ArticlePDF Available

On the Problem of Formalism in Economics

Authors:
  • Loughborough University London

Abstract

The author analyses "critical realist" economic methodology with respect to application of mathematical modeling. He indicates strong and weak sides of critical realist argument, putting emphasis on the works by T. Lawson. An alternative view on the role of formal technique in economics is proposed, taking into account the diversity of interpretative contexts while applying mathematical models.
On the Problem of Formalism in Economics
Geoffrey M. Hodgson
3 February 2005
An earlier version was published in the Post-Autistic Economics Review, Issue 28, 25 October
2004
This version was published in:
Economics in the Shadows of Darwin and Marx: Essays on Institutional and Evolutionary
Themes, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, 2006, ch. 7.
‘O Probleme formalisma v economicheskoi teorii’ (in Russian), Voprosy Economiki, 2006,
no. 3, pp. 112-124.
The Business School, University of Hertfordshire, De Havilland Campus, Hatfield, Hertfordshire AL10 9AB, UK
http://www.herts.ac.uk/business http://www.geoffrey-hodgson.ws
g.m.hodgson@herts.ac.uk
- 1 -
On the Problem of Formalism in Economics
Geoffrey M. Hodgson
Modern Economics is Sick
In his Reorienting Economics, Tony Lawson cites this magnificently appropriate quotation by
Mark Blaug (1997, p. 3):
Modern economics is sick. Economics has increasingly become an intellectual game
played for its own sake and not for its practical consequences for understanding the
economic world. Economists have converted the subject into a sort of social mathematics
in which analytical rigour is everything and practical relevance is nothing.
I believe that on this issue, Lawson, Blaug and I are in agreement: the victory of technique
over substance is a chronic problem within modern economics. Although the victory of
formalism can be dated to the 1950s (Blaug 1999, 2003), by the 1980s the problem had
become much more serious. Because mathematics has swamped the curricula in leading
universities and graduate schools, student economists are neither encouraged nor equipped to
analyze real world economies and institutions. Arjo Klamer and David Colander (1990, p. 18)
reported a survey which showed that only 3 per cent of graduate students on top US
economics programmes perceived ‘having a thorough knowledge of the economy’ to be ‘very
important’ for professional success, while 65 per cent thought that ‘being smart in the sense of
problem-solving’ is what matters, and 57 per cent believed that ‘excellence in mathematics’
was very important.
In 1988 the American Economic Association set up a Commission on the state of graduate
education in economics in the US. In a crushing indictment, the Commission expressed its
fear that ‘graduate programs may be turning out a generation with too many idiot savants
skilled in technique but innocent of real economic issues’ (Krueger et al, 1991, pp. 1044–5).
Alan Blinder (1990, p. 445), a member of the Commission, commented:
Both students and faculty find economics obsessed with technique over substance . . . the
many macro and micro theory exams the Commission examined . . . tested mathematical
puzzle-solving ability, not substantive knowledge about economics . . . Only 14 percent of
the students report that their core courses put substantial emphasis on ‘applying economic
theory to real-world problems.’
Alarm bells concerning technique displacing substance in economics have been sounding for
many years (Ward, 1972). However, although mainstream economics has made some
significant theoretical advances in the 1990s, including an increasing adoption of institutional
and evolutionary themes, the situation concerning formalism has not got any better.
Perhaps the most serious emerging problem is that the graduate students of the 1980s and
1990s, who are skilled in technique but who have an impoverished understanding of
economic principles and their history, are now beginning to achieve positions of seniority and
- 2 -
influence in the university departments, associations and journals of the economics
profession. Their growing power and influence will ensure that formalism further consolidates
its overwhelming hegemony, to the detriment of wider-ranging conceptual and
methodological enquiry. This problem is particularly serious in Britain and America, where
formalism has achieved its earliest and most complete victory. But the process is delayed
rather than absent elsewhere.
Both Blaug and Lawson face the problem of formalism head-on. But, as I shall elaborate
below, their evaluations differ. Blaug complains that formalism has been associated with a
detachment of economics from substantial and practical issues. Lawson’s (1997, 2003) attack
is more extensive and radical. He develops at length a methodological critique of what he
calls ‘deductivism’ and identifies this as the root of the formalist malady. One of my main
purposes here is to examine some prominent aspects of Lawson’s critique of formalism. I
shall argue that his stance is too limiting, with the expected outcome that mathematical and
econometric tools will be illegitimate except under ‘seemingly rare’ (Lawson, 2003, p. 21)
conditions.
Tony Lawson’s Critique of Formalism
Lawson affirms that the systems addressed by the social sciences are open, in that they are
subject to multiple extrinsic and intrinsic disturbances. This makes the task of prediction
either difficult or impossible. For Lawson (1997, p. 288), ‘event prediction is usually
infeasible’ and ‘in any case not required for a successful science of economics’.
