997; Letelier et al. 2003,2006; Cornish-Bowden et
Fig. 3 Representation of the non-intuitive idea that the system outsideof a living system may be spatially
inside. In the origin of life metabolism may ocurr in the membranes rather than inside the space surrounded
by the vesicles. Note that Robert Hook (16351703) who discovered cells, thought that the spatial inside of
cells is not living matter (Mazzarello 1999)
8
Another advantage of not including the production of a boundary in the definition of autopoiesis is that non-
molecular autopoietic systems, as society, may be more clearly characterized as autopoietic systems. In fact,
one of the major objections to consider society autopoietic is the absence of a production of a boundary which
makes sense: These ideas are based, in my opinion, on an abuse of language. In autopoiesis, the notion of
boundary has a more or less precise meaning. When, however, the net of processes is transformed into an
interaction among people, and the cellular membrane is transformed into the limit of a human group, one
falls into an abuse, as I expressly said.(Varela 2000, see also Luisi 2003). Note that medieval cities were
defined by their boundaries (a closed defensive wall), however this kind of definition is not applicable in
modern societies.
P. Razeto-Barry
al. 2007; Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007). As a consequence, the common theoretical
contraposition between autopoiesis and self-reproduction as strictly competing ideas (e.g.,
Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007) is not necessary. Although Varela (2000; Luisi et al.
1996) admits that autopoietic systems may be in homeostasis or in growth tending to self-
replication, he systematically emphasizes the regeneration of degraded elements as an
essential factor of autopoiesis. By contrast, I propose that even though there may be
autopoietic systems which are not self-reproductive, and self-reproductive systems which
are not autopoietic, also there may perfectly well be autopoietic systems which are strictly
self-reproductive (such as the special type of self-catalytic network generated in the labora-
tory by Luisi and collaborators). That is, there may be autopoietic systems without disinte-
gration of their components, and thus in constant growth and sef-reproduction.
It should be clear that the definition D1 I propose is compatible both with systems whose
mass is maintained in homeostasis and with systems whose mass is in constant growth (auto-
catalytic and auto-reproductive networks). If the products of an auto-catalytic network
generate the conditions necessary to maintain the network as a discrete unit in space, then
the network is an autopoietic system. As a consequence, I reject the recently proposed idea
that autopoietic systems are a Robert Rosen (M,R) type of system (Letelier et al. 2003,2006;
Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007; Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007), since it is essential that
a (M,R) system have degradation and reparation.
9
It is worth noting that no one has yet
generated in the laboratory an artificial system (or a concrete model for the evolution of life
on Earth) which is a homeostatic autopoietic system, which without doubt is the most
recurrent conception of an autopoietic system, both in the original formulation of its authors
and in its formalizations (Maturana and Varela 1972;1980; Varela et al. 1974; Varela 1979;
McMullin and Varela 1997; Varela 2000; McMullin 2004; Letelier et al. 2003,2006;
Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007; Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007).
Autopoiesis and Circular Causality
Maturana and Varela often emphasized that autopoiesis implies a certain circularity. In their
terms, an autopoietic system is open in structure (components enter and leave) but is closed
in its organization (its relations are closed as in a circle).
10
From this idea came others which
the authors used, such as operational closure
11
,operative closure,recursivity, and self-
referential systems. Here we address the question: How should this circularity be under-
stood? Firstly, what seems clear is that it is a circular causality.
12
The notion of circular
9
The symbol (M,R) comes from metabolism-repair systems, also called metabolism-replacement systems
by Letelier et al. (2006). Essential to any materialization of a (M,R) system is the decay of the catalysts, which
is counterbalanced by a group of replacement reactions which re-synthesizes the catalysts (Cornish-Bowden
and Cárdenas 2007,2008). By contrast, in an autocatalytic network the catalysts do not necessarily decay (or
their half-life is much greater than the life of the organisms). I thank Carlos Medina for bringing this point to
my attention.
10
The authors make reference to the circularity of autopoiesis in most of their works. Here I take only two
examples (from Maturana and Varela 1980): ‘…living systems as systems defined as unities through the basic
circularity of their production of their components(xiv); Living systemsareall organized in a closed
causal circular process(p. 9, italics are mine).
11
According to Fleischacker (1988), the term organizational closurewas replaced by operational closure
by Varela since 1982.
12
See Note 8. According to Robert Rosen organisms are different from machines because they are closed to
efficient causes.(Quoted in Letelier et al. 2003, p.265). Letelier et al. (2003,2006) identified this claim with
the circularity of autopoiesis subsumed by the term metabolic closure.
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
causality first arose with the appearance of cybernetics, around 1946 (Umpleby 2005), in
which the feedback mechanism was represented graphically as a cycle (a circle with a
defined direction). For the creators of cybernetics, the cyclic vision of the feedback mech-
anism assumes a representation of nodes and relations between nodes, which is collectively
closed on itself and in which the nodes represent states of particular variables of a system,
and the relations between nodes represent the control relations of these states (Fig. 4). Now,
what type of causal circularity is autopoiesis?
Obviously all circularity is a circularity of some kind of relations. The causal circularity
of feedback proposed by the cyberneticists is a circular relation among control relations.
Autopoiesis is usually interpreted as a causal circularity of production relations (see the first
quotation in Note 10), which is consistent with the literal interpretation of the concept as
self-production. However, according to the earlier arguments, this is not possible.
Circularity means that the leaving and entering relations are the same. Starting from a given
point, the relations of the cycle must return to the same point (Fig. 4). If the relation is that of
production, then starting from any pointall components of the system composing the unit
by means of the relations of production, all the components of the system should be
produced. That is, using the earlier nomenclature, if the set Xproduces the set Y,(XY), that
the production of the system is circular implies X0Y. However, we have already rejected
this. If autopoiesis were a circular causality of production, then the types of components
which constitute the system should (indirectly, mediated by a complicated network of
relations) produce themselves; that is, produce exactly the same types of components.
However, an autopoietic system only produces a subset of all the types of elements of the
system (YX). Then, in what sense can its organization be understood as circular (supposing
that this is in fact possible)? Definition D1 may be of help.
A living being is undoubtedly a system of production (in which production refers
specifically to chemical reactions). Although the components of the system do not produce
all the components of the system, they do produce that subset of components whose internal
production is necessary to maintain the network function as a unit(D1). And since the
system must maintain itself to meet D1, this subset of components must be capable of
procuring the internal presence of the rest of the components of the system from the exterior,
bringing them inand maintaining them in a sufficiently local proximity to compose a
Fig. 4 Abstract representation of a causal cycle
P. Razeto-Barry
physical unit. That is, it is not especially relevant whether the functional components of the
system (we may exclude the waste) come from the environment or are produced internally,
what is important is that they be present.
13
If the chemical reactions of a system produce
90 % of its components and the other 10 % are taken from the environment, this system is no
more autopoietic than one which produces 10 % of its components and takes the other 90 %
from its environment; for this reason there cannot be degreesof autopoiesis.
14
This means
that there is circularity, but even in a system based on production the circularity does not
come from the production relations, but rather from a circularity of physical proximity. Thus
the basis of the circularity is that the physical proximity of the components of the system
allows the production of components whose internal production is necessary for the physical
proximity of the components of the system (that which constitutes the network as a discrete
unit in space). This may allow us to understand Varelas emphasis on the production of
membrane components that spontaneously form vesicles as a very practical specification of
the concept of autopoiesis; not because the production of a boundary is in itself essential, but
rather because the membrane is an efficient manner of maintaining a molecular system
united, especially in an aquatic medium. If the system does not control molecules diffusion
reactantsdilution will lead to the cessation of chemical reactions in which they are
involved.
15
This causal relation may be profitably understood as a probabilistic causality.
16
That is,
what the physical proximity of the components of a system does is to increase the
probability that the components of the system are constantly in physical proximity. Thus,
autopoiesis would be a particular type of circular probabilistic causality. Physical proximity
(or spatial-temporal cohesion) is not a scientifically unimportant quality; on the contrary, it is
the base of all chemical reactions, catalysis in particular. If we want to produce a chemical
reaction, what we have to do is bring the reactants into close proximity, which greatly
increases the probability that the product will be produced. In fact, this is exactly what a
catalyst does; an enzyme is a molecular approximation machine.
In summary, paraphrasing Maturana and Varela, an autopoietic machine is a homeostatic
system of chemical production which has its own individual identity as a variable which it
maintains constant.
