ArticlePDF Available

Phylogeny and beyond: Scientific, historical, and conceptual significance of the first tree of life

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

In 1977, Carl Woese and George Fox published a brief paper in PNAS that established, for the first time, that the overall phylogenetic structure of the living world is tripartite. We describe the way in which this monumental discovery was made, its context within the historical development of evolutionary thought, and how it has impacted our understanding of the emergence of life and the characterization of the evolutionary process in its most general form.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Phylogeny and beyond: Scientic, historical, and
conceptual signicance of the rst tree of life
Norman R. Pace
a,1
, Jan Sapp
b
, and Nigel Goldenfeld
c
a
Department of Molecular, Cellular and Developmental Biology, University of Colorado, Boulder, CO 80309;
b
Biology Department, York
University, Toronto, ON, Canada M3J 1P3; and
c
Institute for Genomic Biology and Department of Physics, University of Illinois, Urbana,
IL 61801
Edited by Edward F. DeLong, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA, and approved December 20, 2011 (received for review November
29, 2011)
In 1977, Carl Woese and George Fox published a brief paper in PNAS that established, for the rst time, that the overall phylogenetic
structure of the living world is tripartite. We describe the way in which this monumental discovery was made, its context within the
historical development of evolutionary thought, and how it has impacted our understanding of the emergence of life and the
characterization of the evolutionary process in its most general form.
Afundamental breakthrough in
biological science occurred in
1977, and most biologists did
not notice. The paper by Woese
and Fox (1) in 1977 was 2.5 pages in length
and contained a single table of numbers
that compared sequence snippets derived
from small subunit rRNAs of different
organisms. The table provided the rst
gene sequence-based quantitative assess-
ment of phylogenetic (evolutionary) rela-
tionships between representatives of the
major known kinds of organisms (1). The
paper showed that all cellular life falls into
one of three large relatedness groups:
eukaryotes (our kind of cells, which con-
tain a nuclear envelope), eubacteria
[Woese and Fox (1) termed the group and
this group is where classically studied
bacteria t], and archaebacteria [an un-
usual group of recently described organ-
isms named by Woese and Fox (1) to
distinguish the group from eubacteria]. In
describing the phylogenetic relationships,
the results also charted the rst scientic
view of deep evolutionary history. Both
these fundamental aspects of biology, the
phylogenetic structure of life and the
course of early evolution, previously were
only realms of speculation.
However, the methods and data used in
the work by Woese and Fox (1) were
unfamiliar to most biologists, even mo-
lecular biologists. Traditional biologists,
students of plants and animals, paid little
attention, because the results had little
bearing on their interests. Because of
a joint press release by the National
Aeronautics and Space Administration
and the National Science Foundation that
supported Woeses research, the paper
was heralded on the front page of The New
York Times for discovery of a third form
of life(2). However, the few biologists
who noticed sometimes reacted negatively,
and articles denouncing the claims were
published. Subsequent developments
showed that the methods and conclusions
of the paper were sound.
Several aspects of the paper by Woese
and Fox (1) sparked skepticism. One
was the arcane nature of the molecular
data, which few could appreciate. The re-
liance on a single gene to trace major
trends in evolution was an equally alien
concept. Some quibbled about the name
archaebacteria; others objected to The
New York Times publicity. Most impor-
tantly, however, the conclusions of the
paper ew into the face of the common
wisdom of the time regarding the basic
divisions of biology and the nature of early
evolution. It was generally believedand
still is taught in our textbooksthat life
is of two kinds: on one hand, eukaryotes
and on the other hand, prokaryotes, which
lack nuclear membranes and as the name
implies, were supposed to have preceded
and evolved into eukaryotes. However,
eubacteria and the newly discovered group
of archaebacteria both lacked nuclear
membranes. Eukaryotes seemed not de-
rived from either bacteria or arch-
aebacteria; all three kinds of organisms
seemed to represent aboriginal lines
of descent.
In this retrospective, we view the 1977
paper by Woese and Fox (1) from three
standpoints. First, we discuss the specic
accomplishments of this landmark paper
and how the program of research initiated
and led by Woese from the late 1960s to
the present day has spawned a revolution
in microbiology and other elds contin-
gent on microbiology, including ecology
and the health sciences. Second, we dis-
cuss the place of that paper in the history
of evolutionary biology, where its un-
precedented use of molecular sequences
associated with rRNA provided the rst
window into the deep timeline of life, one
independent of theoretical prejudices that
had awed earlier efforts to classify life.
Finally, we describe how the under-
standings sparked by the paper are bring-
ing a new face to the study of evolution by
compelling biologists to address founda-
tional issues related to the very concepts of
species and organism and bringing to the
fore the deep limitations of earlier ac-
counts of the evolutionary process.
Lead Up to the Paper
The 1977 paper by Woese and Fox (1) was
an early example of what we would today
call molecular phylogeneticsthe com-
parison of macromolecular sequences to
infer genealogical and thereby, evolution-
ary relationships. The notion of comparing
sequences to infer relationships was put
forward in 1958 by Francis Crick (3) and
more formally, by Emil Zuckerkandl and
Linus Pauling in 1965 (4). This was a
time when determination of protein se-
quences had become, to some extent,
tractable with protocols developed by Fred
Sanger (5), who received his rst Nobel
Prize for that development and the de-
termination of the amino acid sequence of
insulin in the 1950s (5). Protein bio-
chemists began to develop phylogenetic
relatedness maps, phylogenetic trees,
based on amino acid sequences derived
from various organisms, mainly animals.
Russell Doolittle sketched out vertebrate
evolution using blood-clotting brinopep-
tides in the work by Doolittle and Feng
(6); the work by Fitch and Margoliash (7)
used the mitochondrial protein cyto-
chrome C to relate animals and some
fungi. However, not all organisms possess
cytochrome C, and for that reason alone,
its amino acid sequence could not be used
to infer the patterns of relationships
among all of life.
Carl Woese came to the study of evo-
lution from a background in biophysics and
Author contributions: N.R.P., J.S., and N.G. wrote the paper.
The authors declare no conict of interest.
This article is a PNAS Direct Submission.
See Classic Article Phylogenetic structure of the prokary-
otic domain: The primary kingdomson page 5088 in issue
11 of volume 74.
See Classic Prole on page 1019.
1
To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-mail:
Norman.Pace@colorado.edu.
www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1109716109 PNAS
|
January 24, 2012
|
vol. 109
|
no. 4
|
10111018
PNAS CLASSIC PERSPECTIVE
an interest in the genetic code and its
origins. During the early 1960s, the nature
of protein synthesis and the makeup of the
genetic code were just being worked
out (8). Woese was a contributor to early
thought on the genetic code and had
conducted experimental studies to try to
understand the chemical basis of the ca-
nonical assignments of different amino
acids to particular codons (the DNA or
RNA base triplets that specify the amino
acid sequence of a protein during protein
synthesis) (9). His 1967 book The Genetic
Code: The Molecular Basis for Genetic
Expression focused prescient attention on
the RNA elements of the protein synthe-
sizing machinery (10). Woese, along with
Francis Crick (11) and Leslie Orgel (12)
after him, are considered founding cham-
pions of the idea that nucleic acids played
more than template roles in the origin of
biological systems, thus giving rise to the
notion of a hypothetical prebiotic RNA
world in which nucleic acids served as both
catalytic entities and genetic templates
(13). Woese was concerned that the
emerging paradigm for the mechanism of
protein synthesis was too static and had
no evolutionary dimension. As early as
1969, as articulated in a letter to Francis
Crick, he understood that the only way to
reveal the essence of the process was to
study its conservation and variation in
different organismsits evolutionin
a phylogenetic framework. He set out to
do that study by comparing rRNA se-
quences. This task was daunting at that
time before the development of rapid se-
quencing protocols, but it was the only way
to quantify evolutionary change.
All cells contain ribosomes, which carry
out protein synthesis and typically are
composed of 50% RNA and 50% pro-
tein. The ribosome consists of two sub-
units: a small subunit (SSU), which
contains the 1,500- to 2,000-nt-long SSU
rRNA (also called 16S or 18S rRNA to
denote size), and a large subunit (LSU),
which has two RNA molecules (a 120-nt
5S rRNA and a 3,000- to 5,000-nt LSU
rRNA). [Most eukaryotes contain a fourth
LSU rRNA (5.8S rRNA), but this RNA
corresponds to one end of the bacterial,
archaeal, and some eukaryotic LSU
rRNAs.] Woese began with 5S rRNA,
because its small size rendered it amena-
ble to the sequencing technology of the
time. He studied bacteria because of his
background in working with Bacillus
subtilis and the practical requirement to
prepare highly radioactive RNA for
sequence analysis.
RNA sequencing developed in the mid-
1960s mainly through the efforts of Fred
Sanger and his colleagues using the general
approach used for Sangers protein
sequencing protocol (14). A
32
P-labeled
RNA was digested with base-specic
RNases, and the sequences of the resulting
oligonucleotides were determined by di-
gestion with other nucleases. Next, frag-
ments of incomplete digestion of the RNA
were isolated and digested completely,
and the digestion products were analyzed;
eventually, the sequence could be inferred
from the oligonucleotide contents of
overlapping fragments. Mitchell Sogin,
then a graduate student with Woese,
learned the techniques from David H. L.