Lawson (1997, pp. 16-17) argues that ‘deductivism’ presumes ‘event regularities’ or
‘constant conjunctions of events or states of affairs’ with regularities of the form ‘whenever
event x then event y’. Philosophically, this is a rather atypical definition of deductivism,
because it refers to empirical regularities concerning events rather than logical deductions
concerning propositions. He seems to suggest that logical or mathematical constructions, if
they are to be of relevance or use, must be some kind of map of reality at the level of events.
For example, Lawson (2003, p. 22) writes of the importance of a ‘“fit” with reality’.
From this stance, his critique of the use of formalism in economics readily follows. Social
reality is an open system, generally lacking in ‘constant conjunctions of events’. By contrast,
in either a strict or a stochastic sense, formal models generate regularities in the form: if x
then y. Such event regularities are highly limited in the social realm. Accordingly, there is a
general mismatch between formal models and reality. If economics is to progress, then formal
modelling must be limited those cases where such regularities pertain, and these appear to be
rather rare.
In the absence of formal models, what does the theorist do? Lawson realizes that no theory
(formal or discursive) can proceed without some degree of abstraction: it is impossible to
consider all elements and interactions at once. Indeed, he develops his methodological notion
of abstraction at length. But here he faces a difficulty. If abstraction is necessary, and it
involves the limitation of the sphere of consideration and the exclusion of additional relations
or disturbing forces, then doesn’t this too imply the assumption of a closed system? Stephen
Nash (2004) has recently argued in the affirmative, suggesting that Lawson too must assume
conditions or forms of closure. To some extent, however, Lawson (1997, p. 236) anticipates
this objection. He proposes a distinction between ‘abstraction’ and ‘isolation’ in the following
terms:
- 3 -
When we focus upon varying productivity performances here, conditions of work there,
rising or falling unemployment rates, and so on, we do not suppose that these features we
choose to emphasise exist in isolation, even as a temporary, heuristic, measure. To do so
is to assume a totally different world from the one in which we live, and one that has no
bearing upon it. … In short, there is literally a world of difference between leaving
something (temporarily) out of focus and treating it as though it does not exist. The
achieving of an abstraction and treating something as though it existed in isolation are
not the same thing at all.
He uses this distinction to protect his argument against the objection that his method of
abstraction also implies the assumption of closure; he argues that abstraction does not imply
closure but isolation does. With some important nuances and qualifications, Lawson (1997,
pp. 131-3) associates the notion of isolation with the work of Uskali Mäki (1992, 1994) and
contrasts isolation with his own concept of abstraction. However, I shall argue later below
that the distinction is, at least in prominent practical instances, difficult to sustain.
Lawson takes a relatively extreme position in his attitude to formalism in economics, even
among critics of mainstream economics, and even among the school of ‘critical realists’ to
which he belongs. For example, critical realists such as Paul Downward (2000, 2003) have
defended a more frequent use of some econometric techniques. Lawson points to very few
concrete instances where econometrics has been appropriately deployed; Downward points to
several. And the critical realist Erik Olin Wright (1994, pp, 183-9) has strongly supported the
use of ‘explicit abstract models, sometimes highly formalized as in game theory’ and other
‘rational choice models’. Lawson takes an extreme position, even within critical realism. An
extreme position such as Lawson’s is not necessarily inappropriate or wrong by virtue of its
extremism, but it does invite repeated criticism.
Perhaps as a consequence, in Lawson’s later writing there has been a slight shift of tone and
emphasis, if not substance as well. For example, Lawson (1999, pp. 7-8) proposes that from
the fact that ‘the world is open and structured, it does not follow’ that economists ‘ought
thereby not to engage at all in formalistic methods such as econometrics.’ He continues:
The possibility of successes with the latter requires local closures. … Critical realism
thus cannot and does not rule out a priori their limited occurrence. Rather, critical
realism adopts an essentially ex posteriori orientation … the opponent is the advocate of
any form of a priori dogma.
With some amendments, Lawson (2003, pp. xix, 27, 178-9) repeats a similar argument in
several places in his latest book. Again and again he insists that he is not against the use of
econometrics or models in principle, but that they are of highly limited use given the closure
conditions upon which they depend. He writes that ‘a blanket rejection of econometrics, or
indeed of any other method, is not a stance that is, or could be, sponsored in critical realism.’
What is opposed is not econometrics but ‘the reduction of economics to formalistic analysis.’
But he then goes on to say that the ‘application of formalistic methods requires certain
(closure) conditions constituting special configurations of social reality that (unsurprisingly
from the perspective sustained) have turned out to be rather rare.’ In a recent essay, Lawson
(2004) again repeats his insistence that he is not ‘anti-mathematics’. But his expectation
remains that the conditions for its effective and proper use would be rare.
In these passages at least two features are emphasized. The first is a strong, sincere and
repeated claim of anti-dogmatism concerning whether or not mathematics can or should be
used. But he lays down criteria for its use, including the requirement of (approximated) local
closure. As a result of these criteria, the specific measure of his own anti-dogmatism, in
- 4 -
practice rather than in intention, is how far he would admit that open systems might appear (or
be approximated) in reality. Lawson argues that his critical realist perspective suggests at the
outset that they are ‘limited’ or even ‘rather rare’. Accordingly, the ontological arguments in
Lawson’s critical realism lead him right away to expect that the possibilities for formalism are
highly restricted. This sets limits on his anti-dogmatist stance, despite his pronounced anti-
dogmatist intentions. Although Lawson imposes no absolute normative ban on the use of
mathematics, his arguments limit its legitimate use to ‘rare’ circumstances only.
