ArticlePDF Available

Davydov’s concept of the concept and its dialectical materialist background

Authors:

Abstract

The goal of this article is to investigate Davydov’s concept of the concept against the backdrop of its philosophical system, namely, dialectical materialism. In the first part, after briefly sketching the context of Davydov’s work, I consider some ontological and epistemological ideas on which Davydov bases his concept of the concept. I pay particular attention to Hegel’s and Marx’s contributions. Then, I discuss Davydov’s concept of the concept and the relationship between the logical and the historical—a relationship that proved to be crucial in the making of the educational curricular program he and El’konin launched in the 1960s in Russia. I argue that, in tune with the dominant epistemology of the twentieth century, Davydov’s concept of the concept is based on a scientific outlook of the world, one in which theoretical scientific thought is considered the pinnacle of human cognition. I conclude with a critique that intends to place the notion of the concept in a broader dialectical materialist perspective.
Radford, L. (2021). Davydov’s concept of the concept and its dialectical materialist
background. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 106, 327342.
Davydov’s concept of the concept and its
dialectical materialist background
Luis Radford
Abstract
The goal of this article is to investigate Davydovs concept of the concept against the
backdrop of its philosophical system, namely, dialectical materialism. In the first part,
after briefly sketching the context of Davydovs work, I consider some ontological and
epistemological ideas on which Davydov bases his concept of the concept. I pay
particular attention to Hegels and Marxs contributions. Then, I discuss Davydovs
concept of the concept and the relationship between the logical and the historicala
relationship that proved to be crucial in the making of the educational curricular program
he and Elkonin launched in the 1960s in Russia. I argue that, in tune with the dominant
epistemology of the twentieth century, Davydovs concept of the concept is based on a
scientific outlook of the world, one in which theoretical scientific thought is considered
the pinnacle of human cognition. I conclude with a critique that intends to place the
notion of the concept in a broader dialectical materialist perspective.
1
Introduction
One of the best-known works of Vasily Vasilyevich Davydov, at least in the Western world, is
Types of Generalization in Instruction (Davydov, 1990). In this book, Davydov provides a
definition of what a concept is. He says:
A concept functions here as a form of mental activity by means of which an idealized
object and the system of its connections, which reflect in their unity the generality or
essence of movement of the material object, are reproduced. (Davydov, 1990, p. 116;
emphasis in the original)
328
This article is a critical commentary on Davydovs functionalist concept of the concept. My
critical commentarywhich is part of an increasing interest in better understanding the nature
of mathematical concepts (de Freitas, Sinclair, & Coles, 2017)is an attempt to investigate
Davydovs concept of the concept against the backdrop of its philosophical system, namely
dialectical materialism. My contention is that it is only through an examination of the philo-
sophical system that underpins Davydov
s work that we can fully appreciate both his concept of
the concept and its educational implications. I start by offering a short sketch of the historical
context of Davydov
s work and the general vision that oriented his curricular research. Then, I
discuss some key ideas of Davydov
s dialectical materialist background. The rest of the article
revolves around Davydovs concept of the concept and the problem of the historical and the
logical, a problem that proved to be crucial in the making of the educational curricular program
Davydov and Daniil Elkonin launched in the 1960s in Russia. Drawing on Heideggers view
of Being and Adornos negative dialectics, I conclude with a critique that intends to place the
notion of the concept in a broader dialectical materialist perspective.
2
The context
In 1959, 2 years after having defended his doctoral thesis under the guidance of Piotor
Galperin, Davydov started working at the Institute of General and Pedagogical Psychology
of the Academy of Medical Sciences of the USSR (Rubtsov, 2015). In collaboration with
El
konin, he started developing a
modeling experiment,
which came later to be known as the
Elkonin-Davydov curriculum. Davydovs modeling experiment was embedded in a Soviet
educational reform initiated in 1958 by Nikita Khrushchevs government. The reform sought
to overcome the poor
academic level of students and their [in]ability to apply their knowledge
to practical tasks and workplace-related activities(Boyko, 2019, p. 83). In mathematics, the
reform was led by the famous mathematician Andrey Kolmogorov. It is in this context that
governmental efforts were made to rebuild the curriculum and to produce new textbooks
(Abramov, 2010). Commenting on the inadequacy of the mathematics curriculum of the time,
Davydov (1975a) notes that Deficiencies in the traditional mathematics curricula for the
school are being discussed frequently both here and abroad (p. 55).
Davydov cites Kolmogorov, saying that mathematics
studies the material world from a particular point of view, that its immediate subject is
the spatial forms and quantitative relationships of the real world. These forms and
relationships themselves, in their pure form, rather than specific material bodies, are the
reality which mathematics studies. (Kolmogorov, cited in Davydov, 1975a p. 68;
emphasis as in Davydovs passage)
From this viewpoint, Davydov notes:
The curriculum should provide the child with work in which he (sic) will be able to
move away from concrete bodies accurately and at the proper moment, after having
distinguished their spatial forms and quantitative relations and having given them their
pure form.
Only on the basis of this can he (sic) develop an accurate understanding of
mathematics. (Davydov, 1975a, p. 68)
Naturally, the child cannot start from the pure forms of mathematics. What the research
mathematician has before him (sic) in its
pure form
has to be constructed in the child
s head.
329
This form is not given to him (sic) at the start (Davydov, 1975a, p. 68). The fundamental
question was then as follows: What organization of the course and what method of intro-
ducing concepts contributes best to the solution of this problem?(p. 68). Davydovs
experimental research, carried out for about 25 years and mainly conducted at the Experimen-
tal School N. 91 in Moscow, was an attempt at answering this question. Davydov argued that
the curriculum should be based on clear logical principles to structure its content. He claimed
that it is particularly necessary to determine the most appropriate concepts with which to
begin mathematics instruction in school(1975a, p. 56). Structuring the curriculum through
logical principles was, however, not enough. An appropriate psychological approach was also
needed. As he put it, the outdated curriculum of his time was failing to provide for the
necessary development of childrens mathematical thought (1975a, p. 55).
But the distinctiveness of Davydovs approach is not to be found in his resorting to
logical and psychological principles to structure the mathematics curriculum. What
makes it really distinctive is Davydovs understanding of the logical and psychological
principles. Drawing on dialectical materialism, he derived the overarching goal of his
whole enterprise. The goal was not about developing a curriculum that would allow the
child to simply acquire mathematical knowledge. To think so is to miss entirely
Davydovs whole point. As Schmittau and Morris aptly put it, Davydovs curriculum
has as its overriding goal the development of the ability to think theoretically (2004, p.
61; see also Ivashova, 2011, p. 59) or, in the words of Libâneo and Freitas, the
formation of theoretical-scientific thought (2013, p. 318). Now, for Davydov, the
attainment of theoretical-scientific thought is not the result of a speculative mind getting
hold of concepts through ruminative cogitations. It is rather a sensuous developmental
process that, in tune with Vygotskys school of thought, privileges the process of
generalization. Starting from material objects and the immediate character of empirical
knowledge(Davydov, 1990, p. 115; emphasis in the original), generalization allows one
to recognize the inner structure of scientific concepts and the system of their constitutive
connections.
Thus, when Davydov intends to understand what a number is, he purposely moves beyond
the immediacy of empirical knowledge and tries hard to find the theoretical connections that
would constitute the scientific concept of number. After a theoretical archeological excavation
(of which I will have more to say below), rather than counting aggregates of objectsrather
than cardinality as such
he finds relations: relations like
more than,
” “
less than,
and
equal
to (Davydov, 1975a, 1975b, 2008). From here he devises a curricular organization of
arithmetic and algebra that might look puzzling when considered from traditional epistemol-
ogies like those offered by idealism and empiricism.