Bishop, a postdoctoral student from
Fred Sangers laboratory who was then
working in the Sol Spiegelman laboratory
at the University of Illinois. Sogin set up
the necessary facility for Woeses group.
Woese and his students determined sev-
eral bacterial 5S rRNA sequences. They
showed that the rRNA sequences could be
used as phylogenetic markers for bacteria
(15). They also showed that evolutionary
variation in sequences could be used to
determine how the RNAs fold into sec-
ondary structure (so-called phylogenetic
comparative RNA structure analysis) (16).
However, it soon became clear that 5S
rRNA, at only 120 nt in length, was too
small in size and hence, information con-
tent to provide for accurate phylogenetic
assessments.
The SSU rRNA, at 1,5002,000 nt, was
information-rich, but because of its rela-
tively large size, it was practically impos-
sible to determine the entire sequence
using the Sanger method. Woese posited,
however, that the full sequence of the
RNA was not necessary for phylogenetic
comparisons and that sufcient infor-
mation was available in the collection of
oligonucleotide fragments that result from
specic nuclease digestions of SSU
rRNA. Woese argued that any oligonu-
cleotide six residues or longer had a low
probability of random occurrence in
a molecule the size of the SSU rRNA;
therefore, they could be assumed to be
homologous in different organisms and
have common ancestry, and they could be
used in phylogenetic assessments. He and
his colleagues began to generate catalogs
of sequences of oligonucleotides that re-
sulted from digestion of the RNA with
ribonuclease T1, which cleaves at G resi-
dues and therefore, produces oligonu-
cleotides that are comprised of some
collection of U, C, and A with a single G.
The resulting oligonucleotides were re-
solved by 2D electrophoresis, rst on cel-
lulose acetate at pH 3.5 and then on DEAE
cellulose paper at pH 1.9 using Sangers
protocols. The autoradiogram shown in
Fig. 1 is an example of such an RNase T1
ngerprint of a
32
P-labeled SSU rRNA.
The positions of the different oligonu-
cleotides in the electropherogram reect
size, base composition, and sequence of
the particular oligonucleotides. Longer
oligonucleotides were excised from the
paper for secondary and sometimes, ter-
tiary digestions with other ribonucleases to
determine the sequences. Preparation and
analysis of any particular SSU rRNA
were somewhat risky processes. They in-
volved labeling cell cultures with many
millicuries of
32
P-orthophosphate, pro-
cessing the highly labeled RNA, and con-
ducting up to 5- to 8-kV electrophoresis
in 100-L tanks lled with rened kerosene as
a coolant. The analysisof RNA sequences in
these ways probably could not be con-
ducted today because of safety regulations.
Three Kinds of Life
George Fox joined Woese at the University
of Illinois as a postdoctoral fellow. When
the catalogs of SSU sequences proved
informative, Fox worked with William
Balch, then a graduate student in the
laboratory of Ralph Wolfe at the Univer-
sity of Illinois, to prepare
32
P-labeled SSU
rRNAs from methanogens, organisms
that produce methane (natural gas) as
a metabolic product. Although environ-
mentally important, methanogens were
little studied because of their requirement
Fig. 1. Ribonuclease T1 oligonucleotide nger-
print. As outlined in the text, data reported in the
paper by Woese and Fox (1) in 1977 consisted of
catalogs of oligonucleotide sequences derived
from RNase T1 digestion of small subunit (SSU)
rRNAs. The rst step of the analysis involved res-
olution of RNase T1 digests of 32P-labeled rRNA
by 2D electrophoresis and locating labeled oligo-
nucleotides on the 80 ×100-cm sheet of electro-
phoresis paper by autoradiography. The result, an
RNase T1 ngerprint of the specic RNA, is shown;
notations were made by Woese during the anal-
ysis of archaeal rRNAs. Larger phylogenetically
informative oligonucleotides are in the upper
one-half of the pattern.
1012
|
www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1109716109 Pace et al.
for extremely anoxic conditions for
growth, and as a result, there was no
classication system of these organisms.
Labeled RNAs went to technician Linda
Magrum for ngerprinting and then to
Woese for work up of oligonucleotide
sequences and compilation of the catalogs.
The SSU catalogs provided the rst
phylogeny and classication of those
organisms, but more importantly, the
methanogen oligonucleotide catalogs dif-
fered markedly from catalogs of any bac-
teria that had so far been examined (17).
Today, we would compare DNA or RNA
sequences from different organisms ex-
plicitly in terms of percent identity, an
intuitively meaningful comparison even to
a nonspecialist. Comparison of oligonu-
cleotide catalogs was not so straightfor-
ward, which possibly contributed to the
lack of comprehension and resulting
skepticism that greeted the paper by Woese
and Fox (1). The single table in the work
by Woese and Fox (1) was a matrix
that compared association coefcients,
S
AB
values, of different SSU oligonucleo-
tide catalogs. (S
AB
values for catalogs of
organisms A and B are calculated as
S
AB
=2N
AB
/(N
A
+N
B
), where N
A
and
N
B
are the numbers of nucleotides in se-
quences of hexamers or larger in the
catalogs of organisms A and B and N
AB
is
the number in common to the two
catalogs.) The higher the S
AB
, the more
similar the sequences and the more closely
related must be the organisms repre-
sented by the sequences. The single table
in the paper by Woese and Fox (1), the
matrix of S
AB
numbers, showed clearly
that lifeat least SSU rRNA sequences
fell into three distinct relatedness groups
or urkingdoms as Woese and Fox termed
them. Each urkingdom was further char-
acterized by collections of signature oli-
gonucleotides found only in that group
and not the other groups. In addition to
these idiosyncratic markers, there were
universal signatures, oligonucleotide se-
quences found in all organisms examined.
For the rst time, it was actually shown
that all life is related phylogenetically.
This nding was a seminal nding not
previously established but widely and im-
plicitly assumed. However, more strikingly
and wholly unexpectedly was their data
indicating that there were at least three,
not two, primary lineages of life.
The results of the paper showed that
a large-scale map of lifes diversity could
be seen as three branches corresponding
to eukaryotes, eubacteria, and archae-
bacteria. However, where was the root of
the tree (assuming there was one)? Where
was the origin of it all or some place
in the tree that would correspond to a hy-
pothetical last universal common ances-
tor? Were two of the urkingdoms more
closely related to one another than to
the third urkingdom, or did the three
branches spring independently from some
universal ancestor?
These questions could not be answered
from the necessarily limited 1977 data
and indeed, would not be settled for more
than another decade when Iwabe et al. (18)
and Gogarten et al. (19) used paralogous
rooting, a phylogenetic technique de-
veloped by Margaret Dayhoff, a pioneer in
bioinformatics (20), to establish that the
origin was deep on the eubacterial line.
The eukaryotes and archaebacteria
seemed to constitute a sister group to the
exclusion of bacteria. The result came as
no surprise, because by this time (1989),
the phylogenetic work of Woeses group
had stimulated a large-scale effort, par-
ticularly in Germany, to determine the
molecular biology and biochemistry of
archaebacteria. Many aspects of the fun-
damental molecular biology of eukaryotes
and archaebacteria proved to resemble
each other more than their bacterial
counterparts. For instance, during tran-
scription, eukaryotes and archaebacteria
were both known to use TATA binding
proteins in promoter selection, whereas
bacteria use σ-factors, a different basic
mechanism (21); the DNA replication
enzymologies of eukaryotes and archae-
bacteria resemble one another far more
so than either resembles the eubacterial
version (22). The biochemical and molec-
ular criteria generally supported the root-
ing of the tree and a deep, at least partial
relationship of eukaryotes and archae-
bacteria. The rudiments of a scientically
grounded universal tree of life were
in place.
In 1990, Woese, with colleagues Otto
Kandler and Mark Wheelis, proposed the
formal designation domains to denote the
three major phylogenetic groups, which
they proposed be named Eucarya,Bacteria,
and Archaea (formerly archaebacteria)
(23). The diagrammatic phylogenetic tree
that they used to support their classica-
tion is reproduced as Fig. 2. For the rst
time, a universal tree of life had been
determined in a scientically rigorous way.
The eld of molecular phylogeny is still
a contentious one, but the large-scale
organization shown in Fig. 2 is generally
accepted.
Revolution in Microbiology
The development of a sequence-based
phylogenetic framework for the identi-
cation of microbes would revolutionize
microbial ecology (24) and more generally,
bring together evolution and ecological
studies under a single empirically based
framework. It had long been appreciated
that microbial ecology is the critical driver
of the global biosphere. However, progress
to achieving some understanding of envi-
ronmental microbes had been hampered
by the general necessity to culture micro-
organisms, even for identication. This
need was a crippling constraint, because
few environmental microbes, perhaps
much less than 1%, can be cultured using
standard methods (25). Consequently,
the microbial ecologist had little access
to environmental organisms and little
knowledge of even the kinds of microbes
that occur in the environment.