17
Individual identityis understood to be the same as numerical
identityor quantitative identity (reviewed in Noonan 2009), that is, the maintenance of a
discrete spatio-temporal unit (i.e., without losing spatio-temporal continuity or increasing or
13
Note that contemporary organizational approaches to function (e.g., Moreno and Ruiz-Mirazo 2009) do not
ascribe functionality in any component of a living system created externally, which contrasts with the wide
intuition that vitamins and cofactors are functional molecules which are not internally produced but obtained
from the environment. Consistent with the present analysis the function of these molecules is guaranteed
because they have the effect of allowing the maintainance of the autopoiesis, not matter whether they come
from external or internal sources. Furthermore, many functional parts of multicellular living beings are
microorganisms of other species, kingdoms and domains which are not internally produced but obtained
from the environment (Pepper and Rosenfeld 2012; Costello et al. 2012).
14
It was recently argued that in a network of biochemical processes the distinction between enzymeand
metaboliteis arbitrary and unnecessary (Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007). This reinforces the fact that it
is not necessary for the understanding of autopoietic organization to know what types of elements enter into
the system or what role they play in the network of chemical reactions (e.g., whether they participate in
peripheral,intermediateor centralreactions of the network).
15
Any autocatalytic set must be confined to a sufficiently small volume(Kauffman 1993, p.298).
16
A review of the notion of probabilistic causality and its application to evolutionary biology may be found in
Razeto-Barry and Frick (2011).
17
According to Maturana and Varela (1973)An autopoietic machine is a homeostatic system which has its
own organization as the variable which it maintains constant([1994], p. 69, in this article all quotations from
publications in Spanish are my translations). I criticize this affirmation in the next section.
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
decreasing its numberor quantity), although its properties or qualities may change (i.e. losing
its qualitative identity, see Noonan 2009). Thus the only condition on the chemical system is that
it maintains constantly (by its chemical production) its components in physical proximity in such a
way that it insures the spatio-temporal continuity which characterizes it as a unit.
18
It must be kept in mind that a living system is not only a physical system but notably also
a chemical system. What distinguishes a living bacterium from a frozen bacterium or a
crystal is that the living being is a machine characterized by chemical reactions. A crystal
maintains its individual identity by itself (and the physical proximity of its constituents)
trivially, due to the immobility of the relative positions of its components, but it is not a
production machine. It is very easy in the laboratory to generate a crystal spontaneously;
however, generating a concatenated system of chemical reactions which maintains its
individual identity thanks to the products of these reactions is something that only has been
achieved recently by Luisi and collaborators artificially in the laboratory, and they still have
not been able to make the system homeostatic. From the chemical point of view, what is
impressive about living systems is their exceptional coherence of chemical reactions which
maintain stably (i.e. without disintegrating or spreading out in a continuous mass
19
)a
discrete unit in space-time.
From the above we extract that possibly the idea of autopoiesis has seemed trivial to some
because it is not commonly emphasized that chemical reactions (i.e. processes of chemical
production) are not similar, in relevant aspects, to the springs of physicists or the circuits of
engineers. Chemical reactions imply the constant modification of the individual identity of
the components involved (reactants which become products), which in general impedes a
component from maintaining its function over time (the main exceptions are the enzymes).
This makes it very difficult to produce or even outline formally the conditions which permit
the continued existence of an autopoietic system based on chemical reactions. This does not
occur with the homeostasis of a servomechanism or the self-organization of a tornado or a
Bénard cell. In these cases it is true that a tornado or a Bénard cell are units whose dynamics
make probable the incorporation of components from their surroundings which maintain
their individual identity. However, what makes them different from a living being is that
living beings are systems which produce components in the form of chemical reactions, in
which the individual identity of the components is constantly modified. The maintenance of
individual identity of a tornado does not involve more variables than the position and
velocity of the particles in its locality. The particles themselves are not modified in the
whirlwind; they enter and leave without modifying their identity. They have the same form
when they enter and when they leave, they leave being themselves, without substantial
modification.
20
18
Note that this definition of individual identity(or quantitativeor numerical) is only applicable in the
context of systems in physical space. To apply this analysis to other spaces or domains (social, linguistic,
psychological, etc.), the concept of individual identity(and its differentiation from qualitative identity)
must be clearly specified.
19
This property may be related to thermodynamics as the maintenance of low entropy (see note 20).
20
From this viewpoint, I dare to propose that the thermodynamic characteristic recognized in living beings as
being systems permanently away from thermodynamic equilibrium (Schneider and Kay 1994)maybe
considered as a consequence of the definition of autopoiesis applied to systems of concatenated chemical
reactions. That is, the mere requirement that a system maintain its individual identity in spite of consisting of
concatenated chemical reactions requires that the system be in permanent thermodynamic disequilibrium. This
affirmation is not immediately obvious and must be demonstrated. However, it is plausible from the fact that
systems far from equilibrium may tend to form local zones of order (Schneider and Kay 1994), and that the
spatio-temporal congruence proper to the components of a unit with a continuous existence in space and time
constitutes a source of order in itself (as happens with tornadoes).
P. Razeto-Barry
In summary, and as a specification of D1 in physical space, I propose a schematic
definition of molecular autopoiesis (D2):
D2: A system is autopoietic if and only if:
1. It is a network of physical and chemical processes.
2. This network chemically produces a subset of the components which are parts of the
network.
3. This subset of components, by means of relations among its members and with the
components of its surroundings, generates the conditions necessary to maintain the
components of the network in physical proximity, collectively forming a spatially
discrete individual unit over time.
Autopoiesis and Organization
One of the greatest sources of confusion generated around the concept of autopoiesis
has been the use that Maturana and Varela gave to the concept of organization. One
phrase of Maturana and Varela (that was paraphrased previously) was used recurrently
to explain what an autopoietic system is: A living system is a homeostatic system
whose homeostatic organization has its own organization as the variable that it main-
tains constant(Maturana and Varela 1980, p. 48). I will show that the emphasis of the
authors in the maintenance of self-organization is difficult to understand due to the
sense in which the word organizationis used by these authors.
At first the reader tends to interpret organizationin the usual way, that is, as the
configuration of the existing relations among the components of a system; as the
relations which determinethe dynamics of the interactions and transformations of the
components(Maturana and Varela 1994, p. 67). But later in the text one understands
that, according to the authors, the organization which is maintained constant in the case
of an autopoietic system is the type of organization which defines living beings, that is,
autopoietic organization. Thus the questioned affirmation is equivalent to saying an
autopoietic system is a system which maintains its autopoietic organization as the
variable which it maintains constant. That is like saying that a chair is an object
that maintains its chair organization as the variable which it maintains constant. That
is, the affirmation would be only a non-informative tautology (i.e., by definition of its
terms it cannot be false). On the other hand, if by organizationwe understand the
relations which determinethe dynamics of the interactions and transformations of the
components(as is usual), the affirmation would imply a system composed of relations
which do not change over time, a system without ontogeny, without individual history
(and of course an insect in metamorphosis would not be a living being, see Valenzuela
2007); that is, something very different from the idea of a living being. As we saw
before, definition D1 implies that what characterizes an autopoietic system is not its
capacity to oppose changes in its organization, but rather its capacity to oppose the
disintegration of its spatio-temporal unity (in spite of its constant chemical reactions).
This also implies that the concept of organizational invariance(Letelier et al. 2003,2006; Cornish-
Bowden et al. 2007) is not an acceptable term as a formalization of the concept of autopoiesis.
Some of the confusion related to the concept of autopoiesis are associated with a number
of the pseudo-problems and classical confusions which have been generated in philosophy
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
and continue to the present day, due to not distinguishing between individual identity
(0quantitativeor numericidentity) and qualitativeidentity (these pseudo-problems are
reviewed in Tugendhat 2002 [1992] and Tugendhat and Wolf 1997 [1983]). Individual
identity refers to what specifies particular individuals (or tokensin philosophical jargon),
while qualitative identity refers to what specifies the classes (or kinds) of individuals defined
according to their properties (or types). This confusion arises principally because both
concepts are referred to using the ambiguous terms of identityor self.
21
Maturana
clearly defines organizationas that which specifies the type or class to which an individual
or system pertains, distinguishing it from the structurethat specifies the characteristics of
the individual as a particular system or token.
22
However, the authors tend to specify an
autopoietic system as a system which achieves the production and maintenance of a same
(constant) organization. That is, unless the authors want to fall into a simple tautology by
making organizationequal autopoietic organization, they are affirming that autopoietic
systems are systems which produce that which maintains their qualitative identity (their
properties) constant. That is, systems which do not change their properties during their lives!
In other words, the affirmation is either tautological or is false. Put another way, autopoietic
systems do not maintain an organizational homeostasis (homeostasis of their qualitative
identity), but rather a homeostasis of their individual unity (homeostasis of their quantitative
identity). This is the reason for the paraphrase based on D1: An autopoietic machine is a
homeostatic system of chemical production which has its own individual identity as the
variable which it maintains constant.