Davydov presented a schema of the main curricular ideas in various papers (see, e.g.,
Davydov, 1975b; see also Schmittau & Morris, 2004). I will limit myself here to merely
mention that the curriculum starts with a focus on a quantitative comparison of quantities
(length, width, volume, and area), first on instructional material, then on representations
through line segments and letters, in order to assert whether A = B, A B, A > B, or A <
B, without reference to numbers. In Davydovs view, the use of symbols is required to
help children move away from specific objects and to pay attention to the connections at
the heart of theoretical concepts. Symbols, indeed, help the children to divorce them-
selves from using objects so that they can focus on verbal and logical evaluations
(constructions of the type: ifandthen…’) (Davydov, 1975b, p. 140). As a result of
plunging into the theoretical realm through symbols, What becomes central for the
330
children is the relationship itself, its type, rather than the [material] objects (Davydov,
1975b, p. 164).1
In a similar vein, the children use letters to represent unknown parts of a whole (e.g., h + r =
t) and reflect on their mutual connections (see Schmittau & Morris, 2004, p. 70; see also
Freiman and Fellus, this Special Issue). The use of letters, however, should not be seen as
something that makes the child enter automatically into the realm of algebra. For Davydov,
algebra is not about using letters. To understand the use of letters in Davydovs approach, we
have to bear in mind that Davydov is following the Vygotskian tradition where theoretical
thinking is mediated. And it is this mediationa theoretical mediationthat signs are
accomplishing. Signs, in this account, allow the child to perceive, deal with, and reproduce
the essence of the object under study. This is why it is crucial, for example, that in the
reproduction of the essence of number, children shift from equality (A = B) to inequality (A +
K > B) and back (A + K = B + K) (Davydov, 1975b, p. 137).
Davydovs logical approach to the concept of number and its shift from techniques of
calculation
to the study of the structural characteristics of mathematical
objects
’”
(Davydov,
1975b, p. 141) is a reminiscence of Piagets epistemological analyses. Yet, while Piaget talks
about invariants, one-to-one correspondence, and abstraction (Piaget, 1964), Davydov (1990),
by contrast, talks about generalizationthe generalization of material objects into idealized
objects, which, as it proceeds in practical, sensuous activity, discloses the generality or essence
of the object. The general that this general-ity produces should not to be confounded with the
general of empiricist generalizations. The general (or essence) that Davydov refers to has to be
understood in its dialectical materialist sense, that is, as the genetically initial cellof some
developing integral system which generates all its particular manifestations
(Davydov, 1967,
p. 50; emphasis in the original).
The goal of the two following sections is to offer an overview of Davydovs dialectical
materialist background. Although the content is theoretical, I hope that it will be helpful in
better appreciating Davydovs approach and in particular his concept of the concept, which I
see as the cell of his curricular enterprise. My overview is organized in two parts, one
dealing with ontology (which explains, for instance, Davydovs insistence that a concept is
made up of internal connections), and one dealing with epistemology (which explains how
things are known).
3
The ontology of dialectical materialism
3.1
The principle of universal connection
Davydov
s dialectical materialism starts from a Spinozist, systemic, ontological premise about
the nature of the world (Spinoza, 1989). According to this premise, the world is an aggregate
1
Here is an example:
The students are shown a picture of two balloons. The volume of one balloon is labeled L; this balloon is
completely drawn. The other balloon of volume P is only partially drawn. The problem says: If L = T and
T > P, then L
P. The students are unable to directly compare the volumes (one is only partially drawn)
so
they have to make an inference about the relationship between L and P. (Schmittau & Morris, 2004,
pp. 6364)
331
of objects and phenomena linked with one another by extremely diverse relations and
connections (Spirkin, 1990, p. 119).
The idea that objects are linked to other objects through systems of relations and connec-
tions is articulated in the work of Hegel, upon which dialectical materialism draws. In the
Encyclopaedia, Hegel notes that A determinate content . . . contains a manifold connection
within itself and is the basis for connections with many other objects (Hegel, 1991, p. 89;
emphasis in the original). As a result, in this view, material and ideational objects are not
merely substantial things. Objects are relational through and through. The essence of an
objectand in the previous section we saw this idea in Davydovs account of number
consists indeed in the connections that link such an object to other objects.
3.2
Motion and development
Dialectical materialism considers the world in constant motion. All is in flux, on the path
toward something else (Spirkin, 1990, p. 123), pushed, so to speak, in one direction or
another by connections and relations. In social life, for instance, the needs and interests of
people constitute basic connections that underlie the forms of production of a community.
Among the different types of connection in the universe, there is one that plays a significant
role in dialectical materialism: it is the law-governed connection, which serves to explain
development:
Development is an irreversible, definitely oriented and law-governed change of
material and ideal objects resulting in the emergence of new qualities
(Spirkin, 1990, p. 123;
emphasis in the original).
In general terms, law-governed connections can be conceived of in several different ways.
They can be conceived of as laws of the worldobjective laws that have nothing to do with
the individuals. These laws are not human-made. The discovery of the laws that govern the
universe is indeed, in this line of thought, the task of scientific research. Dialectical materialism
adopts here a kind of Galilean view of the universe, which provides it with scientific-rationalist
ontology.
Law-governed connections can also be understood as laws created by the individuals
subjective laws that individuals produce to make sense of their world. So, while the first
Galilean view gives the primacy to the object (truth lies in the object), the second one gives the
primacy to the subject (truth lies in the subject).
Davydov draws on a different dialecticsa Hegelian dialectics as articulated further by
Marx. This materialist dialectics rests on a view where subject and object become entangled,
so that law-governed connections always contain the imprint of human activity, which makes
them neither transcendental vis-à-vis the individuals nor merely subjective.
There is another question that we need to discussthe meaning of the essence that, as we
saw in the Introduction, Davydov brings to the fore in his understanding of what a concept is.
3.3
Essence and phenomena
Dialectical materialism makes from the outset a distinction between essence and phenom-
ena. Essence and phenomena are part of two different ontological realms. A phenomenon
(or appearance) is what is observable, sensible. Essence, by contrast, is inaccessible to
human perception. In the words of Davydov, essences are internal, essential relationships
[that] cannot be observed directly by the senses(Davydov, 1990, p. 119; emphasis in the
original).
332
While in Kants (2003) dualistic theory of knowledge, the realm of the essence (the realm
of things-in-themselves) remains beyond human cognition, for Hegelian dialectical materialism
this is not the case. There is a clear and explicit relationship between them: within the dynamic
ontological view of the universe, essences are conceived of as continuously passing into
appearances.
Essence, Spirkin says, is the basis of all the forms of their external manifestation . . .
Essence is in this sense something internal, a certain organizing principle of the objects
existence in the forms of its external expression (Spirkin, 1990, p. 155; emphasis in the
original).
The problem of theoretical thought is precisely to reveal the connections and relations of
objects, as these connections manifest externally or actualize themselves in the realm of
objectively interconnected phenomena (Davydov, 1990, p. 119).2
Within the dialectical materialist framework, essences lose the metaphysical meaning with
which idealism endowed them. Essences as a system of internal connections manifest them-
selves in motion, in practical activityas when children compare lengths of visible, non-
visible or partially visible objects (as in footnote 1) or add fractions (Swanson & Williams,
2014).
4
The epistemology of dialectical materialism
The previous section offered a short account of the ontology of dialectical materialism. Now
we turn to its epistemology. The question is: What does it mean to know? The answer is in
Hegels work. As previously mentioned, for Hegel, an object of knowledge is a determinate
content; that is, a manifold of connections within itself and the basis for connections with other
objects. In this context, To be cognizant,Hegel says, means nothing else but the knowing
of an object according to its determinate content
(Hegel, 1991, p. 89). In other words, I know
something if I go beyond the superficial aspect of the object and know its essence (internal
relations and connections). The question that naturally arises in this context is the question of
the kind of knowing that we, as humans, are capable of. Hegel notes that
if we inquire into the truth of knowledge, it seems that we are asking what knowledge is
in itself. Yet in this inquiry knowledge is our object, something that exists for us; and the
in-itself that would supposedly result from it would rather be the being of knowledge for
us. What we asserted to be its essence would be not so much its truth but rather just our
knowledge of it. (Hegel, 1977, p. 53; emphasis in the original)
Knowledge, hence, would not be knowledge of the object itself, but our knowledge of it.