With the phylogenetic framework for
classication in place and the subsequent
development of recombinant DNA and
sequencing technology, rRNA gene
sequences began to be used to sidestep the
requirement for culture to identify envi-
ronmental organisms (26). rRNA genes
could be isolated directly from environ-
mental DNA as recombinant clones or the
products of the PCR and sequenced to
identify environmental organisms phylo-
genetically. Such sequences are incisive
identiers for microbes, and therefore,
correlations between organisms and envi-
ronments became possible. Moreover,
the rRNA or other gene sequences also
could be used for development of molec-
ular tools, such as in situ hybridization
probes, for the study of environmental
organisms in their native environments.
Surveys of rRNA gene sequences from
different environments continue to expand
knowledge of microbial life in all of the
phylogenetic domains, and it is clear
that, so far, we are only scratching the
surface of a vast reservoir of microbial
Fig. 2. Diagrammatic phylogenetic tree used to illustrate the proposal of three phylogenetic domains in
1990. Modied from Woese et al. (23).
Pace et al. PNAS
|
January 24, 2012
|
vol. 109
|
no. 4
|
1013
diversity. Currently, about 2 million rRNA
sequences are held by the sequence data-
bases, and more than 99% of these se-
quences are environmental sequences (27).
The 1977 paper (1) and its aftermath
transformed microbiology by introducing
a phylogenetic framework for exploring
lifes diversity and developing a universal
tree of life, a natural system of classication
based on genealogy. This phylogenetic
framework spans most of evolutionary time
on Earth as a microbial world, hitherto
absent from classical evolutionary biology.
Evolution Without Microbes
The neo-Darwinian evolutionary synthesis
that emerged in the 1930s and 1940s was
a conception void of microbial foundation.
It was formed in a world of two kingdoms:
plants and animals. Microbiology largely
remained a world apart from evolutionary
biology until the development of new
concepts and methods for determining the
phylogenetic relationships based on uni-
versal characteristics at the core of the
molecular genetic system of all organisms.
The concept of highly conserved char-
acteristics, far removed from the vicissi-
tudes of life, from which one could
reconstruct the main course of evolution
had been central to evolutionary biology
from its beginnings. In Philosophie
Zoologique, Jean Baptiste de Lamarck
(28) argued that, to classify organisms
correctly, one had to distinguish relatively
trivial characteristics that were modied
through the inuence of environmental
conditions from the essential system of
organs. The former adaptive traits repre-
sented the branchings of the tree of life.
The latter represented the course of in-
creasing complexity of organization.
Comparisons of the essential system of
organs, he said, could be made only be-
tween the higher groupings of animals and
not between species or genera; they
were less conspicuous in plants and not
conspicuous at all in the Infusoria (28).
The existence of highly preserved char-
acteristics through which one could trace
the tree of life was equally central to
Charles Darwins theorizing in regard to
descent with modication. As Darwin
wrote to his friend Thomas Henry Huxley
in 1857, the time will come I believe,
though I shall not live to see it, when we
shall have very fairly true genealogical
trees of each great kingdom of nature
(29). Darwin (30) wrote in On the Origin of
Species that all true classication is ge-
nealogical; that community of descent is
the hidden bond which naturalists have
been unconsciously seeking, and not some
unknown plan of creation, or ... the mere
putting together and separating objects
more or less alike(30).
For Darwin no less than for Lamarck, to
have a natural classication that reected
the course of evolution, one needed to
distinguish trivial characteristics from the
essential characteristicsor organs of
high vital or physiological importance
(30). As he explained in On the Origin
of Species,
[i]t might have been thought ... that those
parts of the structure which determine the
habits of life, and the general place of each
being in the economy of nature, would be
of very high importance in classication.
Nothing can be more false ... It may
even be given as a general rule that the less
any part of the organization is concerned
with special habits, the more important it
becomes for classication (30).
Embryological characters,he said,
are the most valuable of all(30).
Comparative morphology, anatomy,
embryology, and the fossil record were the
ways to distinguish homology from analogy
and thus, order organisms according to
their evolutionary relatedness. However,
bacteria lacked both morphological com-
plexity and a fossil record. One could not
tell which characteristics were ancient
and of common ancestry, which charac-
teristics were more recent adaptations,
which characteristics were homologous,
and which characteristics were analogous.
Microbiologys Scandal
In his great work Systema Naturae, Carl
Linnaeus (31) had placed all Infusoria
(microbes) in one species that he pre-
sciently baptized Chaos infusoria. Bacterial
classication remained in chaos for the next
200 y. Bacteria were not put into groups
based on principles of homology and evo-
lution but based on as many characteristics
as possible and principles of utility for in-
dustry and medicine. Bacteria were ar-
ranged into a nested hierarchy of orders,
families, genera, and species based on cell
shape, plane of cell division, ability to form
spores and/or colonies, possession of a-
gella, whether cells were connected,
whether they were branching, staining re-
actions, relation to temperature and oxy-
gen, pigment production, pathogenicity,
and a broad diversity of biochemical prop-
erties (32).
Although some microbiologists held
out hope for a natural classication, one
based on evolutionary relationships (33,
34), by the middle of the 20th century, they
were forced to admit that their efforts
were futile (35). Admitting defeat, Roger
Stanier, Michael Doudoriff, and Edward
Adelberg (36) declared in the rst edition
of their popular text The Microbial World
that it is a waste of time to attempt
a natural system of classication for bac-
teria ... bacteriologists should concentrate
instead on the more humble practical
task of devising determinative keys to
provide the easiest possible identication
of species and genera(36).
Even distinguishing different microbes
from one another was troublesome for
microbiologists. For medical researchers,
they were all simply germs as Joseph Lister
called them in 1874; microbe was in-
troduced 2 y later (37). Some thought they
were little animals, and others thought
that they were little plants. Louis Pasteur
spoke sometimes of microscopic plants,
sometimes as animalcules and sometimes
as virus (the Latin word for poison). In
the early 1870s, the term bacteria (Greek
for little staff or rod) also began to be
used for the smallest of germs: for all
those minute, rounded, ellipsoid, rod sha-
ped, thread-like or spiral forms(38, 39).
Throughout most of the 20th century,
bacteria were understood to be plants;
their classication was the domain of
botanists who referred to them as the s-
sion fungi or Schizomycetes as Carl Nägeli
had named them in 1857. This notion
persists in our age today with common
use of microora to describe microbes.
Breaking out of the plantanimal dualism
would prove to be difcult.
In his speculative phylogenetic tree of
1866, Ernst Haeckel, who coined the
terms ontogeny, phylogeny, and phylum,
placed bacteria and blue-green algae
(now cyanobacteria) in a division that he
called Monera, and he christened another
kingdom the Protista. The Monera were
supposed to lack the fundamental division
of labor of nucleus and cytoplasm exhibited
in true cells and bridge the gap between
the living and the nonliving. Whether the
organization of the bacterium and the
blue-green alga t Haeckelsdenition was
hotly contested throughout the early
20th century (32, 40, 41). A few micro-
biologists proposed that bacteria and the
blue-green algae should be granted their
own kingdom, Monera (34, 42). However,
others doubted that the grouping was
monophyletic. Additionally, it was far
from clear that the blue-green algae
really lacked a nucleus and how smaller
bacteria such as Rickettsia and Chlamydia
could be distinguished from viruses (36).
In a famed paper titled The Concept of
a Virus,André Lwoff (43) drew what
he considered to be a unequivocal dis-
tinction between a virus and a bacterium
on the basis of EM and chemistry. The
virus contained only one kind of nucleic
acid, either RNA or DNA, enclosed in
a coat of protein; it possessed few, if any,
enzymes, and it did not reproduce by di-
vision like a cell. In 1962, Stanier and
Van Niel (44) wrote a sister paper, The
Concept of a Bacterium, that aimed to
resolve issues about the anatomy of the
bacterium once and for all. Any good
biologist,they wrote, nds it intel-
lectually distressing to devote his life to
1014
|
www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1109716109 Pace et al.
the study of a group that cannot be readily
and satisfactorily dened in biological
terms; and the abiding intellectual scandal
of bacteriology has been the absence of
a clear concept of a bacterium(44).
Borrowing terms from Lwoffs former
mentor Edouard Chatton (45, 46), Stanier
and Van Niel (44) distinguished pro-
karyotic cells (Greek for before karyon or
nucleus) from eukaryotic cells (Greek
for true nucleus). The latter divided by
mitosis and possessed a membrane-bound
nucleus, an intricate cytoskeleton, mito-
chondria, and in the case of plants cells,
chloroplasts. Prokaryotic cells were small-
er and lacked those structures. Stanier and
Van Niel (44) wrote that the
principle distinguishing features of the
procaryotic cell are: 1 absence of internal
membranes which separate the resting
nucleus from the cytoplasm, and isolate the
enzymatic machinery of photosynthesis
and of respiration in specic organelles; 2
nuclear division by ssion, not by mitosis,
a character possibly related to the presence
of a single structure which carries all the
genetic information of the cell; and 3 the
presence of a cell wall which contains
a specic mucopeptide as its strengthening
element (44).