23
Another of the pseudoproblems related to autopoiesis due to not distinguishing between
qualitative identity and individual (or quantitative) identity is the so-called problem of
infinite regressionstated by Rosen (1959) in the causal circularity of living beings
(Letelier et al. 2003,2006; Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2008). Robert Rosen believed
that there was a kind of paradox in the regeneration of components, in which the components
of a living being are produced by other components of the being, which in turn are produced
by other components of the being, and so on. However, the error lies in not considering that
the regeneration is a replacement of elements of the same type. There is nothing paradoxical
in a series of events among particular elements (tokens) producing reactions which generate
other particular elements. What makes the system stable over time is that the elements
21
A classical example of this is the woman who says youre not the same man I fell in love with. Obviously
she is not denying the individual identityof the man, she says it to him (e.g., Peter) and not to someone else.
In fact, if she were talking to another person and not to Peter, we would either think she was crazy or had
confused Peter with someone else. She means that he (the same individual, Peter) doesn´t have the same
qualities he had when she fell in love with him; that is, she claims that his qualitative identitychanged (see
Tugendhat 2002 [1992]). The individual identity is not lost when properties change; what is lost is the
qualitative identity.
22
According to the author: The relations between components that define a composite unity (system) as a
composite unity of a particular kind, constitute its organization.He defines structureas The actual
components (all their properties included) and the actual relations holding between them that concretely
realize a system as a particular member of the class (kind) of composite unities to which it belongs by its
organization, constitute its structure.(Maturana 1980, Introduction, pp. xix-xxx, in Maturana and Varela
1980). Maturana (1978, p. 32) affirms that organization refers to the relations between components that
define and specify a system as a composite unity of a particular class, and determine its properties as such a
unity, while structure refers to the actual components and the actual relations that these must satisfy in their
participation in the constitution of a given composite unity. I thank Aldo Mascareño for the last reference.
23
This also runs counter to studies of autopoiesis such as that of Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas (2008), in
which the maintenance of individuality is an accident, an abstract imposition which does not result from the
dynamics of the system. The same can be said about the majority of computational models of autocatalytic
reaction networks (see McMullin 2000).
P. Razeto-Barry
produced are approximately of the same type (approximately, of course, unless there is no
change of qualities during ontogeny). In fact, in autopoiesis there is regeneration of both the
types of elements and the types of relations (which, as an epiphenomenon, produce the
regeneration of the process of regeneration). Thus there is no infinite regressionwhatso-
ever in living beings which is different from any other habitual causal process in nature,
including any cybernetic machine.
24
Autopoiesis and Multicelularity
The essentiality that biology gives of chemical reactions to understand the life is well
represented in Helmonts (1648) claim: All life is chemistry(from Pross 2004).
Certainly, the main sources of control of processes in living systems are chemical reactions.
However, even in unicellular organisms and minimal cell prototypes many necessary
processes to the system maintenance are different from chemical reactions or processes
catalyzed by chemical reactions of the system. For example, in the model of Varela et al.
(1974, McMullin and Varela 1997) there are reactions of concatenation and disintegration
that are not catalyzed by products of the system (McMullin 2000). Furthermore, processes of
molecules diffusion and vesicles formation are physical spontaneous processes in which
there are not changes of chemical substances. Thus, in living beings not all processes
(relations) necessary to maintain the system are, or are catalyzed by, chemical reactions. In
addition, multicellular living beings depend essentially on many physical (non chemical)
processes to its maintenance. For example, circulatory, lymphatic, and respiratory systems in
animals are based on fluids flowing within a network of vessels, valves and chambers, in
which changes of pressures, heat release and many other physical phenomena are funda-
mental to organisms survival. A single mechanical obstruction of a cerebral artery may
cause the death and disintegration of a multicellular organism (see also Goldenfeld and
Woese 2011).
Maturana and Varela (1973,1980) briefly characterized multicellular organisms as
second-order autopoietic systems, which means that they are made up of (first-order)
autopoietic systems.
25
However, they do not affirm that multicellular organisms are first-
order autopoietic systems. Maturana and Varela (1992 [1987]) faced directly this problem:
What is the organization of metacellulars?Are some metacellulars autopoietic unities?
That is, are second-order autopoietic systems also first-order autopoietic systems?(p. 87).
However, authors finally avoided giving a response: For the purposes of this book, we shall
leave open the question of whether or not metacellular systems are first-order autopoietic
systems.Because in the case of metacellulars, we are still ignorant of the molecular
processes that would constitute those metacellulars as autopoietic unities comparable to
cells.(pp. 8889) and characterized multicellular organisms only as lineagesof cells. This
point becomes critical to autopoiesis becomes a unifying concept for biology and a good
definition of living being. If multicellular organisms (the paradigmatic living beings, Wilson
2000) are not autopoietic then multicellular organisms are not living beings! In fact,
24
It is possible that what made so attractive the introduction of the notion of circularityin cybernetics due to
the circular causality(of feedback systems), is that we erroneously tend to think that if the causality of tokens
is never backward (that is, there is never backward causation, see Faye 2010), then neither is the causality of
types. The causal circularity of feedback is precisely a circularity of types of events, not of particular events.
25
What is common to all metacellulars in the five kingdoms is that they include cells as components of their
structure. That is why we say that metacellulars are second-order autopoietic systems.(Maturana and Varela
1992, p. 87)
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
according to Weber and Varela (2002), multicellular organisms are not themselves auto-
poietic systems: Autopoiesis has been explicitly formulated for the minimal living system,
the cell. () A multicellular organism (and this includes all vertebrates usually taken as
prototypical organisms) is not in itself an autopoietic unit of second order, since its
organization does not follow the same selfcontructing principles.(p. 115).
It is possible that Maturana and Varela did not include multicellular organisms as
autopoietic systems because of their misguided emphasis in chemical reaction networks
and in the production of a boundary, which as I have analyzed previously, are unnecessary
for the definition of autopoiesis. According to definitions D1 and D2, multicellular organ-
isms are clearly (first-order) autopoietic systems. The ontogeny of mammals develops from a
unicellular (zygote) state to a morula, a blastula and so on, as a consequence of the chemical
production of a subgroup of the components which maintain it as a discrete multicellular
unit. It is important to note that multicellular organisms such as adult humans produce their
own boundary (e.g., the skin in vertebrates, shells and cuticles in invertebrates and plants,
respectively); however, in contrast with unicellular organisms, the production of the border
is not what physically maintains the system as a unit. We can think of multicellular
formations of Myxobacteria in Prokarya or Dictyostelium in Eukarya, but also of human
beings tortured by ancient indigenous Moche people in South America whom took the skin
off of their prisoners while maintaining them alive (Castillo 2000).
26
Essential components
of multicellular organisms are chemical products that maintain cells joined. Probably the
first step in the evolution of multicellularity was the chemical production of components that
prevent the daughter cells from separating after the replication (Bonner 1998). It seems that
this kind of processes is not improbable because multicellularity has evolved independently
many times in each domain of life (Bonner 1998; Carroll 2001). Thus the network of
interconnected components of multicellular organisms, chemically produce the components
that maintain the components of the network in physical proximity, collectively forming a
spatially discrete individual unit over time.
Autopoiesis and Life
Now that the definition of autopoiesis has been re-examined and redefined, it may be seen
that the definition of living beingas a molecular autopoietic systemis a good definition
which serves as a demarcation criterion of living beings. That is, autopoiesis understood in
its subtle formulation (D1 and D2) is a singular relational property which effectively allows
the differentiation of the main groups of systems which we recognize as living beings from
the rest of the objects and non-living systems. As we have seen, the self-production
characteristic of autopoiesis is not the production of the totality of the components which
the system materializes, nor is it the production of the same organization of components and
relations which give rise to the products of the network, but rather the production of the
subgroup of components which actively conserve the continuous discrete existence of the
system (that is, which conserve the spatio-temporal individual identity of the system in spite
of the chemical reactions it undergoes). This definition excludes not only the machines
26
Note that the formation of external and internal boundaries in multicellular organisms is a derived evolved
property, posibly increasing autonomy (Rosslenbroich 2009), analogously to the formation of external and
internal membranes in the first cells (Hargreaves and Deamer 1978; Hanczyz et al. 2003; Budin and Szostak
2011) and in firsts unicellular eukaria (Kutschera and Niklas 2008), respectively. The idea of a living being as
abagcontaining liquid should be thus given up.
P. Razeto-Barry
generated so far by humans (such as automobiles) and typical inanimate natural objects
(such as crystals), but also excludes self-organized dynamic systems such as whirlwinds,
Bénard cells, and other natural physical systems as dissipative structures.