Consciousness provides its own criterion from within itself, so that the investigation becomes
a comparison of consciousness with itself (Hegel, 1977, p. 53).
The object, it is true, seems only to be for consciousness in the way that consciousness
knows it; it seems that consciousness cannot, as it were, get behind the object as it exists
for consciousness so as to examine what the object is in itself. (Hegel, 1977, p. 54;
emphasis in the original)
2 The adjective objective should not be understood as independent of the individual. As mentioned previously,
in dialectical materialism, the connections between things and phenomena refract the entanglement between
subject and object.
333
Imagining the object as concealed behind a curtain, Hegel says that
there is nothing to be seen
unless we go behind [the curtain] ourselves (Hegel, 1977, p. 103; emphasis in the original).
However, what we would see, were we to walk behind the curtain, is ourselves at work. The
inside of things is a construction of the mind. If we try to lift the veil that covers the real, what
we will find is only ourselves, the universalizing activity of the mind that we call understand-
ing (Andler, 1931, p. 332).
It seems, then, that we have reached an impasse and that, as humans, we are limited to have
a subjective knowledge of things, knowledge of appearances only. This was Kants (2003)
conclusion. In Kants account, this was the limit of pure human reason. But it is precisely at
this point that Hegel went further. He reasoned that if the comparison between the object and
our knowledge about it (the object in itself and the object for us or for consciousness) do not
correspond, we still can alter our knowledge
to make it conform to the object
(Hegel, 1977,
p. 54).
However, Hegels crucial innovation is not to be found in the adjusting endeavor of our
knowledge to make it come closer and closer to the object, to its essence, to Truth. What Hegel
is articulating in these passages is a new theory of knowing that moves epistemology beyond
the classical objectivist and subjectivist paradigms of Western thought.
We see that consciousness now has two objects: one is the first in-itself, the second is the
being for-consciousness of this in-itself . . . the first object, in being known, is altered for
consciousness; it ceases to be the in-itself, and becomes something that is the in-itself
only for consciousness. (Hegel, 1977, p. 55; emphasis in the original)
As a result, there is an entanglement between object and subject, world and consciousness.
They co-produce each other mutually.
Hegels theoretical position gained great popularity during the nineteenth century in
German intellectual circles. German philosophers engaged in discussions about his work
one way or the other. And Karl Marx was certainly not the exception. He found Hegels
account very idealistic. For Marx, the entanglement between object and subject is not the result
of a majestic flight of consciousness in its march to perfection. In the first of the Theses on
Feuerbach (Marx, 1998), the co-creation of subjects and objects and their entanglement are
explained as occurring in something terrestrial: in praxis, or sensuous collective human
practical activity. Through praxis human affection and cognition become
inscribed in matter
(Aron, 1981, p. 91). This inscription constitutes the essential structure of reality
Wirklichkeit,
which for Marx signifies effective reality; that is to say,
everything that offers itself first of all
to consciousness as constituting reality
(Macherey, 2008, p. 47). In this way, effective reality
embraces much more than the products of human activity (i.e., les oeuvres humaines): it also
embraces the embodiments of social needs built culturally and historically and the ideas and
values of a given culture at a certain moment (Descombes, 1996). As a result, objects (material
or ideal) do not present to us as untouched by humans but as something already carved by
history. In this line of thought, truth is neither on the side of the object (as ahistorical
materialism suggested) nor on the side of the subject (as idealism and empiricism contended).
In articulating the epistemological question of the subject and object in this way, by going
beyond the classical dichotomy objective/subjective, Marx opened up a fresh avenue to look at
human cognition in a new anthropological way (Dupré, 1983; Henry, 1976). To know an
object amounts to putting into action a dynamic of reflection and explanation that reproduces
the very movement of reality without . . . fixing it in the consideration of some of its isolated
results, cut off from the complex conditions of their elaboration (Macherey, 2008, p. 74).
334
It is from this anthropological perspective on human cognition that Davydovand before
him, Vygotsky, Luria, and Leontevexplored a new path to the study of human psychology.
And it is in this sense that consciousness and objects appear in Davydov
s work. For Davydov,
objects are objects of need. He quotes Rubinstein: Objects of needs and actions, rather than
objects of contemplation, are given initially (Davydov, 1990, p. 111). He also quotes G. A.
Kursanov: For a thing to function for human consciousness, it should function as an object of
activity (p. 190; emphasis in the original).
Bearing in mind the previous dialectical materialist background, we can now turn to
Davydovs concept of the concept.
5
Davydov’s concept of the concept
As mentioned in the introduction, Davydov defined a concept as follows:
A concept functions here as a form of mental activity by means of which an idealized
object and the system of its connections, which reflect in their unity the generality or
essence of movement of the material object, are reproduced. A concept simultaneously
also functions as a form for reflecting the material object and as a means of mentally
reproducing, constructing itthat is, as a particular mental action. (Davydov, 1990, p.
116; emphasis in the original)
He explains that, ontogenetically speaking, this object appears first as existing independently
of the individual. There is, hence, an element of passivity where the object appears having an
objective content vis-à-vis the individual and an element of activity since
to have a concept of
an object means to reproduce or construct it mentally (Davydov, 1990, p. 116). Davydov
continues: This action of constructing and transforming a mental object is an act of under-
standing and explaining it, of discovering its essence (p. 116).
He sympathetically cites Kant who has astutely noted that thinking means acting’”
(Davydov, 1990, p. 116). In this context, Davydov mentions Kant
s concept of the schema and
reminds us that Kants key terms such as drawing or describing in the formation of
schemas are
none other than reproducing or constructing an object on an ideal level
(p. 117).
He ends up approvingly citing Y. M. Borodii saying that a concept is a rule for reproducing
an object, or, expressed in Hegels language, a measure (p. 190).
There are three things in Davydovs concept of the concept:
(1)
A concept is a form of mental activity.
(2)
It reproduces or constructs on an ideal level the essence of the object.
(3)
It works normatively.
I will dwell on these points below.
(1)
A concept is a form of mental activity.
The first point indicates that a concept is a psychological entity. It is an activity carried out
by an individual. This activity is of a certain type. It is mental.
(2)
A concept reproduces or constructs the essence of the object.
The second point states that, in the concept of an object, the essence of the object can be
captured in its mental construction or reproduction. Not any reproduction will fit here. The
construction has to satisfy a condition: it is supposed to reproduce the objects essence. We
335
can ask the question: is such a thing possible? For Davydov, it is. And, as we can see, this is a
very strong epistemological assumption.
Of course, Davydov was very well aware of the epistemological commitment he was
making. In fact, on this point, as we saw above, he drew on Kants concept of the schema and
the role imagination plays therein. He wrote: Kant was right in indicating its [the imagina-
tion
s] role in constructing a concept
(Davydov, 1990, p. 118). But he disagreed with Kant on
two counts:
First, he disagreed with Kants assumption that schema-making and imagination are
both powers of the mind (something that is built into the architectonics of the human
mind). On this point, Davydov and Kant are far away from each other. As a good
dialectical materialist thinker, Davydov understood human cognition as something deep-
ly related to the cultural-historical context. We find the following statement at the very
beginning of his very dense chapter Basic Propositions in the Dialectical Materialist
Theory of Thought: An individual persons thought is the functioning of historically
developed forms of societys activity which have been conferred on him (Davydov,
1990, p. 108; emphasis in the original). And then, this other statement: An analysis of
the origin and development of thought must begin with a clarification of the features of
human labor activity (Davydov, 1990, p. 108). These statements, which derive from
Marxs ideas of effective reality (Wirklichkeit) and human cognition discussed above, are
antithetic to Kants conception of human thought. Kants philosophy and dialectical
materialism parted ways here and ended up informing two radically different
pedagogiesone articulated around the work of Piaget and the other articulated around
the work of Vygotsky, one of which is the Elkonin-Davydov Program.