The prokaryote was, thus, dened
largely negatively. Although they had for-
saken a natural classication for bacteria,
they asserted nonetheless that the pro-
karyote was a monophyletic group of
common origin (44). All these organisms
share the distinctive structural properties
associated with the procaryotic cell ... and
we can therefore safely infer a common
origin for the whole group in the remote
evolutionary past(47). In fact,they
wrote, this basic divergence in cellular
structure, which separates the bacteria and
blue-green algae from all other cellular
organisms, probably represents the great-
est single evolutionary discontinuity to be
found in the present-day world(47).
The kingdom Monera, thus, rose like
a phoenix from the ashes. It was to be one
of ve kingdoms, along with animals,
plants, fungi, and protists (microbial eu-
karyotes) (48, 49).
The prokaryoteeukaryote dichotomy
for the description of lifes diversity was
quickly instated among the canons of bi-
ology. Born in a time when the search
for a natural system for microorganisms
had been abandoned, the prokaryote
concept contained just as many untested
assumptions as the old taxonomic con-
jectures: the prokaryote was a mono-
phyletic grouping that preceded and gave
rise to eukaryotes. Indeed, nothing was
known of prokaryote or eukaryote origins;
they could have arisen one or many times.
Clash
The paper by Woese and Fox (1), Phy-
logenetic Structure of the Prokaryotic
Domain: The Primary Kingdoms,clash-
ed with the doctrines and methods of
classical microbiology in several ways.
First and foremost was the prokaryote
eukaryote dualism. Phylogenetically,
Woese and Fox (1) wrote, life is not
structured in a bipartite way along the
lines of organizationally dissimilar pro-
karyote and eukaryote. Rather it is (at
least) tripartite(ref. 1, p. 5090). Second,
the eukaryotic cell organelles did not
originate solely in the gradual neo-Dar-
winian manner by gene mutation and se-
lection but rather, saltationally through
symbiosis as long had been suggested.
The SSU rRNA data left no doubt that
the chloroplast is of speciceubacterial
origin(1). The case was not yet as cer-
tain for mitochondria. The nature of the
engulngspecies(thepureurcaryote)
that would have lacked eukaryotic or-
ganelles was unknown.
The manuscript received severe criti-
cisms when it was submitted to PNAS in the
summer of 1977 (1). One reviewer rec-
ommended that it not be published on
methodological grounds that their
claim for a tripartite division of the mi-
crobial world was as unfounded as their
claims in regard to symbiosis and the ori-
gin of eukaryotic organelles. For Woese
and Fox, rRNA was a highly conserved,
nonadaptive structure at the core of all
organisms. Nested deep in the center of
essential cellular functions, the SSU rRNA
was, as Woese (50) later put it, the ulti-
mate molecular chronometer.However,
for critics, an rRNA oligonucleotide cata-
log was merely a trait like any other, and
classication on its basis held no more
validity than classifying birds, bats, and
insects on the basis of their possession of
wings. That one molecule or many could
be used to discern phylogenetic relation-
ships was more than many classical mi-
crobiologists could accept; the molecular
approach was pronounced by some as
doomed to failure (51).
The belief that it was impossible to know
the phylogenetic relationships among
microbes because of a lack of fossil record
was well-entrenched in the minds of
microbiologists. As Stanier et al. (52) wrote
in The Microbial World in 1970,
[r]eection and experience have shown,
however, that the goal of a phylogenetic
classication can seldom be realized. The
course that evolution has actually followed
can be ascertained only from direct his-
torical evidence contained in the fossil
record. This record is at best fragmentary
and becomes almost completely illegible in
Precambrian rocks more than 400 million
years old (52).
However, this publication was well
after Zuckerkandl and Pauling (4) had
written Molecules as Documents of
Evolutionary History,and Francis Crick
(3) had written as far back as 1958 that the
amino acid sequences of proteins are
the most delicate expression possible of
the phenotype of an organism and vast
amounts of evolutionary information may
be hidden away within them(3). There
was, indeed, a strange disconnect between
microbiology and molecular biology,
one that was nally resolved through the
SSU rRNA sequencing method reported in
the paper by Woese and Fox (1) in 1977.
The SSU rRNA sequencing method
had remarkable predictive success. Most of
the higher taxa above the genus would
have to be reclassied on the basis of SSU
rRNA phylogenies. When that technology
surprised microbiologists by predicting
unexpected relationships, it was corrobo-
rated by other data. Nothing was more
striking than the phenotypically diverse
organisms that came to be included in the
archaebacteria urkingdom by 1980 (do-
main archaea). It comprised methanogens,
found in the guts of rumens, extreme
halophiles known for rotting salted sh,
and extreme thermoacidophiles that live in
conditions that would cook other organ-
isms (53). The group was found to have
many highly conserved characteristics in
common: their walls lacked murein pepti-
doglycan (the only positive characteristic
of the prokaryotes), their tRNAs were
unique, the lipids in their membranes were
ether- and not ester-linked, their tran-
scription enzymes were unlike the enzymes
of the classic bacteria, and their viruses
were unlike the viruses of the classic
bacteria.
The SSU rRNA phylogenies also de-
nitively resolved the venerable question of
whether chloroplasts and mitochondria
originated as symbionts (1, 16, 54). Con-
jectures in regard to the symbiotic origin
of cell organelles had been discussed
throughout the 20th century, but that
question remained far outside the realm of
empirical inquiry (55). As Wilson (56)
commented in his famed book The Cell in
Development and Heredity,[t]o many,
no doubt, such speculations [symbiotic
origin of organelles] may appear too fan-
tastic for present mention in polite bi-
ological society; nevertheless it is within
the range of possibility that they may
someday call for more serious consider-
ation(56).
Such speculation did, indeed, call for
more serious consideration in the early
1960s with evidence that mitochondria and
chloroplasts each possessed their own
DNA and translation apparatus. That these
organelles might have originated as sym-
bionts was the conclusion of virtually every
paper, showing that they possessed their
Pace et al. PNAS
|
January 24, 2012
|
vol. 109
|
no. 4
|
1015
own DNA (5759). However, proof of
origin was lacking, and the debates were
sterile. As Woolhouse (60) remarked, the
time has come to bury this kind of specu-
lation with, by way of an epitaph, a parody
of Wittgensteins well-known remark,
Whereof one cannot know, thereof one
should not speak’” (60). Stanier (61) de-
creed that the problem of eukaryotic cell
origins would always remain in the realm
of metascience: [i]t might have happened
thus; but we shall surely never know
with certainty,Stanier (61) quipped.
Evolutionary speculation constitutes a kind
of metascience, which has the same in-
tellectual fascination for some biologists
that metaphysical speculation possessed
for some medieval scholastics. It can be
considered a relatively harmless habit, like
eating peanuts, unless it assumes the form
of an obsession; then it becomes a vice (61).
SSU rRNA phylogenetics belied that
statement. Molecular evolution revitalized
evolutionary biology and provided a new
basis for empirical investigations of pro-
found new questions concerning the evo-
lution of the cell and its components.
Molecular phylogenetic methods and
concepts constituted a paradigm apart
from classical evolutionary biology. Mo-
lecular methods for classication based on
GC content, DNARNA hybridization,
and amino acid sequencing of proteins had
begun to revitalize the aim for a phyloge-
netic classication of bacteria in the 1960s
and 1970s. However, those approaches
could not offer universal and quantitative
methods for a universal tree of life.
Inuence on Evolutionary Biology
The work by Woese and Fox (1) and its
continuation within the Woese group have
had an enormous impact (e.g., roughly
one-quarter of the 40,000 total citations to
Woeses work originate just from refer-
ences) (1, 23, 50, 62), and its methods are
revolutionizing disciplines as varied as
marine science and the study of the human
microbiome for medicine. This success has
perhaps overshadowed the original moti-
vations and may even have stimulated so
much activity in genomics per se that
Woeses overarching interests in funda-
mental evolutionary questions have been
relatively neglected. We close out this
retrospective with a brief account of how
the work by Woese and Fox (1) began,
the extent to which their work has inu-
enced evolutionary thought, and the way
in which their ideas are still unfolding.
Woese and Foxs discovery that all living
systems are representatives of one of three
aboriginal lines of descentdid not
emerge in a vacuum (1). It was a water-
shed event (but not the culmination) in
an iconoclastic program of research that
Woese had been pursuing since the
mid-1960s, one with the goal of under-
standing the evolution of the complex
structure of the modern cell from the
origin of life (32). In this goal, he was
arguably more ambitious than Darwins
statement of the problem, which was re-
ectedinthetitleofDarwins great work,
On the Origin of Species (30). Indeed,
Woeses concept of the evolution prob-
lem greatly surpassed prevailing views on
what at that time passed for the deepest
thinking on the question. Woese would
not nd it necessary to cite On the Origin
of Species until 1992 (63), reecting nei-
ther a stubbornness of character nor
a contrived striving for originality. The
fact of the matter is that Woese had
not even read Darwins original work
until around 2000, because its relevance
to Woesesprogramhadseemedremote
until that time.