A definition of a living being should also serve as a demarcation criterion for borderline
beings, those at the edge of life. Autopoiesis excludes several such beings such as viruses,
viroids, transposons and prions, since these are not systems which have chemical reactions
whose products maintain the discreet individual unity in space. Other borderline systems are
the apparently superorganismssuch as those of social insects or colonies of coelenterates;
in this case the epithet autopoietic is less clear, since the spatial unity is somewhat less clear.
In spite of this, the individual identity of a colony is usually quite clear and may be followed
in space and time; these must be included as living beings. This may be unintuitive
conclusion is consistent with recent approaches that understand organismalityas a con-
tinuous variable characterized by a high level of cooperation and low level of conflict among
parts. These approaches consider that colonies of insects are organismsin the same degree
than an individual animal or human being (Queller and Strassman 2009; West and Kiers
2009).
27
One of the permanent difficulties in the definitions of living beings is that they must
satisfy two conditions which are in constant tension; they must be compatible with the
theories of the origin of life on Earth, in which reproduction appears to be essential, and they
mustnotfallintothemule paradox(Szathmáry 2002), that is, conclude that non-
reproductive systems such as mules are not living beings. One classical dispute in the
theories of the origin of life is whether self-maintained metabolism preceded self-
replication or whether self-replication occurred first (Pross 2004). In any case, it appears
that the basic characteristic of the most primitive living beings (pre-cellular) is the self-
reproduction (of singular molecules or complete metabolic systems) (Pross 2004; Razeto-
Barry 2012), which is a key condition for their propagation and evolution. However, any
definition which requires self-reproduction as a definitive condition for life falls into the
mule paradox, that is, it excludes individuals which are clearly living beings but which are
not self-reproducing (such as mules and some castes of eusocial insects). The subtle
definitions D1 and D2 resolve this tension, because both the growth which tends to self-
reproduction and the homeostatic maintenance (not self-reproductive) of a system are special
cases which comply with the definition of autopoiesis. Thus both self-reproductive vesicles
(e.g., Zepik et al. 2001; Luisi 2006) and non-reproductive organisms (mules, naked mole
rats, worker bees, plants without seeds) are autopoietic systems as long as some subset of the
products of their internal chemical reactions provides the maintenance of the individual
identity of the system. It seems evident that self-reproductive autopoiesis is the ancestral
condition, but non self-reproducing autopoiesis has arisen many times in the past, and re-
occurs with every organism born infertile (see also Razeto-Barry 2012).
The above is highly relevant for the compatibility of autopoiesis with the theories of the
origin of life. The fact that definitions D1 and D2 make autopoiesis compatible with the non-
homeostatic self-reproduction without internal disintegration of components is what allows
autopoiesis to be compatible with any currently plausible theory of the origin of life on Earth
27
These [colonies of social insects] are sometimes referred to as superorganisms, but why not just call them
organisms? From an adaptive perspective, a colony of social insects is analogous to the colony of cells that
comprise a human(West and Kiers 2009). Following Queller and Strassman (2009), we may say that an
autopoietic system is a system with high level of cooperation among parts based on strong reciprocity(see
West et al. 2011 for a critical review), such that a typical homeostatic autopoietic system is a system with high
indirect reciprocityamong types of molecules (autocatalytic network) and some level of punishment
(degradation of molecules).
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
(e.g., see Pross 2004). This is because in general the half life (or spontaneous decay) of the
components of living beings is much greater than the life span of the organisms. In fact, the
decay of the polymers of currently living beings is the result of complex degradation
networks (such as the systems of protein degradation). However, it is hard to imagine that
in the origin of life there were sophisticated molecular systems (Pross 2004) such as those
required for the degradation of enzymes and other products of metabolism. Thus homeo-
static autopoietic systems with internal degradation of components are derived living beings
and not primitive ones.
28
Definitions D1 and D2 not only resolve the mule paradox, but also
allow a definition of living being compatible with origin of life theories and serves as a good
criterion for the demarcation of uni- and multicellular living beings.
Probably one of the greatest defects of the concept of autopoiesis as a definition of a
living being is that it is only a descriptive definition and not mechanical-causal. That is, the
property in question does not refer to causes or forces which may be analyzed within
physical, chemical or thermodynamic theories. One consequence of this is that the auto-
poietic property also does not explain other properties of living beings in causal terms. A
good definition not only should give the conditions for recognition of a living being, but also
the conditions for the production and manipulation of living systems (Escobar 2011). For
example, one might require that every reaction of an autopoietic system be spontaneous, but
autopoiesis does not specify the thermodynamic conditions which allow the complete
system to function as an autonomous machine, nor does it define its energetic relation with
the environment. The specification of the directive forces may be essential to the under-
standing of the nature of life (Pross 2004). However, in spite of this shortcoming, it appears
that autopoiesis (under D1 and D2) is the only simple property actually available which
allows a satisfactory definition of living being, satisfying the majority of the theoretical and
practical criteria of a good definition.
Final Conclusions
The analysis of the concepts of autopoiesis (D1) and molecular autopoiesis (D2) have led me
to conclusions which contrast strongly with an important part of the literature which deals
with autopoiesis. Here I provide a summary of the points in which this work opposes other
publications.
First, I conclude that the autopoiesis of a system does not imply the production of all the
components of the system, in contrast to the opinions of Capra 1996; Letelier et al. 2003 and
Luisi 2003 (see note 3); thus the circularity of autopoiesis is not a causal circularity of
production relations, and therefore I reject the concept of metabolic closure(Letelier et al.
2003,2006)orclosure of the reaction network(McMullin 2000, p. 167) as a character-
ization of autopoiesis.
Second, I conclude that the concept of autopoiesis is not tautological, trivial or
unscientific, and neither are its derivations, in contrast to the conclusion of a number
of authors (Zolo 1990;Munch1992; Scheper and Scheper 1996,Swenson1992a,
1992b, Manríquez and Rothammer 1997; Gallardo 1997; Nespolo 2003; Valenzuela
2007,2010),
Third, the concept of autopoiesis is not highly complex, nor does it imply an undecidable
or un-computable process, as suggested by Letelier et al. (2003,2006) (see also the seventh
conclusion below).
28
I owe this point to Carlos Medina (see note 7).
P. Razeto-Barry
Fourth, the internal production of the border or external membrane is not essential to the
concept of autopoiesis, in contrast to the analyses and formalizations of Varela et al. (1974),
Fleischaker (1988), Luisi et al. (1996), McMullin and Varela (1997), and Varela (2000).
Fifth, multicellular organisms are first-order autopoietic systems (in contrast to Weber
and Varela 2002).
Sixth, the disintegration and regeneration of disintegrated components is not essential to
autopoiesis, in contrast to Varela et al. (1974), McMullin and Varela (1997), Varela (2000),
Letelier et al. (2003,2006), McMullin (2004), Cornish-Bowden et al. (2007), Cornish-
Bowden and Cárdenas (2007).
Seventh, and as a consequence of the previous, I conclude that autopoietic systems are
not a type of Robert Rosens (M,R) system, in contrast to the conclusions of Letelier et al.
(2003,2006), Cornish-Bowden et al. (2007) and Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas (2007).
One consequence of this is the third conclusion above.
Eighth, I conclude that the concept of autopoiesis is not in contraposition to that of self-
reproduction (in contrast, for example, to Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007) and that the
homeostatic autopoietic systems described by the majority of the formalizations of the
concept (Maturana and Varela 1972;1980; Varela et al. 1974; Varela 1979; McMullin and
Varela 1997; Varela 2000; McMullin 2004; Letelier et al. 2003,2006; Cornish-Bowden et al.
2007; Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007) are only particular cases of an autopoietic
system, which do not correspond to the systems which characterized the origin of life,
which in turn implies that homeostatic autopoiesis is an evolutionary derived, not primitive
property.
Ninth, I conclude that an autopoietic system is not a system which maintains the
properties of its organization (type) constant, in contrast to Maturana and Varela (1973,
1980), due to which I reject the term organizational invarianceof Letelier et al. (2003,
2006) and Cornish-Bowden et al. (2007) as a formalization of the concept of
autopoiesis.
Tenth, I conclude that the so-called problem of infinite regressionof Rosen (1959),
Letelier et al. (2003,2006) and Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas (2008) is a pseudo-problem
produced by not distinguishing between the concepts of individual identity(quantitative)
and qualitative identity.
Acknowledgements I thank Carlos Medina, Roberto Torretti, Luis Razeto, Lafayette Eaton, Gabriel Razeto
and Leonardo Sepúlveda for useful comments on previous versions of this manuscript. I especially thank
Carlos Medina for a number of ideas in this article (see notes 7, 9, and 28). I thank an anonymous reviewer for
useful suggestions.
References
Ashby WR (1957) An Introduction to Cybernetics. Chapman and Hall LTD
Avery J (2003) Information theory and evolution. World Scientific Publishing, London.