Second, Davydov is in disagreement with Kant on the role of material culture in the
constitution of the schema. For Davydov, the question of material culture is crucial as it is
through the practical activity with concrete objects, and more specifically with their conceptual
transformation, that the essence of an object can be disclosed. Davydov wrote that through the
transformation of material things
the learning person comes to understand the relation between
a material
s external appearances and changes in appearances
(Davydov, 1999, p. 126).
So, there are important disagreements in the ways Davydov and Kant understood the
human mind. Both thinkers recognize the active side of the mind in concept formation, but
they end up taking different routes.
The differences may be better appreciated if we bear in mind the fact that Davydovs
concept of the concept draws from an epistemological shift that occurred in sixteenth century
Europe. Before this shift, to know a thing was generally understood as to know the properties
of such a thing. This conception of knowing was epitomized by classical Greek geometry.
Then, with the arrival of new forms of production in the late Middle Ages and early
Renaissance, with the invention of Western capitalism, the conception of knowing changed.
As Arendt put it, within the new epistemology of early modernity, to know something became
associated with knowing the manner of its production: I know a thing whenever I under-
stand how it has come into being(Arendt, 1958, p. 585). We find this conception clearly
articulated in Spinozas 1667 text (modern edition in Spinoza, 1989), De Intellectus
Emendatione (Improvement of the Understanding). Spinoza says that a true idea shows
how and why something is or has been made (1989, p. 29). Thus,
If a circle be defined as a figure, such that all straight lines drawn from the center to the
circumference are equal, every one (sic) can see that such a definition does not in the
336
least explain the essence of a circle, but solely one of its properties. (Spinoza, 1989, p.
32)
Within the new epistemological paradigm, the how and why something is or has been made
have to be revealed in what Spinoza calls its
proximate cause.
Spinoza then gives the proper
definition: the figure described by any line whereof one end is fixed and the other free. This
definition clearly comprehends the proximate cause (Spinoza, 1989, p. 32).
Spinozas concept of proximate cause is what appeared later thematized as a schema or a
rule, as we have seen in Davydovs concept of the concept. In his commentary on Spinozas
definition of the circle, Davydov says:
Spinoza perceived the essence of a circle in the act of its emergence or construction
(creation). Its definition should express the reason why the given thing arose, the
method of constructing it . . . Here a method of obtaining any and infinitely varied
circles is given. (Davydov, 1990, p. 117)
Spinozas definition of a circle is cited again and again by dialectician thinkersDavydov
himself, as we have seen, but also other dialecticians such as Ilyenkov (1977). Its importance
does not reside only in that it provides us with a neat and short example of a concept (i.e., as
something rule-based). The example can also be thought of in terms of an activity with a
concrete objectthe compassthrough which a transformation of material marks on a paper
may acquire a theoretical content.
(3)
A concept works normatively.
The third point about Davydovs concept of the concept refers to the regulatory feature of
concepts. As Davydov put it, individuals act and produce things according to the concepts
which exist as norms in the society beforehand (1990, p. 118). From an ontogenetic
viewpoint, in this perspective, individuals do not create concepts; they encounter them. This
point has to do with one of the main tenets of dialectical materialism that I mentioned before,
according to which individuals find the conditions of possibility of their thinking in the
historically developed forms of activities of their society.
I shall come back to the implications of Davydovs ontological position in the concluding
section. For the time being, I want to discuss the question of the historical and the logical
aspects of concepts.
6
The historical and the logical
Davydov did not embrace a recapitulationist idea of concept development. That is, he did not
accept the idea that ontogenesis is a recapitulation of phylogenesis, or, more simply put, that
human cognitive development follows the same path as the historical path in the development
of ideas. To accept a full repetition would mean that knowledge would repeat itself regardless
of time and culture. On the other hand, to accept a full independence between ontogenesis and
phylogenesis would amount to reducing the production of knowledge to what individuals do
right now, independent of historical influences. To accept a full independence between
ontogenesis and phylogenesis could easily lead to the kind of epistemological subjectivism
that we find in Kants theory of knowledge, for instance. These two extreme points (full
recapitulation and full independence) are at odds with the tenets of Hegels dialectics and its
ensuing dialectical materialism. Davydov offers an intermediate position. Ontogenesis repeats
337
phylogenesis in some qualified sense only. As he put it, Ontogenesis . . . does not repeat
phylogenesis in totality
(Davydov, 1975a, p. 65; my emphasis). There must be some kind of
relationship between them. But what is it?
Davydovs educational work is, in practice, articulated around this question. As mentioned
in Section 2, Davydov believed that the school curriculum should start from the basic or
essential connections that make up the essence of the conceptual objects to be learned. There is
an important ontological assumption here: according to this assumption, objects of knowledge
can be broken down into a few relations or connections. The problem, then, is to find those
small relations or connections. This ontological assumption is supplemented with a method-
ological one: history, on the one hand, and current mathematics on the other, can provide us
with the clues to find them. In other words, we need to look at the historical and the logical
dimensions of knowledge, and their relationship.
In dialectical materialism, such a relationship is often considered in the following terms.
The logical is associated with the movement of essences. The historical is associated with the
actual movement of the phenomena of effective reality. In this context, the logical is consid-
ered as the theoretical reflection of the historical (see Kopnin, 1966, p. 84). In terms of the
concepts discussed in the previous sections, history finds its material in the ontological
category of Appearance or Phenomena (the Concrete)not in the category of essences (the
Abstract). But, as mentioned before, in dialectical materialism, these categories are deeply
interconnected. History, it turns out, is but another name for the theoretical principle of the
unity between the Abstract and the Concrete, Essence, and Appearance. This is why the logical
aspect of an object,
besides reflecting the history of the object itself, also reflects the history of
its knowledge
(Kopnin, 1966, p. 188). It does not come as a surprise, then, that the problem of
the relation between the logical and the historical constitutes
the most important [problem] of
dialectical logic (Kopnin, 1966, p. 84).
From a methodological viewpoint, To reveal the essence of an object it is necessary to
reproduce the actual historical process of its development
(Kopnin, 1966, p. 186; emphasis in
the original). But at the same time, the reproduction of the actual historical process of the
objects development is only possible if we know the essence of the given object (Kopnin,
1966, p. 186). It seems that we run into a vicious circle. Marx (1993) agonized in front of this
problem in the Grundrisse, where he was trying to find the proper categories to understand
production and consumption. So, how do we get out of this vicious circle? The dialectical
answer is this: We can grasp the essence by studying its more mature forms as they appear in
the phenomenological realm. This is why, The researcher must begin the study of the object
by the end, by the most mature form; for in this most mature form, [the] essential aspects [of
the object] appear in a more developed way
(Kopnin, 1966, p. 186). Hence, it does not come
as a surprise that Vygotsky cites Marx arguing that the anatomy of man (sic) is the key to the
anatomy of the ape (Vygotsky, 1978, p. 94). It does not come as a surprise either that in his
investigations Davydov turned to the most evolved mathematical forms of his time. What did
he find? Bourbaki. The Modern Mathematics of the twentieth century: Bourbaki, but also
Lebesgue, Kolmogorov, and others. Through his habitual sharp, penetrating, incisive, and
brilliant multidisciplinary approach, he embarked in a theoretical archeological excavation to
understand these most mature mathematical forms. What he found was a structural conception
of mathematics. Davydov cites Bourbaki extensively and his idea that the fundamental
mathematical notion is not the number. In mathematicslike in life, as understood by the
Marxist structuralists of Davydov
s time, such as Althusser (1965)
there are structures rather
than objects. Davydov hence searched hard to find those essential connections and relations
338
out of which mathematics as a school subject should be erected. He found that it is not
numbers we should start with, it is not counting, but other more primitive or fundamental
relations that underpinned, in the twentieth century modern conception of mathematics, the
notion of number, namely, the relations of order (less than, more than, equal to) and
equivalence. For him, the primitive notion is quantity (understood as a collection of objects
endowed with a total order relation). He wrote:
the concept of number arises within the context of measurement of a continuous quantity
so that a multiple relationship is established between that quantity and a part of it that is
used as a unit of measure. According to this it is possible to consider counting as the
measurement of a set of discrete objects. (Davydov, 1982, p. 228)
Thus, in this view, the origin of arithmetic thinking is not to be found in cardinality.