Generally, one can also ask if an all-pervasive, anti-dogmatist stance were possible. Some
prior ‘dogmatic’ presuppositions are necessary for any engagement with the world. We
assume that our car will start and the sun will rise in the morning. We assume that the face we
recognise is the face of the same person with which it was associated yesterday. We assume
that the meanings of words have not changed overnight. The removal of all dogma would
mean a disabling nihilism of universal scepticism. In such circumstances, no observation
could be completed and no theory could be established. Human activity would become
paralyzed if we ceased to believe in the essential dogma that most of the natural regularities
and social institutions of today will survive until tomorrow. We often admire anti-dogmatism
as a commendable personality trait, but modern philosophy of science upholds that some
considerable degree of dogmatism is unavoidable. As Charles Sanders Peirce (1934, p. 156)
put it long ago, contrary to René Descartes we ‘cannot begin from complete doubt. We must
begin with all the prejudices which we actually have’.
The second feature of Lawson’s argument above is the proclamation of ‘an essentially ex
posteriori orientation’, although what precisely is meant by this is insufficiently clear. Critical
realists rightly emphasize the importance and priority of ontological commitments. Consider
fundamental ontological commitments such as ‘ubiquity determinism’ (Bhaskar, 1975, pp. 70-
1), which means that every event is deemed to have a cause. We have known at least since the
days of David Hume that it is impossible to deduce causes a posteriori from our experience of
events. It is in the very nature of such primary ontological commitments that they are neither
based on nor deduced from evidence or experience. One of the crucial aspects of the
philosophical assault on positivism in the middle of the twentieth century was the
reaffirmation of the importance of such prior ontological commitments, which cannot be
established by appeal to evidence or experience alone (Quine, 1951; Caldwell, 1982). So one
is left wondering what ‘an essentially ex posteriori orientation’ means, and how it can be
reconciled with an insistence on the primacy of ontology.
Again I detect a slight post-1997 shift of tone and emphasis when Lawson (2003, pp. 20-1)
openly discusses the possibility that econometrics might be of use in some instances:
Clive Granger has argued convincingly that it is possible to use econometrics to provide
relatively successful short-run forecasts of phenomena such as electricity loads and peaks
in regions wherein one factor, temperature, or more specifically the extreme cold,
dominates behaviour. … The point remains, however, that the sorts of conditions in
question appear a posteriori not to be typical of the social realm. Rather, as I say, social
reality is found to be a quintessentially open, structured, dynamic and highly internally-
related system, amongst other things, whilst the conditions for achieving a local closure
are seemingly rare.
This is the only example I can find where Lawson has pointed to a specific piece of
econometric analysis and acknowledged its legitimacy. Note, however, the strictness of the
key condition involved. According to this passage, for econometrics to be applicable, ‘local
closure’ must be actually achieved, not merely approximated. However, it is clearly the case a
- 5 -
posteriori that electricity consumption (even in cold regions) is a feature of an open rather
than a closed system. For instance, electricity consumption is generally affected by its price.
Such prices are heavily influenced by global market conditions. Global markets are far from
being closed systems. Granger did not provide an example which establishes local closure.
Granger’s (2004) defence of econometrics applies to a broader class of phenomena. By the
logic of his own argument, Lawson should have deemed econometrics to be also inapplicable
to this electricity generation situation described by Granger. Lawson’s single claimed
example of the legitimate use of econometrics turns out to be illicit according to his own key
criterion.
Indeed, if we require that formal models can only be applied in contexts where local closure
is actually achieved, then this would mean that such models were inappropriate in other
sciences and disciplines, such as biology, physics or engineering. Generally, in multiple
contexts, in both the natural and social world, such closures are absent, as Roy Bhaskar
(1975) as well as Lawson himself have emphasized. If formal models require strict local
closure, then formal models are never appropriate. But this would overlook the achievement
of mathematical models in some sciences. It may be suggested that local closure is sometimes
approximated in physics, and because of this some formal models can be of use. But it must
be added that models generated through experiments in situations where local closure is
approximated have often been demonstrated to be of considerable value in much wider
applications. Furthermore, models and simulations have also been used with some success in
biology and evolutionary anthropology, which face a high degree of complexity and openness
(Murray, 1989; Boyd and Richerson, 1985).
At least in recent seminar presentations, Lawson has amended his position still further, by
proposing that econometrics might apply when local closure is ‘approximated in reality’. This
formulation contrasts with that in his two (1997, 2003) books, which generally insist that local
closure conditions must actually apply for formalism to be viable. From his amended
standpoint, admitting a degree of approximation to closure, it would be possible to admit the
Granger example as a case of the legitimate application of econometric techniques. The
general problem for Lawson in applying this revised criterion more widely is that the degree
of acceptable approximation is left unspecified. In general, once the insistence on the actual
achievement of local closure is removed, and approximations to closure are admitted, then the
door to econometrics is unlocked and opened.