Bak P (1996) How Nature Works: the Science of Self-Organized Criticality. Springer-Verlag
Barandiaran X, Moreno A (2006) On what makes certain dynamical systems cognitive: a minimally cognitive
organization program. Adapt Behav 14(2):171185
Bedau M (2003) Artificial life: organization, adaptation and complexity from the bottom up. Trends in Cogn
Sci 7(11):506512
Bedau M (2008) What is life? In Sarkar, S. and Plutynski, A. (ed.) A Companion to the Philosophy of Biology.
pp. 455603. Wiley-Blackwell
Bertalanffy L (1950) The theory of open systems in physics and biology. In: Emery FE (ed) Systems thinking.
Penguin, Harmondsworth, pp 7085
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
Bertalanffy L (1968) General system theory. Penguin, Harmondsworth
Bitbol M, Luisi PL (2004) Autopoiesis with or without cognition: defining life at its edge. J R Soc Interface
1:99107
Bognadonov A 1996 [1922]. Bogdanovs Tektology. Dudley, P. (ed.) 1996, Centre for Systems Studies, Hull, U.K
Bonner JT (1998) The origins of multicellularity. Integeative Biol 1:2836
Breitling R (2010) What is systems biology? Front Physiol 1(9):15
Budin I, Szostak JW (2011) Physical effects underlying the transition from primitive to modern cell
membranes. PNAS USA 108(13):52495254
Capra F (1996) The Web of life. Anchor Books, New York
Carroll SB (2001) Chance and necessity: the evolution of morphological complexity and diversity. Nature
409:11021109
Castillo LJ (2000) Los rituales mochicas de la muerte. In Makowski, K. (ed.), Los Dioses del Antiguo Perú.
Colección Arte y Tesoros del Perú. Lima, Banco de Crédito del Perú, pp., 103135
Colapinto J (1985) Maturana and the ideology of conformity. The Family Therapy Networker (May/June): 29
30
Cornish-Bowden A, Cárdenas M-L (2007) Organizational invariance in (M, R)-systems. Chem Biodivers
4:23962406
Cornish-Bowden A, Cárdenas M-L (2008) Self-organization at the origin of life. J Theor Biol 252:411418
Cornish-Bowden A, Cárdenas M-L, Letelier J-C, Soto-Andrade J (2007) Beyond reductionism: metabolic
circularity as a guiding vision for a real biology of systems. Proteomics 7:839845
Costello EK, Stagaman K, Dethlefsen L, Bohannan BJM, Relman DA (2012) The application of ecological
theory toward an understanding of the human microbiome. Science 336:12551262
Dix D (1983) Toward a definition of life semantic and thermodynamic considerations. J Theor Biol
102:337340
Dudley P (1996) Back to basics? tektology and general system theory (GST). Syst Pract Action Res 9(3):273
284
Emmeche C (1992) Life as an abstract phenomenon: is artificial life possible? In: Towards a Practice of
Autonomous Systems, ed. by F.J. Varen, F. Bourgine, Proc. 1st European Conference on Artificial Life.
pp. 466474
Escobar JM (2011) Autopoiesis and Darwinism. Synthese (in press). doi:10.1007/s11229-011-9875-y
Faye J (2010) Backward causation. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Stanford
Fleischacker G (1988) Autopoiesis: the status of its system logic. Biosystems 22:3749
Fleischacker G, Margulis L (1986) Autopoiesis and the origin of bacteria. Adv Space Res 6(11):5355
Friedman I (2002) Short definitions of life. In: Palyi G, Zucchi C, Caglioti L (eds) Fundamentals of life.
Elsevier, New York, p 30
Gallardo MH (1997) Determinismo estructural: ¿teoría o dogma? Rev Chil Hist Nat 70:315319
Geyer F, van der Zouwen J (2001) Sociocybernetics. Complexity, autopoiesis and observation of social
systems. Greenwood Press, London
Gisiger T (2001) Scale invariance in biology: coincidence or footprint of a universal mechanism? Biol Rev
76:161209
Goldenfeld N, Woese C (2011) Life is physics: evolution as a collective phenomenon far from equilibrium.
Annu Rev of Condens Matter Phys 2:299375
Gorelik G (1975) Principle ideas of Bogdanovstektology: the universal science of Organization. Gen Syst
20:145
Gorelik G (1984) Essays from tektology, 2nd edn. Intersystems, Seaside, Calif
Hanczyz MM, Fujikawa SM, Szostak JW (2003) Experimental models of primitive cellular compartmental-
ization: encapsulation, growth, and division. Science 302:618622
Hargreaves WR, Deamer DW (1978) Liposomes from ionic, single-chain amphiphiles. Biochemistry
17:37593768
Kauffman SA (1989) Principles of adaptation in complex systems. Lectures in the Sciences of Complexity. The
Santa Fe Institute Series (Addison Wesley), pp. 619712
Kauffman SA (1993) The origins of order: self-organization and selection in evolution. Oxford University
Press, Oxford
Kauffman SA (2001) Prolegomenon to a general biology, unity of knowledge: the convergence of natural and
human science. Ann N Y Acad Sci 935:1836
Koshland DE (2002) The seven pillars of life. Science 295:22152216
Kutschera U, Niklas KJ (2008) Macroevolution via secondary endosymbiosis: a Neo-goldschmidtian view of
unicellular hopeful monsters and Darwins primordial intermediate form. Theory Biosci 127:277289
Langton C (ed.) (1989) Artificial Life. Addison-Wesley
Letelier J-C, Marín G, Mpodozis J (2003) Autopoietic and (M, R) systems. J Theor Biol 222(2):261272
P. Razeto-Barry
Letelier J-C, Soto-Andrade J, Guiñez Abarzúa F, Cornish-Bowden A, Cárdenas M-L (2006) Organi-
zational invariance and metabolic closure: analysis in terms of (M, R) systems. J Theor Biol 238
(4):949961
Litfin K (2010) Principles of gaian governance: a rough sketch. In: Christ E, Rinker HB (eds) Gaia in turmoil:
climate change, biodepletion, and earth ethics in an age of crisis. The MIT Press, Cambridge
Luhmann N (1986) The autopoiesis of social systems. In: Geyer F, van der Zouwen J (eds) Sociocybernetic
paradoxes. Sage, London
Luhmann N 1995 [1984]. Social Systems. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press
Luhmann N 2007 [1997]. La Sociedad de la Sociedad. Universidad Iberoamericana, México
Luisi PL (1993) The chemical implementation of autopoiesis. In: Fleischaker GR, Stephano C, Pier Luigi L
(eds) Self-production of supramolecular structures: from synthetic structures to models of minimal living
systems. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 179197
Luisi PL (2003) Autopoiesis: a review and a reappraisal. Naturwissenschaften 90:4959
Luisi PL (2006) The emergence of life. From chemical origins to synthetic biology. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge
Luisi PL, Varela F (1989) Self-replicating micelles: a chemical version of minimal autopoietic systems. Orig
Life Evol Biosph 19:633643
Luisi PL, Lazcano A, Varela F (1996) Autopoiesis: the very idea, in: defining life. In: Rizzotti M (ed) The
central problem in theoretical biology. Universitá de Padova, Padova, pp 146167
Luisi PL, Ferri F, Stano P (2006) Approaches to semi-synthetic minimal cells: a review. Naturwissenschaften
93(1):113
Magalhaes R, Sanchez R (2009) Autopoiesis in organization theory and practice. Emerald, U. K
Mahner M, Bunge M (1997) Foundations of biophilosophy. Springer, Berlin
Mann C (1991) Lynn margulis: Sciences unruly earth mother. Science 252:378381
Manriquez G, Rothhammer F (1997) Teoría moderna de la evolución. Amphora Editores, Santiago
Margulis L (1997) Kingdom animalia. In: Margulis L, Sagan D (eds) Slanted truths: essays on Gaia symbiosis
and evolution. Springer, New York, pp 91111
Maturana H (1978) Biology of language: the epistemology of reality. In: Millar G, Lennenberg E (eds)
Psychology and biology of language and thought: essays in honour of Eric lennenberg. Academic, New
York, pp 2949
Maturana H (1981) Autopoiesis. In: Zeleny M (ed) Autopoiesis: A theory of living organization. North
Holland, New York, pp 2133
Maturana H, Mpodozis J (1992) Origen de las especies por medio de la deriva natural o la diversificaion de los
linajes a traves de la conservacion y cambio de los fenotipos ontogenicos. Museo Nacional de Historia
Natural, Publicación Ocasional 46:148
Maturana H, Mpodozis J (2000) The origin of species by means of natural drift. Revista Chilena de Historia
Natural 73:261310
Maturana H, Varela F (1973) De máquinas y seres vivos. Editorial Universitaria, Santiago, Chile
Maturana H, Varela F (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition. The Realization of the Living, Reidel, Dordrecht
Maturana H and Varela F 1992 [1987]. The Three of Knowledge, Shimbhala, Boston
Maturana H, Varela F (1994) De máquinas y seres vivos. Autopoiesis: La organización de lo viviente, 2nd edn.