Cardinality is here a derivative concept. Given the evanescence of a Bourbakist approach to
mathematics today, we can imagine that if Davydov were to engage in the same archeological
digging, he would come up with a different resultand, likely, with a different curriculum
proposal as well.
7
A critique of Davydov’s concept of the concept
By way of conclusion, let me summarize some of the ideas that I have discussed about
Davydovs concept of the concept and outline a brief critique. I hope that my critique may
spark some reflections on the theoretical premises, entailments, and commitments embedded
in the notions of the mathematical concept that we, as mathematics educators, use implicitly or
explicitly in our research.
I mentioned that Davydov drew on the dialectical distinction between the two chief
categories of dialectical materialism: essence and appearance, and he assumed a dialectical
Hegelian-Marxist ontology that links these two categories (as opposed to Kants ontology that
strives to keep them apart). From there he articulated a dialectical concept of the concept: a
concept is a form of mental activity derived from human activity, a reproductive rule that
works ontogenetically speaking in a normative way. From an epistemological viewpoint, to
know an object is to reproduce it mentally in its theoretical movement.
Davydov adopted a view of the concept that is grounded on the model of scientific concepts.
For him, scientific concepts are the basis
of theoretical thought
(Davydov, 1990, p. 116), and as
we saw in Section 2, it was precisely the child
s acquisition of theoretical thought that he strived to
promote through his curricular enterprise. One of the main features of Davydov
s epistemological
stance is the belief that the essence of objects is graspable through the revolutionary concept of
modern science, namely law (see Section 3.2. above). Davydov says: theoretical thought is an
idealization of the basic aspect of practical activity involving objects, and of the reproduction in
that activity of the universal forms of things, their measures, and their laws
(1990, p. 116).
We cannot fail to see that Davydovs concept of the concept is imbued with a general
outlook of the world that favors a certain form of knowabilitythe one that predominated
throughout the twentieth century and considered scientific theoretical thought as the summit of
human cognition. Scientific theoretical thought was perceived as the model par excellence by
which to understand the world. Certainly, Davydov was not the only educational psychologist
to embrace such a view. We only need to think of Vygotskys famous distinction between
everyday and scientific concepts.
339
One of my reviewers argues that Vygotskys (and Davydovs) use of the adjective
scientific to designate a specific type of concept does not amount to any commitment with
a scientific outlook of the world. I would like very much to agree, perhaps more than anyone,
but I do not think that the use of the adjective
scientific
is merely circumstantial. I side here
with van der Veer (1991, 1996), who has shown that Vygotskys work was deeply influenced
by the modern idea of culture that was built around the model of science, a model that
transpires in Vygotsky
s marked interest in tools as means to master nature (and oneself). If we
remove the concept of tool from Vygotskys work, internalization and Vygotskys laws of
cultural development vanish into thin air. In Ape, Primitive Man, and Child, Vygotsky and
Luria argued that the first phase in the childs cultural development lies precisely in the use of
tools:
We have seen how the small child, for whom the world of external objects was initially
alien, gradually comes closer to it, and begins to master those objects and make
functional use of them as tools. This is the first phase in cultural development. (Luria
& Vygotsky, 1998, p. 117)
Vygotskys commitment to a scientific outlook of culture also transpires in his emphasis on
abstract thinking. So, when Luria (1931, 1934) carried out the Psychological Expeditions to
Central Asia (that he prepared with Vygotsky), what were the questions he posed to the
Uzbekistan peasants? Aristotelian syllogismsi.e., the embodiment of decontextualized
thinking.
Undoubtedly, there were very powerful historical reasons in the twentieth century that led
people to see the world through the lenses of science. First, there was the modern general
belief in technology and the promise it held for cultural and social progress (van der Veer,
1996, p. 258). Then, there were the two world wars; then the Cold War (i.e., the time in which
Davydov developed his work). The military successes of these wars were absolutely depen-
dent on scientific and technological development. The famous founding document of
Khrushchev
s reform,
Law on Strengthening the Links Between School and Life, and Further
Development of the System of Public Education in the USSR
conveyed in an explicit manner
the idea of scientific knowability as the true one: The Soviet school educates the younger
generation in the spirit of the most progressive ideas, the ideas of communism, and forms in
young people a materialistic worldviewthe basis of truly scientific knowledge of the world
(Government of the USSR, 1958; cited in Boyko, 2019, pp. 8182; my emphasis).
Within this scientific outlook, law, measure, and calculation became the key concepts to
understand the world. Commenting on this epistemological scientific outlook specific to the
modern period of the Western world, Heidegger (2002, p. 48) says, Beings became [con-
ceived of as] transparent objects capable of being mastered by calculation.Heidegger gives
the example of a stone. The stone presses downwards and manifests its heaviness (p. 24).
But can heaviness be reduced to its numerical value?
If we try to grasp the stone
s heaviness . . . by placing it on a pair of scales, then we bring
its heaviness into the calculable form of weight. This perhaps very precise determination
of the stone is a number. (Heidegger, 2002, p. 25)
Now, can we say that we have grasped the stone in this way? Heideggers answer is no. Can
we say at least that we have grasped the stones heaviness? Again, Heideggers answer is no:
the heaviness of the weight has escaped us
(Heidegger, 2002, p. 25). The stone
shows itself
only when it remains undisclosed and unexplained (p. 25). We could say the same of the
340
circle and its roundness: the process of its construction does not exhaust the essence of the
object (notwithstanding Spinoza and the Spinozist dialecticians).
Davydovs epistemology is articulated around this modern view where truth is of the order
of the logical and the scientifically conceptual. Certainly, the focus on this order of reality is
the strength of scientific thought. But it is also its weakness. The reason is that scientific
thought and its scientific laws necessarily marginalize the centrality of the singular, the
concrete, the sensible, and the complex ever-changing feature of cultural contexts. In doing
so, scientific thought marginalizes a part of the whole complex conditions of the objects
cultural-historical elaboration (e.g., aesthetical, ethical, political, and economic conditions).
But I want to go a bit further. So far, I have been concerned with, and critical of, the totalizing
stance with which scientific thought has been endowed in the understanding of reality. My
argument has been epistemological. Now I want to articulate an ontological argument. What
Heidegger is saying in the citations above is that there is a substrate in any object that is
nonconceptual. In dialectical terms, the nonconceptual of an object is precisely the objects
own negation
the non-identical-with-itself
that which, in the object
s historical movement, is
what the object is not. It is the unsettling and inexhaustible realm of the object that resists
consciousness. As a result, there is always a partial inadequacy of the concept and the real.
Knowledge does not wholly possess any of its objects
(Adorno, 2008, p. 187). In other words,
what individuals produce through practical sensible activitythrough praxisis both concep-
tual and nonconceptual, the latter being
the sheer heterogeneity of thought
(Huhn, 2004, p. 17).
In the creative historical movement of effective reality objects emerge. In their emergence,
each one of them brings to the fore a conceptual dimension, but also a nonconceptual one.