Some Key Problems and Omissions in Tony Lawson’s Critique
Much of Lawson’s discussion of formalism concerns econometrics. He gives insufficient
attention to other applications of mathematical techniques, which serve primary purposes
other than the prediction or explanation of measurable variables. Such additional applications
of formalism include (a) heuristics and (b) internal critiques. I shall address each of these in
turn.
The purpose of a heuristic is to identify possible causal mechanisms that form part of a
more complex and inevitably open system. Heuristics can be useful without necessarily
making adequate predictions or closely matching existing data. Their purpose is to establish a
plausible segment of a causal story, without necessarily giving an adequate or complete
explanation of the phenomena to which they relate.
An example of a formal heuristic that has been persuasive in economics is the ethnic
segregation model constructed by Thomas Schelling (1969). Using a very simple model of
housing location, Schelling showed that ethnic segregation can result even from very small
- 6 -
feedback effects. Even if people only have a very slight preference for their own ethnic group,
this can be enough to cause migration out of mixed ethnic areas, with the end result of
segregated ethnic ghettos. The model is extremely simple, and hardly realistic in its detailed
assumptions. However, making the model more complicated and ‘realistic’ would be beyond
the point, partly because it is obvious that similar outcomes could result from a more
complicated model. Instead, the Schelling model points to a credible mechanism that shows
that ethnic segregation does not necessarily depend upon the actions of bigoted racists. Such
racists exist in the real world, so their inclusion in the model would make it more realistic. But
this would defeat the object of the model, which is to show that segregation might result even
without them. The model abstracts from the more forceful versions of racism that we find in
the real world to establish this key point. In this case, the power of the model is helped by its
unrealisticness. The power of the model lies in its capacity to abstract a plausible bit hitherto
neglected causal mechanism.
In a very useful discussion of such ‘credible worlds’, Robert Sugden (2000) asks probing
questions concerning the role and ‘realisticness’ of this and other heuristic models in
economics. These heuristic models have the paradoxical claim that they are literally
unrealistic yet they seem to illuminate important aspects of reality. Using the Schelling model
alongside George Akerlof’s (1970) famous article on the ‘market for lemons’, which again
claims to establish meaningful propositions about the world on the basis on an admittedly
unrealistic model, Sugden (p. 28) describes these models as ‘credible counterfactual worlds’
that give ‘some warrant for making inductive inferences from model to the real world.’
In no case can the construction of a heuristic or counterfactual model clinch the argument
concerning the causal mechanisms that actually exist in the real world. However, what they
sometimes do show – as in the case of the Schelling model – is that outcomes might not
necessarily result from the causal factors that may be presumed at first sight. To complete the
argument, further theoretical development and empirical enquiry are always required.
I have suggested above that heuristics are appropriate if they successfully abstract an
important causal mechanism in reality. Accordingly, heuristics relate to the very process of
abstraction that Lawson himself highlights. But Lawson suggests that heuristics are isolations
rather than abstractions. So here I must return to Lawson’s (1997, p. 236) attempted
distinction between isolation and abstraction, as quoted above. According to him, the key
difference is ‘between leaving something (temporarily) out of focus and treating it as though
it does not exist’. Again take the Schelling model as an example. Schelling himself accepts
that bigoted racists exist, yet he leaves them out of his model. The purpose of the model is not
to excuse or deny racism, but the more severe forms of racism are deliberately removed.
Nevertheless, the model is extremely and worryingly persuasive.
No-one to my knowledge, including Schelling himself, has suggested that such as model is
a complete or adequate causal representation of the processes underlying the emergence of
ethnic segregation in reality. The model is simply a heuristic step along the road towards that
more complete end. More generally, no sensible mainstream economist would deny that the
world is open, and no adequate presentation of a formal model would omit to mention that
other (omitted) causal mechanisms exist.
Ultimately, Lawson’s attempted distinction between abstraction and isolation hinges on the
precise meaning of notions such as ‘treating [that which is left out of the picture] as though it
does not exist’ and the implied distinction between a ‘temporary heuristic’ and ‘leaving
something temporarily out of focus’. Yet Lawson is insufficiently precise here. If I ‘focus’ on
the workings of a national economy (perhaps without building a mathematical model) and
- 7 -
ignore its trade with other nations, then in what sense might this qualify as a temporary
account, rather than a presumption that such exports and imports do not exist? Surely, some
verbal statement would be required, acknowledging the existence of international trade,
explaining its omission from the current discussion, and suggesting that further work must be
done to incorporate it into the analysis. But this is also the kind of necessary qualification that
we should expect from the best presentations of heuristic models. On the other hand, it would
be impossible to mention all the things that we have left out of the account. In this sense all
theory is ‘temporary’. But do such unmentioned omissions amount to treating some causal
linkages as though they do not exist? If this were the cases, then every theory, including non-
formal, discursive theory, by Lawson’s criteria is a failure. Once we try to apply Lawson’s
criteria, then their insufficiency and vagueness become apparent, and his attempted distinction
between abstraction and isolation is revealed as highly problematic.