So what was Woeses conception of the
evolution problem? First and foremost, it
explicitly drew a connection between the
origin of the genetic code, the translation
mechanism, and the emergence of cells
and their organization. For Woese, speci-
ation was an epiphenomenon of the evo-
lutionary process; the more important
question was that of degree of organiza-
tion. Woese and Fox (1) wrote that [e]
volution seems to progress in a quantized
fashion. One level or domain of organi-
zation gives rise ultimately to a higher
(more complex) one ... Ideally one would
like to know whether this is a frequent or
a rare (unique) evolutionary event(1).
Even earlier, in 1972, Woese (64) had
argued that
there are no such things as specialevo-
lutionary problems. Evolution is not
a mixed bag of various historical acci-
dents... All evolutionary problems ap-
pear to have important common aspects
whether they are intracellular problems or
problems on higher levels of biological
organization. Thus in ostensibly addressing
ourselves to evolutions of genetic codes,
translating mechanisms, etc., we are actu-
ally discovering and dening the basic
principles for all evolution ... The nature
of the elementsinvolved changes from
one example to another, but the patterning
of events in time, the principles of evolu-
tionary construction,seem to remain in-
variant (64).
Woese understood that the goal of ex-
ploring evolution on the longest possible
time scales was not to elucidate the idio-
syncratic history of genes. It is too easy to
think of evolution solely in terms of gene
mutations, ow in gene pools, and, of
course, some vague selectionparameters.
Too much emphasis is placed on the
micro-changes at the expense of the
macro-ordering(64).Hewantedtoun-
derstand universal aspects of the process
of evolution, not the particular sample
path represented by the history of life on
Earth, whose dynamics were imperfectly
captured by the slogan natural selection.
Woese and Fox (1), thus, approached
their work in an open-ended way, one not
constrained by theoretical prejudices
about the particular dynamics of the
evolutionary process. This strategy was
brilliant; not only did they uncover an
unanticipated new domain of life, but
also, they pointed out that there were
many possible modes and tempos of
evolution, of which only onelong
time-scale, core cellular mechanisms
could be properly probed by molecular
phylogeny.
Woese and Foxs approach yielded
a major surprise that could be interpreted
directly and plainly without contamination
from theory. The phylogenetic tree im-
plied by table 1 in ref. 1 clearly showed
three fundamental groupings, results that
were subsequently conrmed and elabo-
rated in compelling detail by Woese and
his collaborators (63, 65). At a stroke,
those data demolished the conception of
the prokaryote as a monophyletic group
that preceded and gave rise to the eu-
karyotic cell. The draft of the phylogenetic
tree that became available during the
1990s provided evidence for a last uni-
versal common ancestor, which is sum-
marized above.
Progenote
Woeses conception of the evolution
question had already led him to surmise by
at least 1971 that life, as we know it today,
descended from an earlier, radically dif-
ferent protocell, which lacked the trans-
lation mechanisms of cells (64). His
rationale for this conclusion is important
to appreciate, because the paper by Woese
and Fox (1) in 1977 bore directly on
the properties of that hypothetical primi-
tive entity.
Woese and Fox (66) had, in parallel to
their experimental work on molecular
phylogeny, published a conceptual paper
that introduced the concept of aprimi-
tive entity ... called [the] progenote, to
recognize the possibility that it had not
yet completed evolving the link between
genotype and phenotype(66). The pro-
genotes were hypothetical ancient life
forms in the throes of developing the re-
lationship between nucleic acid and pro-
tein. Woese had suggested the existence
of the progenote from rather detailed
arguments based on his unrivalled
knowledge of the translation apparatus,
whichwasarticulatedinhisbookThe
Genetic Code: The Molecular Basis for
Genetic Expression in 1967 (10); he con-
sidered these arguments to indicate that
a general principle of evolution was that
complexity emerged through (i) a process
of renement and (ii) a two-step cyclical
1016
|
www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1109716109 Pace et al.
dynamic process that he proposed to
explain the quaternary structure of pro-
teins and that turned out to have re-
markable predictive power (ref. 67, p.
388). These same arguments suggested
a resolution of the old chicken-and-egg
paradox of whether translation preceded
the gene or vice versa. The resolution is
that both emerged from what we would
today call a co-evolutionary process of
renement of translation, in which the
earliest proteins would have been statisti-
cal in character. In other words, early
translation produced not a single protein
but a family of similar proteins, any one of
which was adequate for the task at hand.
Thus, early life was a rickety, free-wheel-
ing construct whose lack of complexity
could tolerate imprecision at the level of
amino acids. The complex modern trans-
lation apparatus would have evolved in
a progenote evolutionary era, with a
tempo and mode based on a high muta-
tion rate of the primitive error-prone
translation system and a pervasive hori-
zontal exchange of genes within the pop-
ulation. During this era, there were no
lineages as such.
Woese and Fox (1) noticed that their
work already implied something funda-
mentally interesting about the progenote
state. Table 1 in ref. 1 established that the
three urkingdoms had to have been at
least 3 billion y old each and therefore,
that the
time available to form each phenotype
(from their common ancestor) is then short
by comparison ... we think that this im-
plies that the common ancestor ... was not
a prokaryote. It was a far simpler entity;
it probably did not evolve at the slowrate
characteristic of prokaryotes (1).
In short, Woese and Foxs early data
already suggested to them that life evolved
from at least a two-step process: a late
stage that they characterized as having
a slow rate of evolution, one which could
be measured using the slowly changing
sequence of rRNA, and an earlier stage
refractory to molecular phylogenetic
analysis, where complexity evolved much
more rapidly, leading to the emergence of
genotype and phenotype as separate cel-
lular features along with a fully functional
translation mechanism.
Woese would return to the progenote
speculations in the succeeding years, em-
phasizing especially the characteristics of
high gene mutation and horizontal gene
transfer (HGT) (68), but by 1998 (69), the
context had become genomics and the
ever-increasing evidence for the wide-
spread occurrence of HGT. Its occurrence
was interpreted by some as being anti-
thetical to the entire program of building
a tree of lifeall which he had addressed
so many years earlier.
Is There Really a Tree of Life?
HGT is the capability that organisms
possess to transfer genes to a non-
genealogically related recipient (70). Once
thought to be an exclusive aspect of mi-
crobial life, HGT has now been docu-
mented to occur between bacteria and
multicellular eukaryotes (71) as well as
between eukaryotes (72). With genomic
evidence for the widespread occurrence of
lateral gene transfer, the notion of a
universal phylogenetic tree came under
severe scrutiny and criticism (73). How-
ever, among Bacteria and Archaea, the
genes that are horizontally transferred are
typically metabolic genes or genes that
confer such traits as antibiotic resistance
and not the nonadaptive informational
genes that are involved in transcription
and translation.
It is now widely recognized that there
can be wide compositional variations in the
genomes of organisms that are nominally
classied together on the basis of their
SSU rRNA phylogeny. That within-group
variation reects the presence of cosmo-
politan genes associated more closely with
a particular environment than with any one
particular organism (74, 75). Woeses
original motivation for constructing a deep
universal phylogenetic tree based on SSU
rRNA sequences to understand the evo-
lution of the molecular genetic system re-
mains largely untouched by HGT. Even
those elements of the translational appa-
ratus that are most susceptible to HGT
(the aminoacyl-tRNA synthetases) show
that the canonical pattern of the rRNA
tree is largely preserved (76). Moreover,
the frequency of HGT is known to depend
on the evolutionary distance between the
lineages concerned, and thus, even if there
is signicant HGT, the impact on the
rRNA phylogenetic tree would be ex-
pected to be rather small: the tree can
reect both the evolutionary history of the
lineage as well as the predominant pat-
terns of gene transfer into and out of the
lineage (77).
Molecular Phylogeny vs. Morphological
Taxonomy
When Woese, Otto Kandler, and Mark
Wheelis (23) formally proposed the three
domains as the natural classication of
taxa in 1990, a direct confrontation with
the status quo ensued. The issues were
well-revealed in Woeses debates with his
most distinguished opponent, Ernst Mayr
(78, 79). First, there was the question of
the great molecular and biochemical di-
versity of the microbial world compared
with the great morphological diversity ex-
hibited by multicellular eukaryotes. For
Mayr (78, 79), the degree of differences
exhibited within the prokaryotic world
simply could not compare with the mor-
phological diversity so readily observed in
the eukaryotic world, and the measure-
ment of that difference using molecular
sequences was anathema compared with
the more descriptive phenotypic dis-
tinctions that he favored.
A second issue concerned the purpose of
a classication system. Mayr (78, 79)
privileged the facility of information re-
trieval over a system based on evolutionary
relationships. In his view, the classi-
cation system should enable a biologist to
quickly identify an organism with a min-
imum of effort and loss of time(79)
rather than reect the genealogy of the
organism. In his response, Woese (80)
broadened the discussion to include the
foundational evolutionary questions that
we have presented above and that, by
that time, had occupied his thoughts for
nearly three decades.