Now, it is in the nature of the nonconceptual to resist translation into the symbolicscientific
laws, painting, poetry, music, linguistic expression, etc. It resists encapsulation:
no matter how hard we try for linguistic expression of such a history congealed in things
[the movement of the real
LR], the words we use will remain concepts. Their precision
substitutes for the thing itself, without quite bringing its selfhood to mind; there is a gap
between words and the thing they conjure. Hence, the residue of arbitrariness and
relativity in the choice of words as well as in the presentation as a whole. (Adorno,
1973, pp. 5253)
Thus, The cognitive utopia would be to use concepts to unseal the nonconceptual with
concepts (Adorno, 1973, p. 10). It is only through the reflexive and critical praxis that
Marx (1998) talks about in the third thesis on Feuerbach (see analysis in Macherey, 2008)
that humans have the possibility to change their circumstances and their ideas. Thus, only
through such praxis, by going to the heart of contradictions, a dim light may be shed on the
nonconceptual. In the course of this movement, human consciousness and the object have been
transformed, but a new nonconceptual has emerged. It is impossible to get rid of the
nonconceptual. It is what propels consciousness forward again and again. This is why the
nonconceptual is the vitality of life. To cite Heidegger again, it is what remains undisclosed
and unexplained
(2002, p. 25). In the case of numbers, to come back to Davydov
s work, the
nonconceptual is that which resists being encapsulated by the concept of quantity and the
structure of total order. In the case of the Euclidean circle, the nonconceptual is that which is
more than the traces left by a radius in motion. Were there a total coincidence between concept
and object, we would find ourselves in a closed universe, a bound reality. Dialecticsi.e., the
movement of life,
the consistent sense of nonidentity
(Adorno, 1973, p. 5)
would collapse:
life would become movement without movement in a tautological silent identity.
341
Like Davydov, I do think that An individual persons thought is the functioning of
historically developed forms of societys activity which have been conferred on him(sic)
(Davydov, 1990, p. 108; emphasis in the original). I concur with him that labor
what I call in
my work joint-labor (Radford, 2019)—“is the basis of all human cognition,and that it is
Only within historically developing modes of . . . activity [that] all forms of thought [are]
formed(Davydov, 1990, p. 108). Yet, I prefer not to conceive of a concept as a mental rule,
but as something more poetic, something that brings together the cultural rationality and
worldview of the contexts where the object has emerged and evolved with all its historical and
political tensions. In this view a concept would be what we enact with others in joint activity
a cultural-historical enactive experience that is not merely conceptual and theoretical, but also
esthetic, ethical, political, and emotional; something that questions us.
Acknowledgments I would like to deeply thank Anna Sfard and two anonymous reviewers of the journal for
their precious comments.
Funding information This article is a result of a research program funded by the Social Sciences and
Humanities Research Council of Canada/Le conseil de recherches en sciences humaines du Canada (SSHRC/
CRSH)
References
Abramov, A. (2010). Toward a history of mathematics education reform in Soviet schools (1960s1980s). In A.
Karp & B. Vogeli (Eds.), Russian mathematics education. History and world significance (pp. 87140).
Singapore: World Scientific Publishing.
Adorno, T. (2008). Lectures on negative dialectics. Cambridge: Polity.
Adorno, T. W. (1973). Negative dialectics. New York: The Seabury Press.
Althusser, L. (1965). Pour Marx [for Marx] Paris: Maspero.
Andler, C. (1931). Le fondement du savoir dans la Phénomenologie de lesprit de Hegel [the foundation of
knowledge in Hegels phenomenology of Spirit]. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, 38(3), 317340.
Arendt, H. (1958). The modern concept of history. The Review of Politics, 20(4), 570590.
Aron, R. (1981). Introduction à la philosophie de lhistoire. [introduction to the philosophy of history]. Paris:
Gallimard.
Boyko, M. (2019). Soviet mathematics curriculum reforms (19581985): Redefining the purpose of mathematics
education. Toronto, Canada: Ph. D. Thesis. University of Toronto.
Davydov, V. (1967). The problem of generalization in the works of L. S. Vygotsky. Soviet Psychology, 5(3), 42
52.
Davydov, V. (1975a). Logical and psychological problems of elementary mathematics as an academic subject. In
L. Steffe (Ed.), Children's capacity for learning mathematics. Soviet studies in the psychology of learning
and teaching mathematics, vol. 7 (pp. 55107). School Mathematics Study Group: Stanford, CA (Original
work published 1966).
Davydov, V. (1975b). The psychological characteristics of the prenumerical period of mathematical instruc-
tion. In L. Steffe (Ed.), Childrens capacity for learning mathematics. Soviet studies in the psychology of
learning and teaching mathematics, Vol. 7 (pp. 109205). School Mathematics Study Group: Stanford, CA.
Davydov, V. (1982). Psychological characteristics of the formation of elementary mathematical operations in
children. In T. P. Carpenter, J. M. Moser, & T. A. Romberg (Eds.), Addition and subtraction: cognitive
perspective (pp. 224238). Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Davydov, V. (1990). Types of generalization in instruction: Logical and psychological problems in the
structuring of school curricula. Soviet studies in mathematics education (vol. 2). Reston, Virginia: NCTM.
Davydov, V. (1999). What is real learning activity? In J. Lompscher & M. Hedegaard (Eds.), Learning activity
and development (pp. 123138). Aarhus: Aarhus University Press.
Davydov, V. (2008). Problems of developmental instruction: A theoretical and experimental psychological
study. (P. Moxhay, Trans. New York: Nova Science Publishers.
de Freitas, E., Sinclair, N., & Coles, A. (2017). What is a mathematical concept? New York: Cambridge
University Press.
342
Descombes, V. (1996). Les institutions du sens [the institutions of meaning]. Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit.
Dupré, L. (1983). Marxs social critique of culture. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Hegel, G. (1977). Hegels phenomenology of spirit (A. V. Miller, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press (First
edition, 1807).
Hegel, G. (1991). The encyclopaedia logic. Part I of the encyclopaedia of philosophical sciences (T, F. Geraets,
W. A. Suchting, & H. S. Harris, trans.). Indianapolis / Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc..
Heidegger, M. (2002). Off the beaten track (J. Young & K. Haynes, trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Henry, M. (1976). Marx. Paris: Gallimard.
Huhn, T. (2004). The Cambridge companion to Adorno. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Ilyenkov, E. V. (1977). Dialectical logic. Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Ivashova, O. (2011). The history and the present state of elementary mathematical education in Russia. In A.
Karp & B. Vogeli (Eds.), Russian mathematics education. Programs and practices (pp. 3780). Singapore:
World Scientific Publishing.
Kant, I. (2003). Critique of pure reason (N. K. Smith, Trans.). New York: St. Martins Press.
Kopnin, P. (1966). Lógica dialectica [Dialectical logic]. Mexico: Editorial Grijalbo.
Libâneo, J., & Freitas, R. (2013). Vasily Vasilyevich Davidov: A Escola e a formacão do pensamento teórico-
científico [Vasily Vasilyevich Davidov: The school and the formation of theoretical-scientific thinking]. In
A. Maturano Longarezi & R. Valdés Puentes (Eds.), Ensino Desenvolvimental. Vida, pensamento e obra dos
principais representantes russos (pp. 315350). Uberlândia, Minas Gerais: Editora da Universidade Federal
de Uberlândia.
Luria, A. R. (1931). Psychological expedition to Central Asia. Science, 74, 383384.
Luria, A. R. (1934). The second psychological expedition to Central Asia. Journal of Genetic Psychology, 41,
255259.
Luria, A. R., & Vygotsky, L. S. (1998). Ape, primitive man, and child: Essays in the history of behavior. Boca
Raton, Fl: CRC Press LLC.
Macherey, P. (2008). Marx 1845. Les thèses sur Feuerbach. [Marx 1845. The theses on Feuerbach]. Paris:
Éditions Amsterdam.