A crucial point here is that in economics we should not and cannot judge models in
isolation. Lawson treats any model as if it were alone an intrinsic claim to be a partial map of
the world. Yet the meaning of any heuristic model depends upon an interpretive framework
that is not contained in the formalities of the model itself. If heuristic models are suitably
hedged and qualified, in the manner suggested above, then these qualifications form part of
the interpretative apparatus for the model. If heuristic models are treated within an adequate
interpretative context, then such heuristic packages can successfully defend themselves
against the charge that they treat other aspects of reality as though they do not exist.
By contrast, Lawson himself isolates formal models from their interpretative contexts,
treating these as if they do not or need not exist, and denies the validity of even ‘temporary’
heuristic models per se. The strictures of appropriate contextualization that Lawson rightly
requires of discursive theory should apply to his treatment of formal models as well.
Bringing the interpretative framework of a heuristic model into the picture is highly
important in appraising the problem of excessive or misplaced formalism in economics. An
alternative diagnosis emerges, in which the malady is not the use of formalism as such but the
inadequacy and underdevelopment of the interpretative context in which they are placed.
Technique can take priority over substance as a result of the relative neglect of interpretative
context. An adequate interpretative framework would depend on the discussion of the genesis,
meaning and methodological significance of key concepts that are involved in the model or its
interpretation. This is never a small task, and if done properly it will be at least as weighty as
the formal technique of the model itself. Yet in modern economics such interpretative and
conceptual matters are often marginalized and underdeveloped. I contend that this is one of
the main problems with formalism in economics today.
While Lawson implicitly treats formal models as if they were claims to map the world, his
explicit metaphor is more frequently of the model as a tool. For example, Lawson (2003, p.
12) notes the ontological mismatch between formal models and reality and suggests that this
is grounds to question their use: ‘Few people … would attempt to use a comb to write a letter
… or a drill to clean a window.’ This argument is not as illuminating as it may seem at first
sight. Of course, we would use a pen to write a letter and a clean cloth to clean a window. Yet
the ontology of pens is very different from that of letters, and likewise there is a big
ontological difference between clean cloths and dirty windows. So there is nothing in this
appropriateness-of-tools argument that rules out, for instance, using closed models to help
understand an open reality.
I now turn to the second use of formalism that is neglected by Lawson: that of an internal
critique. Generally, the impact of an effective internal critique is negative rather than positive;
- 8 -
it shows the limits of an existing theory rather than building a new one. It is nevertheless
important. Consider the example of the critique of mainstream capital theory by Piero Sraffa
(1960) and others. By developing a model with disaggregated rather than aggregated physical
capital, Sraffa showed that the measure of capital could not be independent of profits, wages
or prices. Consequently, any attempt to explain the latter by means of an aggregated capital
variable must assume that which it has to explain. The validity of this argument was later
accepted by Paul Samuelson and others (Harcourt, 1972). It meant that several of the models
and arguments used in the mainstream theory of capital and distribution were either invalid or
dependent on highly restrictive assumptions.
A demonstration that a widely adopted approach depends on restrictive or even implausible
assumptions is a key feature of many of the successful and significant internal critiques that
we find in economics. Other examples include works by Rolf Mantel (1974) and Robert
Rowthorn (1999). Mantel and several other theorists showed that even with the assumption of
individual utility-maximization, the excess demand functions in an exchange economy can
take almost any form, and there is thus no basis in standard general equilibrium theory for the
assumption that they are generally downward sloping. Their work proved very influential in
bringing the microfoundations project in general equilibrium theory to an end (Rizvi, 1994).
Rowthorn showed that prominent models used by governments in macroeconomic policy-
making are based on highly restrictive and unwarranted assumptions.
Such critiques do not themselves provide new theories, although they may suggest some
appropriate measures and establish some relevant pointers. By their nature, internal critiques
are not claims to map the real world. Instead, they are attempts to show that that other theories
are inadequate or overly restrictive in regard to the kind of world to which they relate. I have
not come across an adequate discussion of the role of internal critiques in Lawson’s work,
despite their prevalence the Cambridge tradition of economics that used to be well established
in his university department.
Significantly, neither heuristics nor internal critiques are attempts to map the world with a
model. Accordingly, insofar as they are of some scientific use, severe doubt is cast on
Lawson’s central argument that the adoption of a particular model involves explicit or implicit
assumptions about the ontology of the social world. For him, if an assumption does not occur
in reality, then it is illegitimate in theory – a proposition which would invalidate much theory
in most disciplines. By contrast, it would seem that some models are of use, even if there is a
significant misfit with reality. If so, then Lawson’s main argument falls.
Conclusion
In regard to formalism, many economists propose the extreme view that it is the principal and
necessary means by which economics becomes rigorous and scientific, and thus the
dominance of formalism is a positive sign of success. Lawson takes a position near the other
extreme. He argues that formalism is justified in ‘rare’ circumstances only, where local
closure exists or is approximated. I propose that both attitudes to formalism are flawed, partly
because they both downplay its necessary interface with interpretative structures.