Interestingly enough, the MayrWoese
debate did not address one of the most
contentious issues arising from the paper
by Woese and Fox (1): the denition of
species in the microbial world. Mayr
(78, 79) had famously dened the Bi-
ological Species Concept in 1942 as groups
of interbreeding natural populations that
are reproductively isolated from each
other, but clearly, this concept did not
apply to Bacteria, Archaea, or even mi-
crobial eukaryotes. With the advent of
SSU rRNA phylogeny, it became common
practice to dene operational taxonomic
units by the requirement of close sequence
similarity (typically 97%) (24). However,
as more and more sequencing capability
became available, it became clear that the
spectrum of microbial life was continuous
rather than discrete because of cosmo-
politan genes and HGT. Bacteria seem to
form a radiation, with no specic species
boundaries (27, 81). According to some
estimates, only 40% of the genes in
a particular bacterium typically occur in all
of the genomes of that particular named
species; the other 60% of genes in the
typical bacterial genome occur only spo-
radically in other representatives of the
species or not at all (81). More than 30 y
after the paper by Woese and Fox (1) was
published, the fundamental biological
concept of species remains unresolved.
Legacy
Woese and Fox set out to determine the
degrees of relatedness between all living
organisms using rRNA sequences as
a marker of cellular evolution on slow
time scales subsequent to the emergence of
the modern lines of descent. They discov-
ered that there are three domains of life,
not two domains as had been previously
believed. Their work also strongly con-
strained the nature of life for times shorter
than about 1 billion y, indicating that
before the emergence of a strong phy-
Pace et al. PNAS
|
January 24, 2012
|
vol. 109
|
no. 4
|
1017
logenetic signal of vertical descent, early life
had to evolve rapidly; we now suspect that
its evolution was reticulate in nature.
Modern versions of the techniques used by
Woese and Fox (1) are now routinely used
to sample environments as varied as geo-
thermal hot springs and gastrointestinal
microbiomes, providing unprecedented in-
sight into community structure and dy-
namics. The results challenged the
foundations of classical evolutionary the-
ory, requiring new modes of evolution to be
considered, indicating the presence of an
unexpectedly large microbial pangenome
(aeld of genesto use Woesesfavorite
phrase) (1), and forcing us to reconsider
basic concepts such as the nature of species.
Perhaps no other paper in evolutionary
biology has left a richer legacy of accom-
plishments and promise for the future.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS. We thank Professors Carl
Woese and George Fox for reviewing the manu-
script for accuracy. N.R.P. is supported by the
Alfred P. Sloan Foundation, J.S. is supported by
the Social Sciences and Humanities Research
Council of Canada, and N.G. is supported by
National Science Foundation Grant EF-0526747.
1. Woese CR, Fox GE (1977) Phylogenetic structure of the
prokaryotic domain: The primary kingdoms. Proc Natl
Acad Sci USA 74:50885090.
2. Lyons RD (November 3, 1977) Scientists discover a form
of life that predates higher organisms. NY Times, Sec-
tion A, p 1.
3. Crick FHC (1958) The biological replication of macro-
molecules. Symp Soc Exp Biol 12:138163.
4. Zuckerkandl E, Pauling L (1965) Molecules as docu-
ments of evolutionary history. J Theor Biol 8:357366.
5. Sanger F (1959) Chemistry of insulin; determination of
the structure of insulin opens the way to greater un-
derstanding of life processes. Science 129:13401344.
6. Doolittle RF, Feng DF (1987) Reconstructing the evolu-
tion of vertebrate blood coagulation from a consider-
ation of the amino acid sequences of clotting proteins.
Cold Spring Harb Symp Quant Biol 52:869874.
7. Fitch WM, Margoliash E (1967) Construction of phylo-
genetic trees. Science 155:279284.
8. Judson HF (1996) The Eighth Day of Creation: Makers
of the Revolution in Biology: Expanded Edition (Cold
Spring Harbor Laboratory Press, Plainview, NY).
9. Woese CR, Dugre DH, Saxinger WC, Dugre SA (1966)
The molecular basis for the genetic code. Proc Natl
Acad Sci USA 55:966974.
10. Woese CR (1967) The Genetic Code: The Molecular Ba-
sis for Genetic Expression (Harper and Row, New York).
11. Crick FHC (1968) The origin of the genetic code. J Mol
Biol 38:367379.
12. Orgel LE (1968) Evolution of the genetic apparatus. J
Mol Biol 38:381393.
13. Gilbert W (1986) Origin of life: The RNA world. Nature
319:618.
14. Sanger F, Brownlee GG, Barrell BG (1965) A two-di-
mensional fractionation procedure for radioactive nu-
cleotides. J Mol Biol 13:373398.
15. Rogers MJ, et al. (1985) Construction of the myco-
plasma evolutionary tree from 5S rRNA sequence data.
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 82:11601164.
16. Fox GW, Woese CR (1975) 5S RNA secondary structure.
Nature 256:505507.
17. Fox GE, Magrum LJ, Balch WE, Wolfe RS, Woese CR
(1977) Classication of methanogenic bacteria by 16S
ribosomal RNA characterization. Proc Natl Acad Sci
USA 74:45374541.
18.IwabeN,KumaKI,HasegawaM,OsawaS,MiyataT
(1989) Evolutionary relationship of archaebacteria, eubac-
teria, and eukaryotes inferred from phylogenetic trees of
duplicated genes. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 86:93559359.
19. Gogarten JP, et al. (1989) Evolution of the vacuolar
H+-ATPase: Implications for the origin of eukaryotes.
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 86:66616665.
20. Schwartz RM, Dayhoff MO (1978) Origins of prokar-
yotes, eukaryotes, mitochondria, and chloroplasts. Sci-
ence 199:395403.
21. Thomm M (2007) Transcription: Mechanism and regu-
lation. Archaea: Molecular and Cellular Biology,ed
Cavicchioli R (Wiley-Blackwell, New York), pp 139157.
22. Lao-Sirieix S-B, Marsh VL, Bell SD (2007) DNA replication
and cell cycle. Archaea: Molecular and Cellular Biology,
ed Cavicchioli R (Wiley-Blackwell, New York), pp 93109.
23. Woese CR, Kandler O, Wheelis ML (1990) Towards
a natural system of organisms: Proposal for the do-
mains Archaea, Bacteria, and Eucarya. Proc Natl Acad
Sci USA 87:45764579.
24. Pace NR (1997) A molecular view of microbial diversity
and the biosphere. Science 276:734740.
25. Amann RI, Ludwig W, Schleifer KH (1995) Phylogenetic
identication and in situ detection of individual micro-
bial cells without cultivation. Microbiol Rev 59:143169.
26. Olsen GJ, Lane DJ, Giovannoni SJ, Pace NR, Stahl DA
(1986) Microbial ecology and evolution: A ribosomal
RNA approach. Annu Rev Microbiol 40:337365.
27. Pace NR (2009) Mapping the tree of life: Progress and
prospects. Microbiol Mol Biol Rev 73:565576.
28. de Lamarck JBM, Zoological Philosophy: An Exposition
with Regard to the Natural History of Animals, trans
Elliot H (1984) (University of Chicago Press, Chicago).
29. Darwin C (1857) Darwin to Thomas Henry Huxley: Dar-
win Correspondence Project. Letter 2143. Available at
http://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/entry-2143.
30. Darwin C (1969) On the Origin of Species: Facsimile
Edition (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA).
31. Linnaeus C (1774) Systema Naturae (Laurentius Salvius,
Stockholm), 10th Ed.
32. Sapp J (2009) The New Foundations of Evolution: On
the Tree of Life (Oxford University Press, New York).
33. Kluyver AJ, Van Niel CB (1936) Prospects for a natural
system of classication of bacteria. Zentralbl Bakteriol
Parasitenkd Infektionskr Hyg Abt II 94:369403.
34. Stanier RY, Van Niel CB (1941) The main outlines of
bacterial classication. J Bacteriol 42:437466.
35. Van Niel CB (1955) Natural selection in the microbial
world. J Gen Microbiol 13:201217.
36. Stanier RY, Doudoriff M, Adelberg EA (1957) The Mi-
crobial World (Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ).
37. Carter KC (1991) The development of Pasteurs concept
of disease causation and the emergence of specic
causes in nineteenth-century medicine. Bull Hist Med
65:528548.
38. Cohn F (1872) Uber die Bacterien, die Kleinstein Leb-
enden Wesen. Samsung Gemeinverständlicher Wissen-
schaftlicher Vorträge 7:135.
39. Woodhead GS (1892) Bacteria and Their Products (Wal-
ter Scott, London).
40. Sapp J (2009) Transcending Darwinism thinking later-
ally on the tree of life. Hist Philos Life Sci 31:161181.
41. Sapp J (2005) The prokaryote-eukaryote dichotomy:
Meanings and mythology. Microbiol Mol Biol Rev 69:
292305.
42. Copeland HF (1938) The kingdoms of organisms. Q Rev
Biol 13:383420.