Marx, K. (1993). Grundrisse: Foundations of the critique of political economy. London, England: Penguin
Books.
Marx, K. (1998). The German ideology, including theses on Feuerbach and introduction to the critique of
political economy. New York: Prometheus Books.
Piaget, J. (1964). The childs conception of number. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd..
Radford, L. (2019). On the epistemology of the theory of objectification. In U. T. Jankvist, M. V. D. Heuvel-
Panhuizen, & M. Veldhuis (Eds.), Proceedings of the Eleventh Congress of the European Society for
Research in Mathematics Education (CERME11, February 610, 2019) (pp. 30623069). Utrecht, the
Netherlands: Freudenthal Group & Freudenthal Institute, Utrecht University and ERME.
Rubtsov, V. V. (2015). V. V. Davydov The founder of a significant scientific school and director of the
psychological institute. Psychological Science and Education, 20(3), 182196.
Schmittau, J., & Morris, A. (2004). The development of algebra in the elementary mathematics curriculum of V.
V. Davydov. The Mathematics Educator, 8(1), 6087.
Spinoza, B. (1989). Ethics including the improvement of the understanding. (R. Elwes, Trans.). Buffalo:
Prometheus (Original work published 1667).
Spirkin, A. (1990). Fundamentals of philosophy. Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Swanson, D., & Williams, J. (2014). Making abstract mathematics concrete in and out of school. Educational
Studies in Mathematics, 86, 193209.
van der Veer, R. (1991). The anthropological underpinning of Vygotskys thinking. Studies in Soviet Thought,
42, 7391.
van der Veer, R. (1996). The concept of culture in Vygotskys thinking. Culture and Psychology, 2, 247263.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society. Cambridge, Ma: Harvard University Press.
Publishers note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and
institutional affiliations.
... From this perspective, the development of theoretical thinking requires a specially-organised practical activity -a learning activity in which students can reconstruct mathematical concepts, norms and values and thus learn to master culturally and historically developed theoretical ways of knowing. In mathematics, theoretical thinking is often exemplified by algebraic thinking (Krutetskii, 1976;Radford, 2021). Central to learning activity is the idea of ascending from the abstract to the concrete (Davydov, 2008). ...
... Thus, we hope that our analysis can provide some indication that it is possible to illuminate algebraic ideas through the collective and reflective use of learning models. This may be regarded as a way to allow for complex relational thinking (Davydov, 2008) to take a materialised form that others are able to reflect upon (Radford, 2018(Radford, , 2021; see also H. Eriksson & I. Eriksson, 2020;Eriksson et al., 2019). ...
Article
Full-text available
The overarching aim of this article is to exemplify and analyse how some algebraic aspects of equations can be theoretically explored and reflected upon by young students in collaboration with their teacher. The article is based upon an empirical example from a case study in a grade 1 in a primary school. The chosen lesson is framed by the El’konin-Davydov curriculum (ED Curriculum) and learning activity theory in which the concept of a learning model is crucial. Of the 23 participating students, 12 were girls and 11 boys, approximately seven to eight years old. The analysis of data focuses on the use of learning models and reflective elaboration and discussions exploring algebraic structures of whole and parts. The findings indicate that it is possible to promote the youngest students’ algebraic understanding of equations through the collective and reflective use of learning models, and we conclude that the students had opportunity to develop algebraic thinking about equations as a result of their participation in the learning activity.
... Esta es la idea que subyace a la noción de concepto que se sugiere aquí: un concepto es algo que nos permite involucrarnos de determinadas maneras en el mundo, algo que, como el lenguaje, en lugar de poseerlo, llegamos a disfrutar. Y al disfrutarlo, al abordar nuevas situaciones, cambiamos, nos transformamos (para una discusión más elaborada del concepto de concepto, véase Radford, 2020c). ...
... There is a normative dimension in coming to know about sequences. Knowing about sequences (and about many other things) in a mathematical and scientific way is based on the idea of calculability-one of the chief aspects of instrumental rationality of Western thought (Weber, 1992) and contemporary mathematical thinking (Radford, 2021b). In Lines 19-29 we see how the teacher invites Otis to be more explicit about what has to be added to the terms. ...
Article
Full-text available
In this paper, we turn to the notion of networking theories with the aim of contrasting two theoretical mathematics education perspectives inspired by Vygotsky’s work, namely, the Theory of Objectification and the Documentational Approach to Didactics. We are interested in comparing/contrasting these theories in accordance with the following three main questions: (a) the role that the theories ascribe to language and resources; (b) the conceptions that the theories bring forward concerning the teacher, and (c) the understandings they offer of the mathematics classroom. In the first part of the paper, some basic concepts of each perspective are presented. The second part includes some episodes from a lesson on the teaching and learning of algebra in a Grade 1 class (6–7-year-old students). The episodes serve as background to carry out, in the third part of the paper, a dialogue between proponents of the theoretical perspectives around the identified main questions. The dialogue shows some theoretical complementarities and differences and reveals, in particular, different conceptions of the teacher and the limits and possibilities that language affords in teaching–learning mathematics.
... Because abilities to comprehend and produce abstractions are foundational to computational thinking, it is in generalization that the concrete becomes abstract and teaching and learning can begin to yield computational thought processes. Radford (2021a) states, "generalization allows one to recognize the inner structure of scientific concepts and the system of their constitutive connections" (p. 329). ...
Article
Full-text available
This conceptual paper examines the aspects of human development that are foundational to higher mental functions and how particular features of cognition essential for relational and other types of complex thought are activated and developmentally driven through experiential exposure, specifically with others, to intentionally designed cultural tools of teaching and learning. After taking a closer look at relational thinking, which is a foundation for more complex types of thought such as computational thinking, and a developmentally appropriate pedagogical method for fostering these aspects of cognitive development, we focus on the Elkonin-Davydov early "prenumerical" phase, presenting this curricular approach as a cultural tool which can foster cognitive development. Based on this, we further conclude that the (pedagogical) tools, to which children are exposed within an interactional pedagogy, can affect and shape children's cognitive development. Further, we perceive this work has shown promise as an instructional process for fostering abstract comprehension and relational reasoning in children, and thus, we recommend implementing the Elkonin-Davydov curricular approach in early childhood daily practice.
... the development of ways of thinking within activities for which letter-symbolic algebra can be used as a tool but which are not exclusive to algebra and which could be engaged in without using any lettersymbolic algebra at all, such as, analysing relationships between quantities, noticing structure, studying change, generalizing, problem solving, modeling, justifying, proving, and predicting. (Kieran, 2004, p. 149) From a socio-cultural perspective, with the legacy of Vygotsky (1978), the cultural historical tradition where theoretical thinking is crucial for development of higher order thinking, algebraic thinking needs to be understood in relation to the youngest students as well (Cai & Knuth, 2011;Kieran, 2004;Radford, 2021). Today, there is a growing interest in the El'konin-Davydov curriculum (ED curriculum) in mathematics (e.g. ...
Article
Full-text available
The aim of this article is to exemplify and discuss what teachers using learning activity need to consider when planning and supporting students’ collective theoretical work on algebraic expressions. Data are from two iteratively developed research lessons in two grade 7 classes. The analysis focuses on students’ tool-mediated actions, the mathematical content processed, how the content is dealt with, and on identifying the crucial aspects that enable collective theoretical work. The result provides examples of how the content of the task, its design, and its tools, as well as the teacher’s and students’ tool-mediated actions are crucial factors in the promotion of collective theoretical work.