Yet while Lawson and the mainstream are at odds, there are some shared presuppositions.
Many mainstream economists assume that their models are sufficient to represent the world,
neglecting the interpretative discourses required to make such a claim meaningful. Lawson
too believes that the adoption of a formal model intrinsically upholds some substantial claims
concerning the nature of reality. I believe that both positions are false.
- 9 -
If modern economics is sick, then what is the nature of the sickness? A good answer to this
question is required to help us find an appropriate remedy. Lawson’s medicine is to require
the application of formalism only when local closure is achieved or perhaps approximated.
However this remedy virtually ends up as an inversion of the disease itself, and I have argued
that it is based on a faulty diagnosis.
Especially in his recent writing, Lawson has insisted that he is not against formalism as
such, and he has no dogmatic prescription concerning its use. However, I am aware of only
one example of a piece of econometrics which Lawson has deemed as legitimate, and even
here to admit it he has to fudge the criterion of strict closure declared in his 2003 book. More
recently (but until now only verbally as far as I am aware), he has relaxed this criterion to
allow econometrics to be used when closure is approximated, rather than actually achieved.
The consequent challenge for Lawson is to be more specific about the degree of
approximation and to point to still further examples of the legitimate use of mathematical
models in economics. Until this is done, Lawson remains in the extreme position of admitting
as legitimate only one specific case, among hundreds of thousands of examples that are
available to us.
Middle ground solutions are not intrinsically warranted simply because they are middle
ground. But part of the tragedy of modern economics is that they have so far received limited
attention and consideration, with notable exceptions such as a recent article by Victoria Chick
and Sheila Dow (2001).
I suggest that the problem with formalism is not the general inappropriateness of formalism
itself, but it is the problem identified by Blaug in the quotation near the beginning of this
article. Blaug sees the kind of formalism in modern economics as ‘an intellectual game played
for its own sake’ rather than for its use in explaining and engaging with the real economic
world. Blaug complains that in modern economics ‘analytical rigour is everything and
practical relevance is nothing’. Again the solution here is not necessarily to confine formalism
to the very rare conditions of actual or approximated closure, but to ensure that concerns for
practical relevance come to the fore. Formal techniques should be the servants rather than the
masters of scientific enquiry.
It is also worth bearing in mind that there is an example of a social science in which formal
methods and models have hitherto been put to little use, apart from statistics. Yet this
discipline is widely acknowledged to be in a state of severe disorder, especially concerning its
core presuppositions, its self-identity and boundaries, and its relations with other disciplines,
particularly economics and biology. This afflicted social science is sociology. The persistence
of its acute scientific maladies alongside its relatively infrequent use of formalism indicates
that additional problems exist within the social sciences today. These include the
postmodernist affirmation that one theory is as good as another, the frequent choice of a
theory on ideological rather than scientific grounds, and an occasional self-inflicted blindness
concerning the biological aspect of human nature and its significance for the study of human
society.
Despite our differences of view, I wish to emphasize that both Lawson and myself, and
others here cited including Blaug, Chick, Dow and Mäki, adopt a realist philosophical
perspective. Realism acknowledges that a world exists beyond our perceptions. Realists
uphold that, to be adequate, sciences including economics should not be self-contained logical
games but attempts to address and understand aspects of the real world. Accordingly, there is
no room for a philosophy of science in which ‘anything goes’. There is a shared realist
imperative: to understand the real world.
- 10 -
However, I argue here that there is a place for mathematics in economics, even when
conditions of closure are absent or fail to be approximated. I have emphasized the greater
importance of the interpretative structure within which the theory is placed. The pressing
agenda issue for further discussion and enquiry in this area is to explore the inadequately
explored middle ground between the unacceptable extremes of unreflecting worship and (at
least expectational) denial of formal models and methods.
- 11 -
Acknowledgement
The author wishes to thank Mark Blaug, Victoria Chick, Sheila Dow and Tony Lawson for
very helpful comments on earlier versions of this essay.
References
Akerlof, George A. (1970) ‘The Market for “Lemons”: Quality Uncertainty and the Market
Mechanism’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84(3), August, pp. 488-500.
Bhaskar, Roy (1975) A Realist Theory of Science, 1st edn. (Leeds: Leeds Books).
Blaug, Mark (1997) ‘Ugly Currents in Modern Economics’, Options Politiques, 18(17),
September, pp. 3-8.
Blaug, Mark (1999) ‘The Formalist Revolution or What Happened to Orthodox Economics
After World War II?’, in Backhouse, Roger E. and Creedy, John (eds) (1999) From
Classical Economics to the Theory of the Firm: Essays in Honour of D. P. O’Brien
(Cheltenham: Edward Elgar), pp. 257-80.
Blaug, Mark (2003) ‘The Formalist Revolution of the 1950s’, in Samuels, Warren J., Biddle,
Jeff E. and Davis, John B. (eds) (2003) A Companion to the History of Economic Thought
(Malden, MA and Oxford, UK: Blackwell), pp. 395-410.