43. Lwoff A (1957) The concept of virus. J Gen Microbiol
17:239253.
44. Stanier RY, Van Niel CB (1962) The concept of a bacte-
rium. Arch Mikrobiol 42:1735.
45. Chatton E (1938) Titres et travaux scientiques (1906
1937) (Sottano, Italy).
46. Chatton E (1925) Pansporella perplexa, Amoebien á
spores protégées parasite des Daphnies. Reexions
sur la biologie et la phylogenie des Protozoairies.
Ann Sci Nat (Zool) 8:584.
47. Stanier RY , Doudoroff M, Adelberg EA (1963) The M icro-
bial World (Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ), 2nd Ed.
48. Whittaker RH (1969) New concepts of kingdoms or or-
ganisms. Evolutionary relations are better represented
by new classications than by the traditional two king-
doms. Science 163:150160.
49. Whittaker RH, Margulis L (1978) Protist classication
and the kingdoms of organisms. Biosystems 10:318.
50. Woese CR (1987) Bacterial evolution. Microbiol Rev 51:
221271.
51. Margulis L, Guerrero R (1991) Kingdoms in turmoil.
New Sci 1761:4650.
52. Stanier RY , Doudoroff M, Adelberg EA (1970) The M icro-
bial World (Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ), 3rd Ed.
53. Fox GE, et al. (1980) The phylogeny of prokaryotes.
Science 209:457463.
54. Gray MW, Doolittle WF (1982) Has the endosymbiont
hypothesis been proven? Microbiol Rev 46:142.
55. Sapp J (1994) Evolution by Association: A History of
Symbiosis (Oxford University Press, New York).
56. Wilson EB (1925) The Cell in Development and Hered-
ity (Macmillan, New York).
57. Ris H, Plaut W (1962) Ultrastructure of DNA-containing
areas in the chloroplast of Chlamydomonas. J Cell Biol
13:383391.
58. Nass MMK, Nass S (1963) Intramitochondrial bers
with DNA characteristics. I. Fixation and electron stain-
ing reactions. J Cell Biol 19:593611.
59. Nass S (1969) The signicance of the structural and
functional similarities of bacteria and mitochondria.
Int Rev Cytol 25:55129.
60. Woolhouse WH (1967) A review of the plastids by JTO
Kirk and RAE Tilney-Bassett. New Phytol 66:832833.
61. Stanier RY (1970) Some aspects of the biology of cells
and their possible evolutionary signicance. Organiza-
tion and Control in Prokaryotic and Eukaryotic Cells,
eds Charles HP, Knight BCJG (Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, UK), Vol 20, pp 138.
62. Balch WE, Fox GE, Magrum LJ, Woese CR, Wolfe RS
(1979) Methanogens: Reevaluation of a unique biolog-
ical group. Microbiol Rev 43:260296.
63. Wheelis ML, Kandler O, Woese CR (1992) On the na-
ture of global classication. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 89:
29302934.
64. Woese CR (1972) The emergence of genetic organiza-
tion. Exobiology, ed Ponnamperuma C (North-Holland,
Amsterdam), pp 301341.
65. Cavicchioli R (2007) Archaea: Molecular and Cellular
Biology (Wiley-Blackwell, New York).
66. Woese CR, Fox GE (1977) The concept of cellular evo-
lution. J Mol Evol 10:16.
67. Goldenfeld N, Woese C (2011) Life is physics: Evolution
as a collective phenomenon far from equilibrium. Ann
Rev Condensed Matter Physics 2:375399.
68. Woese CR (1982) Archaebacteria and cellular origins:
An overview. Zbl Bakt Hyg I Abt Orig C 3:117.
69. Woese C (1998) The universal ancestor. Proc Natl Acad
Sci USA 95:68546859.
70. Chia N, Goldenfeld N (2011) Statistical mechanics of
horizontal gene transfer in evolutionary ecology. J Stat
Phys 142:12871301.
71. Dunning Hotopp JC (2011) Horizontal gene transfer be-
tween bacteria and animals. Trends Genet 27:157163.
72. Gladyshev EA, Meselson M, Arkhipova IR (2008) Mas-
sive horizontal gene transfer in bdelloid rotifers. Sci-
ence 320:12101213.
73. Doolittle WF (1999) Phylogenetic classication and the
universal tree. Science 284:21242129.
74. Woese CR (2004) A new biology for a new century.
Microbiol Mol Biol Rev 68:173186.
75. Frigaard NU, Martinez A, Mincer TJ, DeLong EF (2006)
Proteorhodopsin lateral gene transfer between marine
planktonic Bacteria and Archaea. Nature 439:847850.
76. Woese CR, Olsen GJ, Ibba M, Söll D (2000) Aminoacyl-
tRNA synthetases, the genetic code, and the evolution-
ary process. Microbiol Mol Biol Rev 64:202236.
77. Andam CP, Williams D, Gogarten JP (2010) Natural tax-
onomy in light of horizontal gene transfer. Biol Philos
25:589602.
78. Mayr E (1990) A natural system of organisms. Nature
348:491.
79. Mayr E (1998) Two empires or three? Proc Natl Acad Sci
USA 95:97209723.
80. Woese CR (1998) Default taxonomy: Ernst Mayrs view
of the microbial world. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 95:
1104311046.
81. Fraser C, Alm EJ, Polz MF, Spratt BG, Hanage WP (2009)
The bacterial species challenge: Making sense of ge-
netic and ecological diversity. Science 323:741746.
1018
|
www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1109716109 Pace et al.
... First, the laboratory had to learn the Sanger RNA sequencing technique. This was done when David Bishop, past trainee of Sanger's and then postdoctoral fellow in the neighboring Spiegelman laboratory, taught the technique to Mitchell Sogin, a graduate student in the Woese laboratory (Pace et al., 2012). Then there was the problem of obtaining different bacterial species. ...
... 45 Prior to the negative reception of the published paper, (2.2.4 below) it encountered resistance already upon submission to the Proceedings. One reviewer, criticizing the methodology of the work and rebuffing the claimed three-domain phylogenetic tree, recommended that the paper be rejected (Pace et al., 2012). ...
Article
Full-text available
Observational and experimental discoveries of new factual entities such as objects, systems, or processes, are major contributors to some advances in the life sciences. Yet, whereas discovery of theories was extensively deliberated by philosophers of science, very little philosophical attention was paid to the discovery of factual entities. This paper examines historical and philosophical aspects of the experimental discovery by Carl Woese of archaea, prokaryotes that comprise one of the three principal domains of the phylogenetic tree. Borrowing Kuhn’s terminology, this discovery of a major biological entity was made during a ‘normal science’ project of building molecular taxonomy for prokaryotes. Unexpectedly, however, an observed anomaly instigated the discovery of archaea. Substantiation of the existence of the new archaeal entity and consequent reconstruction of the phylogenetic tree prompted replacement of a long-held model of a prokarya and eukarya bipartite tree of life by a new model of a tripartite tree comprising of bacteria, archaea, and eukarya. This paper explores the history and philosophical implications of the progression of Woese’s project from normal science to anomaly-instigated model-changing discovery. It is also shown that the consequential discoveries of RNA splicing and of ribozymes were similarly prompted by unexpected irregularities during normal science activities. It is thus submitted that some discoveries of factual biological entities are triggered by unforeseen observational or experimental anomalies.
... Phylogenetics, also known as taxonomy, is the study of evolutionary relationships among biological entities, most commonly species, individuals, or genes (Pace et al. 2012;Brower and Schuh 2021). Observation of sequence, reconstruction of evolutionary history, in-depth learning of evolutionary processes, and development of a better evolutionary model are major components of phylogenetics. ...
Chapter
Phylogenetics and phylogenomics are two related fields that deal with the study of the evolutionary relationships between different organisms. In the context of bacteria and archaea phyla, these fields are used to infer the relationships between different species and to understand how they have evolved over time. Phylogenetic methods use genetic data, such as DNA and protein sequences, to reconstruct the evolutionary history of an organism. Phylogenomic methods, on the other hand, take a genome-wide approach and use the entire genome of an organism to infer its evolutionary history. Both of these methods are widely used in the study of bacteria and archaea phyla and have provided valuable insights into the evolution and diversity of these important groups of organisms. The discovery of Sanger sequencing and PCR in the late 1970s paved the way for microbial taxonomy and classification to shift from a traditional to a sequence-based approach. Next-generation sequencing and bioinformatics approaches are now taking microbial taxonomy studies to a new level and making them more firm than ever before. In this chapter, we talked about how phylogenetics and phylogenomics can be used to figure out ancestry and reconstruct evolutionary relationships.
... This most recent revolution was a result of the integration of the first 2. It began in the 1970s with Carl Woese's work [1], in which he used nucleic acid sequences to determine the evolutionary relationships between microbes; however, at that time, the technology was slow and expensive. Advances in nucleic acid chemistry around 2006 (i.e., "next-generation sequencing"), rendered these determinations rapid and inexpensive, thereby democratizing the process. ...