Editorial Universitaria, Santiago
Mazzarello P (1999) A unifying concept: the history of cell theory. Nat Cell Biol 1:E13E15
McMullin B (2000) Remarks on autocatalysis and autopoiesis. Ann N Y Acad Sci 901:163174
McMullin B (2004) Thirty years of computational autopoiesis: a review. Artif Life 10:277295
McMullin B and Varela FJ (1997) Rediscovering computational autopoiesis. In P. Husbands and I. Harvey
(Eds.), Proceedings of the Fourth European Conference on Artificial Life (pp. 3847). Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press. http://www.eeng.dcu.ie/˜alife/bmcm-ecal97/
Mingers J (1995) Self-producing systems: implications and applications of autopoiesis. PlenumPress, New
York
Morán F, Moreno A, Minch E, Montero F (1999) In: Artificial Life V, Langton CG, Shimonara K (eds)
Further steps toward a realistic description of the essence of life. MIT Press, London, pp 255263
Moreno A, Ruiz-Mirazo K (2009) The problem of the emergence of functional diversity in prebiotic
evolution. Biol Philos 24:585605
Munch R (1992) Autopoiesis by definition. Cardozo Law Rev 13:14631471
Nealson K (2002) Short definitions of life. In: Palyi G, Zucchi C, Caglioti L (eds) Fundamentals of life.
Elsevier, New York, p 45
Nespolo RF (2003) Evolution by natural selection: more evidence than ever before. Rev Chil Hist Nat
76:699716
Noonan H (2009) Identity. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Stanford
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
Pepper JW, Rosenfeld S (2012) The emerging medical ecology of the human gut microbiome. Trends Ecol
Evol 27(7):381384
Popa R (2004) Between necessity and probability: searching for the definition and origin of life. Springer,
Berlin
Porter JR (1976) Antony van Leeuwenhoek: tercentenary of his discovery of bacteria. Bacteriol Rev 40
(2):260269
Pross A (2004) Causation and the origin of life, metabolism or replication first? Orig Life Evol Biosph
34:307321
Queller DC, Strassman JE (2009) Beyond sociality: the evolution of organismality. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B
364:31433155
Rapoport A (1972) The uses of mathematical isomorphism in general system theory. Trends in General
Systems Theory, Bertalanffy et al. (eds.). John Wiley and Sons
Rashevsky N (1954) Topology and life: in search of general mathematical principles in biology and sociology.
Bull Math Biophys 16:317348
Razeto-Barry, P. 2012. What should be the first law of biology? (forthcoming)
Razeto-Barry P, Cienfuegos J (2011) La paradoja de la probabilidad de lo improbable y el pensamiento
evolutivo de Niklas Luhmann. Convergencia 57:1338
Razeto-Barry P, Frick R (2011) Probabilistic causation and the explanatory role of natural selection. Stud Hist
Phil Biol Biomed Sci 42(3):344355
Reason P, Goodwin BC (1999) Toward a science of qualities in organizations: lessons from complexity theory
and postmodern biology. Concepts and Transform 4(3):281317
Reilly M (2008) Early life could have been based on arsenic. The New Scientist 198(2653):10
Rosen R (1958) A relational theory of biological systems. Bull Math Biophys 20:245341
Rosen R (1959) A relational theory of biological systems II. Bull Math Biophys 21:109128
Rosen R (1991) Life Itself. Columbia University Press, New York
Rosslenbroich B (2009) The theory of increasing autonomy in evolution: a proposal for understanding
macroevolutionary innovations. Biol Philos 24:623644
Ruiz-Mirazo K, Paretó J, Moreno A (2004) A universal definition of life: autonomy and open-ended
evolution. Orig Life Evol Biosph 34:323346
Ruthen R (1993) Adapting to complexity. Sci Am 268:130140
Sagan D, Margulis L (1997) The uncut self. In: Margulis L, Sagan D (eds) Slanted truths: essays on Gaia
symbiosis and evolution. Springer, New York, pp 5973
Scheper WJ, Scheper GC (1996) Autopsies on autopoiesis. Behav Sci 41:112
Schneider ED, Kay JJ (1994) Life as a manifestation of the second law of thermodynamics. Math Comput
Model 19(68):2548
Schroder SM (2010) Toward a conceptual framework for biology. Q Rev Biol 85(3):293318
Shannon CE (1948) A mathematical theory of communication. Bell Syst Tech J 27(379423):623656
Shannon CE, Weaver W (1949) The mathematical theory of communication. University of Illinois Press,
Urbana-Champaign, IL
Simon R (1985) Structure is destiny A frogs view of the world. The Family Therapy Networker (May/June):
3243
Skyttner L (2005) General systems theory. Problems, perspectives, practice, 2nd edn. World Scientific,
London
Snyder E (1999) Is freuds model of the mind autopoietic? Ger Rev 74:6778
Solé RV, Munteanu A, Rodriguez-Caso C, Macía J (2007) Synthetic protocellbiology: from reproduction to
computation. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 362:17271739
Swenson R (1992a) Autocatakinetics, yes-autopoiesis, no: steps towards a unified theory of evolutionary
ordering. Int J Gen Syst 21(2):207228
Swenson R (1992b) Galileo, Babel, and autopoiesis (It's turtles all the way down). Int J Gen Syst 21(2):267
269
Szathmáry E (2002) Short definitions of lifeand redefining life: an ecological, thermodynamic, and
bioinformatic approach. In: Pályi G, Zucchi C, Caglioti L (eds) Fundamentals of life. Elsevier, New
York, pp 50, 181195
Tugendhat E 2002 [1992]. Identidad personal, particular y universal. In Problemas, Gedisa, Barcelona
Tugendhat E and Wolf U 1997 [1983]. Propedéutica Lógicosemántica, Anthropos, Barcelona. [Original:
Logisch-semantische Propädeutik, Philipp Reclam jun., Stuttgard]
Umpleby SA (2005) A history of the cybernetics movement in the United States. J Wash Acad Sci 91(2)
Valenzuela CY (2007) Within selection. Rev Chil Hist Nat 80:109116
Valenzuela CY (2010) Neutral illusions, selective nightmares and autopoietic madness. Rev Chil Hist Nat
83:497500
P. Razeto-Barry
Varela FJ (1979) Principles of biological autonomy. Elsevier, New York
Varela FJ (1981) Describing the logic of the living the adequacy and limitations of the idea of autopoiesis.
In: Zeleny M (ed) Autopoiesis: A theory of living organization. North Holland, New York, pp 3648
Varela FJ (2000) El fenómeno de la Vida. Dolmen Ensayo, Santiago, Chile
Varela FJ, Maturana HR (1972) Mechanism and biological explanation. Philos Sci 39(3):378382
Varela FJ, Maturana HR, Uribe R (1974) Autopoiesis: the organization of living systems, its characterization
and a model. Biosystems 5:187196
Varela FJ, Thompson E, Rosch E (1991) The embodied mind. Cognitive science and human experience. MIT
Press, Cambridge, MA
Vargas A (2005) Beyond selection. Revista Chilena de Historia Natural 78(4):739752
Veloz T, Razeto-Barry P, Dittrich P & Fajardo A (2012) Reaction networks and evolutionary game theory.
Journal of Mathematical Biology (forthcoming)
Weber A, Varela F (2002) Life after Kant: natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological
individuality. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 1:97125
West SA, Kiers ET (2009) Evolution: what is an organism? Curr Biol 19(23):R1080
West SA, Mouden CE, Gardner A (2011) Sixteen common misconceptions about the evolution of cooperation
in humans. Evol Hum Behav 32:231262
Wiener N (1948) Cybernetics. Wiley, New York
Wilson JA (2000) Ontological butchery: organism concepts and biological generalizations. Philos Sci 67:
S301S311
Wolfe-Simon F, Jodi Switzer B, Kulp TR, Gordon GW, Hoeft SE, Pett-Ridge J, Stolz JF, Webb SM, Weber
PK, Davies PCW, Anbar AD, Oremland RS (2011) A bacterium that can grow by using arsenic instead of
phosphorus. Science 332:11631166
Wolfram S (2002) A new kind of science. Wolfram Media Inc., Champaign
Wolkenhauer O (2001) Systems biology: the reincarnation of systems theory applied in biology? Brief
Bioinform 2(3):258270
Zepik HH, Bloechliger E, Luisi PL (2001) A chemical model of homeostasis. Angew Chem 40:199202
Zolo D (1990) Autopoiesis: critique of a postmodern paradigm. Telos 23:6180
Autopoiesis 40 years Later. A Review and a Reformulation
... "An autopoietic system is a network of processes which produces all the components whose internal production is necessary to maintain the network operating as a unit." [18] Since its inception, there was an assertion that for a system to be considered autopoietic, it must define a boundary that separates itself from its environment [18][19][20][21][22][23][24][25][26]. Even the Biomimetics 2024, 9, simplified definition above implies the existence of a boundary by suggesting that an autopoietic entity must have an interior. ...