Blinder, Alan (1990) ‘Discussion’, American Economic Review, 80, May, pp. 445-7.
Boyd, Robert and Richerson, Peter J. (1985) Culture and the Evolutionary Process (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press).
Caldwell, Bruce J. (1982) Beyond Positivism: Economic Methodology in the Twentieth
Century (London: Allen and Unwin).
Chick, Victoria and Dow, Sheila C. (2001) ‘Formalism, Logic and Reality: A Keynesian
Analysis’, Cambridge Journal of Economics, 25(6), November, pp. 705-21.
Downward, Paul (2000) ‘A Realist Appraisal of Post-Keynesian Pricing Theory’, Cambridge
Journal of Economics, 24(2), March, pp. 211-24.
Downward, Paul (ed.) (2003) Applied Economics: A Critical Realist Approach (London and
New York: Routledge).
Granger, Clive W. J. (2004) ‘Critical Realism and Econometrics: An Econometrician’s
Viewpoint’, in Lewis, Paul A. (ed.) (2004) Transforming Economics: Perspectives on the
Critical Realist Project (London and New York: Routledge), pp. 96-106.
Harcourt, Geoffrey C. (1972) Some Cambridge Controversies in the Theory of Capital
(Cambridge, Cambridge University Press).
Klamer, Arjo and Colander, David (1990) The Making of an Economist (Boulder: Westview
Press).
Krueger, Anne O. et al. (1991) ‘Report on the Commission on Graduate Education in
Economics’, Journal of Economic Literature, 29(3), September, pp. 1035-53.
Lawson, Tony (1997) Economics and Reality (London and New York: Routledge).
- 12 -
Lawson, Tony (1999) ‘Connections and Distinctions: Post Keynesianism and Critical
Realism’, Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 22(1), Fall, pp. 3-14.
Lawson, Tony (2003) Reorienting Economics (London and New York: Routledge).
Lawson, Tony (2004) ‘On Heterodox Economics, Themata and the Use of Mathematics in
Economics’, Journal of Economic Methodology, 11(3), September, pp. 329-40.
Mäki, Uskali (1992) ‘On the Method of Isolation in Economics’, Poznan Studies in the
Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, 26, pp. 319-54.
Mäki, Uskali (1994) ‘Isolation, Idealization and Truth in Economics’, Poznan Studies in the
Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, 38, pp. 147-68.
Mantel, Rolf R. (1974) ‘On the Characterization of Aggregate Excess Demand’, Journal of
Economic Theory, 12(2), pp. 348-53.
Murray, J. D. (1989) Mathematical Biology (Berlin: Springer).
Nash, Stephen J. (2004) ‘On Closure in Economics’, Journal of Economic Methodology,
11(1), March, pp. 75-89.
Quine, Willard van Orman (1951) ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, Philosophical Review,
60(1), January, pp. 20-43. Reprinted in Quine, Willard van Orman (1953) From a Logical
Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
Rizvi, S. Abu Turab (1994) ‘The Microfoundations Project in General Equilibrium Theory’,
Cambridge Journal of Economics, 18(4), August, pp. 357-77.
Rowthorn, Robert E. (1999) ‘Unemployment, Wage Bargaining and Capital-Labour
Substitution’, Cambridge Journal of Economics, 23(4), July, pp. 413-25.
Schelling, Thomas C. (1969) ‘Models of Segregation’, American Evonomic Review, 59(2), pp.
488-93.
Sraffa, Piero (1960) Production of Commodities by Means of Commodities: Prelude to a
Critique of Economic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Sugden, Robert (2000) ‘Credible Worlds: The Status of Theoretical Models in Economics’,
Journal of Economic Methodology, 7(1), March, pp. 1-31.
Ward, Benjamin (1972) What’s Wrong With Economics? (London: Macmillan).
Wright, Erik Olin (1994) Interrogating Inequality: Essays on Class Analysis, Socialism and
Marxism (London: Verso).
Article
What is seen when one’s gaze falls upon the plurality of thought within economics? If one gazes from the perspective of Slavoj Žižek, of Kojin Karatani, and of Jacques Lacan, one finds a pronounced parallax within the differing perspectives of economic reality. This essay explores the application of parallax ontology—primarily as discussed in Žižek’s The Parallax View—to economic pluralism. Parallax ontology acknowledges that our conception of reality, economic or otherwise, is riven with parallax gaps, to be thought of as irreducible gaps or minimal distances between perspectives. It argues that one should consider these parallax gaps to exist within economic pluralism and to be subjects in and of themselves, a perspective that ultimately rejects any form of monism within economic thought.