Article
Full-text available
All animals and plants likely require interactions with microbes, often in strong, persistent symbiotic associations. While the recognition of this phenomenon has been slow in coming, it will impact most, if not all, subdisciplines of biology.
... A more complete awareness emerged in 1977 when Carl Woese pioneered phylogenetic taxonomy [3], i.e. a phylogeny based upon the comparison of gene sequences that encode ribosomal RNA. Those data revealed an unexpectedly vast diversity in the microbial world, and drastically changed our view of the phylogenetic relationships within the biosphere [4]. This conceptual advance was followed by development of rapid and inexpensive next-generation sequencing techniques, commercially available beginning in 2005, which led to an explosion in the discovery and characterization of a vast array of new microbial taxa [5][6][7]. ...
Article
Full-text available
At a rapid pace, biologists are learning the many ways in which resident microbes influence, and sometimes even control, their hosts to shape both health and disease. Understanding the biochemistry behind these interactions promises to reveal completely novel and targeted ways of counteracting disease processes. However, in our protocols and publications, we continue to describe these new results using a language that originated in a completely different context. This language developed when microbial interactions with hosts were perceived to be primarily pathogenic, as threats that had to be vanquished. Biomedicine had one dominating thought: winning this war against microorganisms. Today, we know that beyond their defensive roles, host tissues, especially epithelia, are vital to ensuring association with the normal microbiota, the communities of microbes that persistently live with the host. Thus, we need to adopt a language that better encompasses the newly appreciated importance of host-microbiota associations. We also need a language that frames the onset and progression of pathogenic conditions within the context of the normal microbiota. Such a reimagined lexicon should make it clear, from the very nature of its words, that microorganisms are primarily vital to our health, and only more rarely the cause of disease. This article is part of the theme issue ‘Sculpting the microbiome: how host factors determine and respond to microbial colonization’.
... This modest table would be the very first sequence-based quantitative assessment of phylogenetic relationships between organisms. Though the unfamiliarity of the process and results presented by Woese and Fox at the time caused the paper to, initially, receive little attention and, later, become a target for criticism from the scientific community, it endured (Pace et al., 2012). Since then, however, phylogenetic systematics has become the archetype approach for the study of systematics and the primary methodology for researching evolution. ...
Thesis
Full-text available
Podarcis vaucheri (Boulenger 1905) and Psammodromus algirus (Linnaeus 1759) are two lacertid lizards native to the Iberian Peninsula and North Africa. Regarding phylogeographic patterns, although the species have been thoroughly studied within their European ranges, knowledge of their variation South of the Strait of Gibraltar remains limited. With this thesis we intended to improve the genetic coverage for both species within their Moroccan range, and to address some issues regarding typically considered taxonomic notions for them: the existence of two main lineages within P. vaucheri—the “main type” and the “Jebel Sirwah” variant—that could warrant its split into two or more separate species; and the appropriateness of the split of P. algirus into two subspecies—P. a. algirus and P. a. nollii—based on their dorsal striped patterns. To achieve our aims, we mainly employed molecular tools, estimating the phylogenetic relationships between individuals within the area, with comprehensive samplings across most of their known ranges. Mitochondrial and a nuclear gene sequences—respectively partial ND4 and partial MC1R—were used. For the P. vaucheri study, this was complemented with species range modelling analysis, in an attempt to understand interactions with the landscape and range contractions and expansions of the species across time.
... Using real and simulated data we found that the topology of a reconstructed phylogenetic tree can be affected by the substitution model used for the reconstruction. Of course and in agreement with (Spielman 2020), we found that phylogenetic trees inferred under similar empirical substitution models, in datasets with low genetic diversity, may not differ [although one can also properly consider that minor differences in the topology of a phylogenetic tree could be dramatic for diverse evolutionary studies (e.g., Soltis and Soltis 2003;Davis et al. 2010;Pace et al. 2012;Moreira et al. 2021)]. However, in other scenarios (i.e., data with large genetic diversity) we found relevant influences of substitution model selection on protein phylogenetic tree reconstruction. ...
Article
Full-text available
Probabilistic phylogenetic tree reconstruction is traditionally performed under a best-fitting substitution model of molecular evolution previously selected according to diverse statistical criteria. Interestingly, some recent studies proposed that this procedure is unnecessary for phylogenetic tree reconstruction leading to a debate in the field. In contrast to DNA sequences, phylogenetic tree reconstruction from protein sequences is traditionally based on empirical exchangeability matrices that can differ among taxonomic groups and protein families. Considering this aspect, here we investigated the influence of selecting a substitution model of protein evolution on phylogenetic tree reconstruction by the analyses of real and simulated data. We found that phylogenetic tree reconstructions based on a selected best-fitting substitution model of protein evolution are the most accurate, in terms of topology and branch lengths, compared with those derived from substitution models with amino acid replacement matrices far from the selected best-fitting model, especially when the data has large genetic diversity. Indeed, we found that substitution models with similar amino acid replacement matrices produce similar reconstructed phylogenetic trees, suggesting the use of substitution models as similar as possible to a selected best-fitting model when the latter cannot be used. Therefore, we recommend the use of the traditional protocol of selection among substitution models of evolution for protein phylogenetic tree reconstruction.
Chapter
In this world, animals are teeming with different microbes comprising bacteria, fungi, and viruses. Animal-microbe interactions have become an interesting research area because of their beneficial and significant role in human life. The human microbiome project reported the significance of gut microbes and also explained complex diversity in a way to equilibrium maintained. For instance, gut microbes help control the colonization of exogenous pathogens. The beneficial role of microbes in humans extended the knowledge from individual taxa to a level of an ecosystem. However, rapid-growing technology provided a great understanding of individual microbes. Little is known about the microbiota association with animals and humans and the significance of microbial consortia in the ecosystem. The knowledge of microbes and host metabolism and their influence on modifying the microbiota ecosystem is important to understand microbiota’s beneficial and pathogenic efficacy. This chapter outlined the current knowledge of microbiota and microbiome in ecosystems and their significant role in human and animal life.
Thesis
Full-text available
This research explored urban changes in the north-central region of the Nile Delta —from the beginning of the Dynastic period (ca. 3150 BCE) until the beginning of the Tulunid dynasty (868 CE)— using a multi-dimensional, long-term approach with different independent variables: Spatiotemporal, Cultural and Urbanistic, Hydrological or Geomorphological, Historical, and Contextual. To investigate the location, connectivity, and permanence of the known archaeological settlements in the Nile Delta, an extended version of the Egyptian Exploration Society’s Delta Survey database was created to analyse settlement patterns through time compared against an original reconstruction of a palimpsestual river network using remote sensing, historical sources, archaeological and geomorphological data, spatial and network analysis. This investigation has studied the extent to which human agency and geomorphology are intertwined and shape urban patterns in the Nile Delta; against the long-lived idea that the Nile River has almost exclusively made Egypt and that the river fluctuations have shaped the Egyptian urban landscape. For some authors like Fernand Braudel, the Nile River has defined the Egyptian world to the point of accepting that Egypt was considered a gift from the Nile, whereas, by contrast, Mesopotamia was made by human hands. In this thesis, however, it is argued that humans and their politics have played a more important role in defining the Nilotic landscape. Hence, this research explored to what extent river shifts and human agency have impacted urban patterns and settlement locations from the Old Kingdom to the modern era with the construction of the High Aswan Dam. Regardless of river fluctuations, settlements persisted, and disastrous events obliterating cities are exceptional events. Urban fluctuations, bliss or misery, heydays or collapse, are certainly political and social happenings intermingled with the omnipresent river Nile.
Article
Article
The frequent discrepancy between direct microscopic counts and numbers of culturable bacteria from environmental samples is just one of several indications that we currently know only a minor part of the diversity of microorganisms in nature. A combination of direct retrieval of rRNA sequences and whole-cell oligonucleotide probing can be used to detect specific rRNA sequences of uncultured bacteria in natural samples and to microscopically identify individual cells. Studies have been performed with microbial assemblages of various complexities ranging from simple two-component bacterial endosymbiotic associations to multispecies enrichments containing magnetotactic bacteria to highly complex marine and soil communities. Phylogenetic analysis of the retrieved rRNA sequence of an uncultured microorganism reveals its closest culturable relatives and may, together with information on the physicochemical conditions of its natural habitat, facilitate more directed cultivation attempts. For the analysis of complex communities such as multispecies biofilms and activated-sludge flocs, a different approach has proven advantageous. Sets of probes specific to different taxonomic levels are applied consecutively beginning with the more general and ending with the more specific (a hierarchical top-to-bottom approach), thereby generating increasingly precise information on the structure of the community. Not only do rRNA-targeted whole-cell hybridizations yield data on cell morphology, specific cell counts, and in situ distributions of defined phylogenetic groups, but also the strength of the hybridization signal reflects the cellular rRNA content of individual cells. From the signal strength conferred by a specific probe, in situ growth rates and activities of individual cells might be estimated for known species. In many ecosystems, low cellular rRNA content and/or limited cell permeability, combined with background fluorescence, hinders in situ identification of autochthonous populations. Approaches to circumvent these problems are discussed in detail.