... "An autopoietic system is a network of processes which produces all the components whose internal production is necessary to maintain the network operating as a unit." [18] Since its inception, there was an assertion that for a system to be considered autopoietic, it must define a boundary that separates itself from its environment [18][19][20][21][22][23][24][25][26]. Even the Biomimetics 2024, 9, simplified definition above implies the existence of a boundary by suggesting that an autopoietic entity must have an interior. ...
... Biomimetics 2024, 9, x FOR PEER REVIEW 2 of 19 Since its inception, there was an assertion that for a system to be considered autopoietic, it must define a boundary that separates itself from its environment [18][19][20][21][22][23][24][25][26]. Even the simplified definition above implies the existence of a boundary by suggesting that an autopoietic entity must have an interior. ...
Article
Full-text available
Ever since Varela and Maturana proposed the concept of autopoiesis as the minimal requirement for life, there has been a focus on cellular systems that erect topological boundaries to separate themselves from their surrounding environment. Here, we reconsider whether the existence of such a spatial boundary is strictly necessary for self-producing entities. This work presents a novel computational model of a minimal autopoietic system inspired by dendrites and molecular dynamic simulations in three-dimensional space. A series of simulation experiments where the metabolic pathways of a particular autocatalytic set are successively inhibited until autocatalytic entities that could be considered autopoietic are produced. These entities maintain their distinctness in an environment containing multiple identical instances of the entities without the existence of a topological boundary. This gives rise to the concept of a metabolic boundary which manifests as emergent self-selection criteria for the processes of self-production without any need for unique identifiers. However, the adoption of such a boundary comes at a cost, as these autopoietic entities are less suited to their simulated environment than their autocatalytic counterparts. Finally, this work showcases a generalized metabolism-centered approach to the study of autopoiesis that can be applied to both physical and abstract systems alike.
... This property is part of the definition of autopoiesis ('self-production'), a concept that Maturana and Varela introduced to characterize living organisms [11,[22][23][24]. The second defining property of autopoietic systems is that they produce their own topological boundary, such as the membrane that separates living cells from their environment. ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper summarizes and reviews Chemical Organization Theory (COT), a formalism for the analysis of complex, self-organizing systems across multiple disciplines. Its elements are resources and reactions. A reaction maps a set of resources onto another set, thus representing an elementary process that transforms resources into new resources. Reaction networks self-organize into invariant subnetworks, called ‘organizations’, which are attractors of their dynamics. These are characterized by closure (no new resources are added) and self-maintenance (no existing resources are lost). Thus, they provide a simple model of autopoiesis: the organization persistently recreates its own components. The resilience of organizations in the face of perturbations depends on properties such as the size of their basin of attraction and the redundancy of their reaction pathways. Application domains of COT include the origin of life, systems biology, cognition, ecology, Gaia theory, sustainability, consciousness, and social systems.
... Thereby, we are building a meaningful and transformative rapport between agents and their environment leading-in the best case-to their flourishing. This gives rise to several properties and implications that are interesting with regard to our question of enacting the self (or an organization) by interacting with the environment: (a) Living and social systems exhibit self-oscillations (Eigenschwingungen); being in resonance with oneself is a prerequisite for engaging in resonance with the environment (compare, for instance, the homeostatic equilibrium found in autopoietic systems [95][96][97]). (b) Only if a system has found its self-resonance, it will be able to articulate its "own voice" to another system. ...
Article
Full-text available
The role of spirituality in organizations has received increasing attention over recent years. The purpose of this conceptual paper is to take up this shift and develop the foundations for an alternative approach to knowledge management: Spiritual Knowledge Management. A key question in spirituality concerns the unfolding of the identity (of an organization) or the self toward a “higher end” or purpose. We propose the concept of the phronetically enacted self (understood here both in an individual and an organizational sense) that helps us conceive of how this unfolding can be achieved in a thriving and sustainable manner. The self is conceptualized as a highly dynamic and emergent “entity” that is grounded in a continuous process of becoming and of transitions transforming a state of potentiality into a state of actuality and fulfillment. Insights from the theory of spirituality, enactive cognitive science, the theory of potentials/possibility studies, phronetic organizations, and resonance theory lead us to a novel understanding of knowledge-driven organizations embodying a spirituality-based and, as a consequence, (regenerative) sustainable approach. Finally, we will develop the basic characteristics and leverage points for transformative shifts toward sustainability in organizations.
... Both are to some degree transparent containers, filled with a diversity of interacting "molecules" or "species" that are continually being consumed and produced, together forming a self-maintaining, closed network of reactions. Thus, the overall system is autopoietic, that is, self-producing (Heylighen, Beigi, & Veloz, 2015;Mingers, 1994;Razeto-Barry, 2012). The complex, branching cycles of consumption and production reactions constitute the cell's metabolism. ...
Chapter
Full-text available
A unique exploration of teleonomy—also known as “evolved purposiveness”—as a major influence in evolution by a broad range of specialists in biology and the philosophy of science. The evolved purposiveness of living systems, termed “teleonomy” by chronobiologist Colin Pittendrigh, has been both a major outcome and causal factor in the history of life on Earth. Many theorists have appreciated this over the years, going back to Lamarck and even Darwin in the nineteenth century. In the mid-twentieth century, however, the complex, dynamic process of evolution was simplified into the one-way, bottom-up, single gene-centered paradigm widely known as the modern synthesis. In Evolution “On Purpose,” edited by Peter A. Corning, Stuart A. Kauffman, Denis Noble, James A. Shapiro, Richard I. Vane-Wright, and Addy Pross, some twenty theorists attempt to modify this reductive approach by exploring in depth the different ways in which living systems have themselves shaped the course of evolution. Evolution “On Purpose” puts forward a more inclusive theoretical synthesis that goes far beyond the underlying principles and assumptions of the modern synthesis to accommodate work since the 1950s in molecular genetics, developmental biology, epigenetic inheritance, genomics, multilevel selection, niche construction, physiology, behavior, biosemiotics, chemical reaction theory, and other fields. In the view of the authors, active biological processes are responsible for the direction and the rate of evolution. Essays in this collection grapple with topics from the two-way “read-write” genome to cognition and decision-making in plants to the niche-construction activities of many organisms to the self-making evolution of humankind. As this collection compellingly shows, and as bacterial geneticist James Shapiro emphasizes, “The capacity of living organisms to alter their own heredity is undeniable.”
Article
The growing differentiation of specialties in education creates the need for a common framework. This chapter discusses the basic premises of complex dynamical systems theory (CDST), its intellectual foundations, and its applicability to the field of education, with a particular focus on the areas of learning and development, school reform, and the persistence of inequity in society. The vocabulary of CDST is reviewed and applied to these problem areas to help deepen our understanding of the challenges facing policymakers and practitioners and provide growing points for the integration of these areas of knowledge into a coherent basis for further research and exploration. The differences between CDST and traditional research paradigms are also duly considered.
Article
The ongoing post-normal times face two intertwining imperatives: sustainability and digital technology. Interestingly, the languages that address these imperatives are increasingly making use of concepts historically associated to or confined to the biological sciences, in particular botany and plant physiology. We address this phenomenon by applying two distinct but interacting conceptual frameworks. First, that of language ecology, i.e., the study of interactions between any given language and its environment. Language has an anticipatory nature, since it is an essential part of how we organise memory and past experience, therefore helping us to understand the present and to project the future. This paper surveys five biological concepts: autopoiesis, ecosystem , exaptation, regeneration, seed. By using an academic search engine, we assessed how often they have been used in academic publications related to biology/botany as compared to other fields. We found that their meanings are being expanded by their use in the sustainability and/or digital technology realms. Motivations for these uses include biomimetics, bio-philia and/or, more simply, manipulation of words with the intention to create specific public or private rhetoric. Second, we examined this linguistic pattern as a symptom of ontological expansion, i.e., the integration and dialogue between technical innovation, philosophy and biology creating space for the emergence of new domains of experience and meanings that did not exist before. This research indicates that botany-and plant physiology in particular-can be an important source of inspiration for futures studies.