Chapter
There are several underlying factors of cyclicality in property markets. Two of these factors are heuristics and biases which have significant impacts on appraiser judgments in real estate valuation process. All estimates include a kind of uncertainty at different levels, and real estate valuation also includes an uncertainty as it is a price estimate aiming to determine the present value of future cash flows. The uncertainty may increase the tendency to use heuristics and biases during real estate valuation due to the complex nature of valuation decision-making. Based on the relevant empirical and experimental literature, these heuristics and biases widely investigated are anchoring and adjustment heuristic, recency heuristic, herding behavior, representative heuristic, loss aversion, regret aversion, false reference point, client feedback, and appraisal smoothing bias. The aim of this study is to explain the role of uncertainty which gives rise to heuristics and to highlight the relation between these heuristics and real estate valuation process and cycles.
Chapter
The introduction of the definition of cyclical assets in the International Valuation Standards (IVSC, 2017, 2020) requires a specific attention while valuing commercial properties with direct capitalization or discounted cash flow analysis. Following the introduction of cyclical capitalization model (d’Amato, Int J Strategic Property Manag 19(3):207–219, 2015) provides a possible solution for the problem of the integration of property market cycle inside the valuation process. In this vein the contribution explores the relationship between inputs and output in the cyclical yield capitalization modelling defining a relationship between variability of market trend and variability of the opinion of value. Evidence confirms the stability of the opinion of value provided by this kind of method.KeywordsCyclical yield capitalizationVariabilityProperty market value
Chapter
The present chapter is an introduction to the first part of the book dealing with the problem of porperty market cycle at theorical level. It seems that property market cycle as an indirect violation of market perfection. This is the reason why in this book we try to create a relationship between property market cycle analysis and professional valuations. This part is a necessary premise to such kind of integration. In this introduction the general organization of the contributions of the first part is provided.
Chapter
It is conventional theory that property valuation activity has neutral effects on transaction prices in property markets. This chapter critiques this view and argues that it prevents the proper identification of the relationship between property valuation and cycles in property markets. An alternative framework is presented, in terms of which the relationship between valuation, transaction prices and market activity is clarified. The framework is further employed to explain price bubbles in property markets which may, in certain cases, presage turning points in market cycles.KeywordsProperty valuationTransaction pricesProperty cyclesPrice bubbles
Chapter
Being aware of the importance and the relevance of property market cycle from social and economic points of views the second parts is dedicated to providing solutions. The contribution is an overview and an introduction to the contributions in the second part of the book mainly focused on providing solutions.
Article
This paper introduces Hume’s law (the fulcrum of the ‘is-ought’ problem of moral philosophy) into the property valuation literature, and uses it as a prism to reflect on the nature and limitations of standard valuation theory. The paper shows how a consideration of Hume’ thesis can help to clarify and solve some specific practical problems in property valuation. The opportunity presented by the subject of property valuation is, in turn, used to reflect back on Hume’s thesis itself, to show conditions under which Hume’s law may be said to be false. The paper makes important contributions both to the property valuation literature and to the literature on moral philosophy. With respect to property valuation, it proposes a change in the manner conclusions of valuations are reported, and the replacement of the notion of valuation accuracy by the wider and more socially appropriate concept of reasonableness.
Chapter
There is an embarrassing polarization of opinions about the status of economics as an academic discipline, as reflected in epithets such as the Dismal Science and the Queen of the Social Sciences. This collection brings together some of the leading figures in the methodology and philosophy of economics to provide a thoughtful and balanced overview of the current state of debate about the nature and limits of economic knowledge. Authors with partly rival and partly complementary perspectives examine how abstract models work and how they might connect with the real world, they look at the special nature of the facts about the economy, and they direct attention towards the academic institutions themselves and how they shape economic research. These issues are thus analysed from the point of view of methodology, semantics, ontology, rhetoric, sociology, and economics of science.
Article
'Almost 150 years after their major works were published Darwin and Marx stand alone as the premier theorists of the evolution of complex living systems. Hodgson's unique contribution in these essays is to capture the spirit of these two great thinkers in their ability to see universal principles in particular contextual frameworks. Using an evolutionary and institutional approach to examine a variety of theoretical issues Hodgson avoids both the postmodern disease of extreme relativism and the rigidity of insisting on "one true religion" for economic theory. This book is a major contribution to the current revolution in economic theory.' - John M. Gowdy, Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute, US. Economics in the Shadows of Darwin and Marx examines the legacies of these two giants of thought for the social sciences in the twenty-first century.
Article
This lively new collection from one of America's leading sociologists covers a wide range of theoretical problems of interest to radical social scientists and political activists. The book opens with a fascinating autobiographical essay exploring the challenges and benefits of being a Marxist scholar in the present era. Following this is a discussion of various issues of class analysis, with particular attention being paid to two overarching themes: class and inequality, and the relationship between class and power. The second section of the book engages the problem of socialism as a possible future to capitalism. Wright attempts to clarify the conceptual status of socialism and discusses why certain reforms such as basic income grants may ultimately require introduction of some for of socialism for their full realization. Interrogating Inequality concludes by examining the general problem of Marxism as a tradition of radical social theory. Three issues in particular are discussed: the central principles of Analytical Marxism as a strategy for reconstructing Marxism as a social scientific theory; the relationship between Marxism and feminism as emancipatory social theories; and the prospects for Marxism in the aftermath of the collapse of communist regimes.