... Por ejemplo, en su propuesta curricular, Vasily V. Davydov elaboró una respuesta muy diferente a la nuestra. En el contexto de un proyecto más amplio de restructuración del programa de estudios de la Unión Soviética, inspirada en la visión de la matemática de su tiempo, la matemática moderna, Davydov buscó organizar la enseñanza alrededor de los "conceptos de 'relación y estructura '" (1975a, p. 101), orientándola al desarrollo de lo que en ese tiempo se consideró la cúspide de la cognición humana: el pensamiento teórico (Radford, 2021a). Siguió los consejos del matemático bourbakista Jean Dieudonné, que decía que "hay que mostrar abiertamente al niño la esencia abstracta del álgebra y desarrollar su capacidad de abstracción y poder teórico" (citado en Davydov, 1975a, p. 109); siguió también los pasos de A. N. ...
Article
Full-text available
Introdução H Á ALGUM TEMPO tem sido feitos esforços para introdu-zir alguns elementos de álgebra no ensino fundamental. Enquanto anteriormente aprender aritmética era apre-sentada como um pré-requisito para aprender álgebra, esta posi-ção curricular tem sido questionada pelo movimento de "Early Algebra" 1. Ao mesmo tempo, surgiram novas questões. Por exem-plo, se a aprendizagem da aritmética não é um pré-requisito para aprender álgebra, por onde começamos? Qual é a relação entre pensamento aritmético e pensamento algébrico? Na primeira parte do capítulo, discuto brevemente a questão do pensamento algébrico e esboço alguns dos resultados que al-cançamos em nossa pesquisa sobre a generalização das sequências. A segunda parte gira em torno do ensino-aprendizagem das equa-ções. Os episódios que discuto nesta segunda parte nos permitem mostrar o caminho que temos seguido no ensino-aprendizagem das equações nos anos iniciais. Os episódios ilustram, ao mesmo tempo, o que entendemos na teoria da objetivação por aprendiza-gem como um encontro coletivo com a matemática. 1 Nota da tradutora: Segundo Kieran (2016, p.1), "Early Algebra" refere-se, no contexto internacional, ao movimento de pesquisa que busca compreender "tanto a natureza do pensamento algébrico como as formas que este pensa-mento pode ser desenvolvido" em crianças entre 6 e 12 anos. Em espanhol, o termo equivalente é "algebra temprana". Na tradução, optamos por man-ter "álgebra inicial" compreendendo que se refere, no contexto nacional, ao recorte dos anos iniciais do ensino fundamental. Radford, L. (2021). O ensino-aprendizagem da álgebra na teoria da objetivação. In V. Moretti & L. Radford (Eds.), Pensamento algébrico nos anos iniciais: Diálogos e complementaridades entre a teoria da objetivação e a teoria histórico-cultural (pp. 171-195). Livraria da Física.
Conference Paper
Full-text available
The growing diverse nature of our STEM spaces has informed education experts to recommend teachers use social-design-based experiments (SDBE) to design teaching-learning curriculum that frames these diversities as a resource. This call for SDBEs comes from identified challenges in existing approaches like funds of knowledge and identity. However, there is a need for a conceptual lens that educators will use to actualize this essential call in Mathematics Education. Given this, I use this proposal to explore existing approaches and their challenges to addressing diversity as a resource. I continue to develop a conceptual lens for teachers to follow in their operationalization of SDBE to design a teaching-learning curriculum that centers diversity as a resource. This conceptual lens comprises a five-phase participatory perspective and relationship to curriculum planning, designing, and enactment where teachers and students co-participate.
Article
This chapter presents an approach to the study of learning which analyzes small groups – such as a dyad, a group, a classroom – or large groups – for example, a community or a social movement. This approach is based on a situativity or sociocultural theory of cognition and learning, where learning is “situated” within complex social and material contexts known as activity systems. Sociocultural theories are related to cultural-historical activity theory, situated learning theory, distributed cognition theory, and cultural psychology. These theories suggest that a full account of learning must extend beyond individualist psychology to analyze and explain social practices, technological artifacts, interactional patterns, and the different roles occupied by the participants.
Article
The interdisciplinary field of the learning sciences encompasses educational psychology, cognitive science, computer science, and anthropology, among other disciplines. The Cambridge Handbook of the Learning Sciences, first published in 2006, is the definitive introduction to this innovative approach to teaching, learning, and educational technology. In this significantly revised third edition, leading scholars incorporate the latest research to provide seminal overviews of the field. This research is essential in developing effective innovations that enhance student learning - including how to write textbooks, design educational software, prepare effective teachers, and organize classrooms. The chapters illustrate the importance of creating productive learning environments both inside and outside school, including after school clubs, libraries, and museums. The Handbook has proven to be an essential resource for graduate students, researchers, consultants, software designers, and policy makers on a global scale.
Article
Full-text available
Resumen La investigación sobre formas de pensamiento algebraico no evade la discusión de las formas de pensamiento aritmético. Resultados de investigación muestran que la ausencia de indicios espaciales en el estudio de secuencias numéricas hace que los estudiantes limiten el proceso de generalización al trabajo sobre relaciones entre números. En este artículo, a partir de datos provenientes de una investigación doctoral y de un programa de extensión con profesores de matemáticas, se analiza la actividad semiótica de una estudiante y de una profesora de primaria, respectivamente. El análisis sugiere la presencia de una zona conceptual en la que formas sofisticadas de generalización aritmética estarían muy cerca de proto-formas de pensamiento algebraico, y, además, abre pistas para profundizar la reflexión epistemológica en aras de lograr una caracterización más inteligible de esta zona conceptual en el aprendizaje del álgebra. Palabras clave: Analiticidad. Generalización aritmética. Generalización algebraica. Pensamiento algebraico temprano. Proto-analiticidad. Resumo/Abstract The investigation of forms of algebraic thinking does not evade the discussion on forms of arithmetical thinking. Previous studies show that the absence of spatial clues in the students' investigation of numerical sequences leads to the generalization of relationships between numbers, which implicitly facilitates the emergence of trial-error strategies that stand as an obstacle to the deductive thinking on which analyticity rests. Based on data from PhD research and an extension program with mathematics teachers, the semiotic activity of a student and a
Article
Full-text available
In this paper I discuss some concepts that are part of the epistemology dimension of the Theory of Objectification-a Vygotskian theory of teaching and learning whose philosophical background comes from dialectical materialism. The epistemological concepts are presented in the first part of the paper. In the second part, they are illustrated through a classroom example.
Book
Full-text available
The great German philosopher and aesthetic theorist Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno (1903-1969) was one of the main philosophers of the first generation of the Frankfurt School of critical theory. As an accomplished musician, Adorno originally focused on the theory of culture and art. He later turned to the problem of the self-defeating dialectic of modern reason and freedom. A distinguished roster of Adorno specialists explores the full range of his contributions to philosophy, history, music theory, aesthetics and sociology in this collection of essays. © Cambridge University Press 2004 and Cambridge University Press, 2006.
Book
Responding to widespread interest within cultural studies and social inquiry, this book addresses the question 'what is a mathematical concept?' using a variety of vanguard theories in the humanities and posthumanities. Tapping historical, philosophical, sociological and psychological perspectives, each chapter explores the question of how mathematics comes to matter. Of interest to scholars across the usual disciplinary divides, this book tracks mathematics as a cultural activity, drawing connections with empirical practice. Unlike other books in this area, it is highly interdisciplinary, devoted to exploring the ontology of mathematics as it plays out in different contexts. This book will appeal to scholars who are interested in particular mathematical habits - creative diagramming, structural mappings, material agency, interdisciplinary coverings - that shed light on both mathematics and other disciplines. Chapters are also relevant to social sciences and humanities scholars, as each offers philosophical insight into mathematics and how we might live mathematically. Offers a range of new perspectives on what a mathematical concept is The book takes an interdisciplinary approach, with chapters authored by mathematicians, philosophers and educators Chapter authors are leaders in their respective fields.
Chapter
Dialectical logic is the science of the most general laws of the development of nature, society and human thought. These laws are reflected in the form of special concepts — logical categories. Therefore, dialectical logic can also be defined as the science about the dialectical categories. As a system of dialectical categories, it investigates their reciprocal connections, sequence and the transitions of one category into the other.