Article
Full-text available
Autoethnographic narratives are ways of normalising and giving meaning to the human experience, allowing the reader to resonate with what is relevant and important in the writer’s experience, while generating new insights and knowledge we would not otherwise access. Using my doctoral journey of striking moments and the shifts created in me, in this paper, I argue that human experiences must be valued as equal to diagnostic and objectivist approaches in the pursuit of knowledge. By juxtaposing my autoethnographic narrative with the Theory of Autopoiesis, acting as both a framework of analysis and metaphor, I offer my emotional process as a political representation, a questioning of power paradigms and a source of knowledge and support to other researchers. The rendering of my journey, from working in and believing in organisations governed by a business logic and rational economic theory, to daring to challenge such discursive powers, shows what is possible through conscious noticing, embracing, and transformation. I argue that by combining scientific theories with analytical autoethnography, we can bridge sciences and communities of practice, and open doors for the application of autoethnography in new professional domains, thereby significantly contributing to an adjustment of research practices and to what counts as knowledge.
Chapter
Our world has always been changing, sometimes rather gradually, at other times more radically. In today’s world, we see both tremendous challenges and potential to shape it in a new and desirable direction. In almost every domain of our lives we are challenged by high levels of volatility, uncertainty, complexity, and ambiguousness (“VUCA world”). In this context of profound technological, digital, social, and political changes and transformations, we have to ask ourselves: what is it that makes us humans human? What does a meaningful and joyful relationship between humans, technology, and the future look like? How do we meet the challenges of increasingly blurred borders between humans and technology in a more human(e) manner? Which skills and mindsets do we need to deal with our uncertain and unpredictable future in order to co-shape it in a purposeful and thriving manner? In this chapter, we will explore the challenges of a VUCA world and take a closer look at what their implications are for our educational systems. We will develop a future-oriented perspective on learning that is based on the concept of learning as co-becoming with the world. We will discuss that this requires futures literacies, such as sense-making capabilities, a constructivist epistemology, systems thinking, designerly ways of thinking and making, and most importantly, a capacity to identify and make use of future potentials. We will both discuss theoretical foundations (e.g., from cognitive science/enactive cognition approaches, systems thinking, etc.) and practical implications, skills, mindsets, and a concrete case study illustrating these concepts.
Article
Full-text available
Este artículo introduce la teoría de Niklas Luhmann en las investigaciones actuales sobre la identidad del yo, explorando sus afinidades con las teorías enactivistas y fenomenológicas. Aunque ambos enfoques reconocen la importancia de la dimensión social, han pasado por alto la sociología de Luhmann a pesar de sus compatibilidades. Por otro lado, el diálogo con estos enfoques puede enriquecer a la teoría luhmanniana con el fin de esclarecer algunos de sus elementos problemáticos. El objetivo principal es abordar el problema de los sistemas psíquicos y su acoplamiento con el cuerpo. El artículo propone cuatro tesis: 1) la teoría de la autopoiesis proporciona una concepción generalizable de la identidaden diversos sistemas; 2) la noción fenomenológica del yo mínimo equivale a la identidad autopoiética del sistema psíquico; 3) el yo de la conciencia implica un acoplamiento con el organismo biológico; 4) el médium del sentido permite la interpenetración entre conciencia y organismo. Esta última tesis cuestiona un presupuesto fundamental de la teoría de Luhmann, pero se argumenta la necesidad de revisarlo para facilitar el diálogo y el enriquecimiento mutuo entre los diferentes enfoques.
Book
How did life begin on the Earth? The units of life are cells, which can be defined as bounded systems of molecules that capture energy and nutrients from the environment -- systems that expand, reproduce, and evolve over time, often into more complex systems. This book is the proceedings of a unique meeting, sponsored by NATO and held in Maratea, Italy, that brought together for the first time an international group of investigators who share an interest in how molecules self-assemble into supramolecular structures, and how those structures may have contributed to the origin of life. The book is written at a moderately technical level, appropriate for use by researchers and by students in upper-level undergraduate and graduate courses in biochemistry and molecular biology. The overall interest of its subject matter provides an excellent introduction for students who wish to understand how the foundational knowledge of chemistry and physics can be applied to one of the most fundamental questions now facing the scientific community. The editors are pioneers in defining what we mean by the living state, particularly the manner in which simple molecular systems can assume complex associations and functions, including the ability to reproduce. Each chapter of the book presents an up-to-date report of highly significant research. Two of the authors received medals from the National Academy of Science USA in 1994, and other research reported in the book has been featured in internationally recognized journals such Scientific American, Time, and Discover.
Book
Stuart Kauffman here presents a brilliant new paradigm for evolutionary biology, one that extends the basic concepts of Darwinian evolution to accommodate recent findings and perspectives from the fields of biology, physics, chemistry and mathematics. The book drives to the heart of the exciting debate on the origins of life and maintenance of order in complex biological systems. It focuses on the concept of self-organization: the spontaneous emergence of order widely observed throughout nature. Kauffman here argues that self-organization plays an important role in the emergence of life itself and may play as fundamental a role in shaping life's subsequent evolution as does the Darwinian process of natural selection. Yet until now no systematic effort has been made to incorporate the concept of self-organization into evolutionary theory. The construction requirements which permit complex systems to adapt remain poorly understood, as is the extent to which selection itself can yield systems able to adapt more successfully. This book explores these themes. It shows how complex systems, contrary to expectations, can spontaneously exhibit stunning degrees of order, and how this order, in turn, is essential for understanding the emergence and development of life on Earth. Topics include the new biotechnology of applied molecular evolution, with its important implications for developing new drugs and vaccines; the balance between order and chaos observed in many naturally occurring systems; new insights concerning the predictive power of statistical mechanics in biology; and other major issues. Indeed, the approaches investigated here may prove to be the new center around which biological science itself will evolve. The work is written for all those interested in the cutting edge of research in the life sciences.
Book
Systems theorists see common principles in the structure and operation of systems of all kinds and sizes. They promote an interdisciplinary science adapted for a universal application with a common language and area of concepts. In order to solve problems, make recommendations and predict the future, they use theories, models and concepts from the vast area of general systems theory. This approach is chosen as a means to overcome the fragmentation of knowledge and the isolation of the specialist but also to find new approaches to problems created by earlier ‘solution of problems.’ This revised and updated second edition of General Systems Theory - Ideas and Applications includes new systems theories and a new chapter on self-organization and evolution. The book summarizes most of the fields of systems theory and its application systems science in one volume. It provides a quick and readable reference guide for future learning containing both general theories and practical applications without the use of complicated mathematics. © 2005 by World Scientific Publishing Co. Pte. Ltd. All rights reserved.
Article
Until now, there are three evolutionary models: I) The Synthetic Theory of Evolution (sTE) also named as the Neo-Darwinian model; II) The Neutral Theory of Evolution (NTE) with its daughter the Nearly-Neutral Theory of Evolution (NNTE); III) The Theory of Evolution by means of Natural Drift (NDTE) (Valenzuela 2007, 2009). All these theories accept that variation of genomes of living beings emerges by mutation. They disagree in relation of the causes of the acquisition and maintenance of the living being organization. STE proposes that the main factor for the acquisition and maintenance of fixated organization is selection and a marginal role of genetic drift. NTE proposed that the acquisition and maintenance of fixated organization is drift with a marginal role of selection, its daughter the NNTE includes besides selection with coefficients similar to the mutation rates. NDTE is derived from the conception of living beings as autopoietic processes, thus the acquisition and maintenance of organization occur by natural drift and living beings are always adapted. The extreme importance given to the factors of evolution, within each theory, has lead to absurd exaggerations that seems now illusions, nightmares or simply madness.
Article
What is the definition of life? I remember a conference of the scientific elite that sought to answer that question. Is an enzyme alive? Is a virus alive? Is a cell alive? After many hours of launching promising balloons that defined life in a sentence, followed by equally conclusive punctures of these balloons, a solution seemed at hand: “The ability to reproduce—that is the essence characteristic of life” said one statesman of science. Everyone nodded in agreement that the essence of a life was the ability to reproduce, until one small voice was heard. “Then one rabbit is dead. Two rabbits—a male and female—are alive but either one alone is dead.” At that point, we all became convinced that although everyone knows what life is there is no simple definition of life, If I were forced to rush in where angels fear to tread, I would offer “a living organism is an organized unit, which can carry out metabolic reactions, defend itself against injury, respond to stimuli, and has the capacity to be at least a partner in reproduction.” But I’m not happy with such a brief definition. When allowed more extensive reflection, however, I think the fundamental pillars on which life as we know it is based can be defined. By “pillars” I mean the essential principles—thermodynamic and kinetic—by which a living system operates.