ChapterPDF Available

Stem Cells: Ethical and Religious Issues

Authors:
BIOETHICS
IN THE 21st CENTURY
Edited by Abraham Rudnick
Bioethics in the 21st Century
Edited by Abraham Rudnick
Published by InTech
Janeza Trdine 9, 51000 Rijeka, Croatia
Copyright © 2011 InTech
All chapters are Open Access distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0
license, which allows users to download, copy and build upon published articles even for
commercial purposes, as long as the author and publisher are properly credited, which
ensures maximum dissemination and a wider impact of our publications. After this work
has been published by InTech, authors have the right to republish it, in whole or part, in
any publication of which they are the author, and to make other personal use of the
work. Any republication, referencing or personal use of the work must explicitly identify
the original source.
As for readers, this license allows users to download, copy and build upon published
chapters even for commercial purposes, as long as the author and publisher are properly
credited, which ensures maximum dissemination and a wider impact of our publications.
Notice
Statements and opinions expressed in the chapters are these of the individual contributors
and not necessarily those of the editors or publisher. No responsibility is accepted for the
accuracy of information contained in the published chapters. The publisher assumes no
responsibility for any damage or injury to persons or property arising out of the use of any
materials, instructions, methods or ideas contained in the book.
Publishing Process Manager Sandra Bakic
Technical Editor Teodora Smiljanic
Cover Designer InTech Design Team
Image Copyright Kinetic Imagery, 2011. Used under license from Shutterstock.com
First published November, 2011
Printed in Croatia
A free online edition of this book is available at www.intechopen.com
Additional hard copies can be obtained from orders@intechweb.org
Bioethics in the 21st Century, Edited by Abraham Rudnick
p. cm.
ISBN 978-953-307-270-8
free online editions of InTech
Books and Journals can be found at
www.intechopen.com
Contents
Chapter 1 Introduction to Bioethics in the 21st Century 1
Abraham Rudnick and Kyoko Wada
Chapter 2 End of Life Treatment Decision Making 7
Juan Pablo Beca and Carmen Astete
Chapter 3 Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions 27
Barbara J. Russell
Chapter 4 Resource Allocation in Health Care 63
Giovanni Putoto and Renzo Pegoraro
Chapter 5 Ethics and Medically Assisted Procreation:
Reconsidering the Procreative Relationship 79
Laurent Ravez
Chapter 6 Stem Cells: Ethical and Religious Issues 87
Farzaneh Zahedi-Anaraki and Bagher Larijani
Chapter 7 The “Cultural Differences” Argument and Its Misconceptions:
The Return of Medical Truth-Telling in China 103
Jing-Bao Nie
Chapter 8 Nanotechnology and Ethics:
Assessing the Unforeseeable 121
Monique Pyrrho
Chapter 9 Speculative Ethics:
Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac? 139
Gareth Jones, Maja Whitaker and Michael King
1
Introduction to Bioethics in the 21st Century
Abraham Rudnick* and Kyoko Wada
Departments of Psychiatry and Philosophy and Faculty of Health Sciences,
The University of Western Ontario
Canada
1. Introduction
Health care is developing rapidly. So are its correlates, such as health care technology,
research, education, administration, communication, and more. Such change requires ethical
deliberation, as change that is not ethically guided poses unnecessary risks. This may be
particularly true in relation to health care, which impacts some of the most central domains
of human life. Bioethics addresses issues of health care ethics. It consists of approaches that
attempt to resolve moral conflicts, viewed as conflicts among moral values that may each be
acceptable in some circumstances but that require prioritizing when combined with other
moral values in particular circumstances. Such approaches include the application of
theories such as consequentialism, which refers to outcomes (such as happiness);
deontology, which refers to duties or intentions (such as the obligation not to lie); virtue
ethics, which refers to character features (such as honesty); principlism, which refers to the
four principles of upholding autonomy (self-determination), beneficence (best interests),
non-maleficence (least harm), and justice (as fairness, for example); and more (Beauchamp &
Childress, 2009; Rudnick, 2001; Rudnick, 2002).
Bioethics ranges across many areas and its scope is still broadening. Some of its emerging
areas address organizational bioethics, global bioethics, and much more. This book focuses
on a sample of emerging as well as more established areas of bioethics. The chapters were
selected according to various considerations, such as interest of authors. Yet in spite of not
being exhaustive, this book illustrates the range and impact of bioethics in the 21st century.
As part of that, some of the chapters go beyond fact and theory into some speculation (the
chapters with more speculative topics can be found near the end of this book). We think this
is necessary for bioethics to be constructive, recognizing that speculation must be checked
by common sense as well as by known fact and theory. Indeed this is how much of bioethics
proceeds (Rudnick 2007).
There are areas of bioethics that are not covered in this book, such as neuroethics,
enhancement ethics, ethics of genetics, and more. We cannot touch on most of them here.
Still, we would like to highlight neuroethics as a likely paradigm of an emerging area in
bioethics. Neuroethics can be defined in part as the ethics of neuroscience
(http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Neuroethics). More specifically, it can be viewed in part as
* arudnic2@uwo.ca
Bioethics in the 21st Century
2
the ethics of brain assessment and manipulation with advanced technology, such as
transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) and (electric) deep brain stimulation (DBS); these
technologies may induce important intended and unintended brain changes. Such brain
assessment and manipulation has implications for personal identity, self-determination,
social influence on health care, and more. Much if not all of this is not new, yet in
neuroethics it is perhaps more prominent than elsewhere and may require new approaches
and solutions. Such emerging bioethics may contribute to ethics more generally, be it by
generating new problems and/or by generating new solutions to old problems that
emerging and established health care practices and related technologies raise in variant
forms. We hope this book will be part of this contribution in the areas that it addresses and
beyond. The editor (first author of this introductory chapter), would like to point out that
due to the publishing process of the book, he cannot take full responsibility for the
substance and style of this book. Such open access publication is a fairly new part of
bioethics in the 21st century, and as such the book exemplifies an aspect of its subject matter.
2. Overview of chapters
In chapter 2, Beca and Astete discuss the issue of decision-making in relation to patients
who have no plausible prospect of recovery. They focus on examples where life support
may no longer be meaningful but rather may prolong the suffering of the patient and the
family members. As is illustrated in one of the four examples presented, some family
members may hold an unrealistic hope for recovery, no matter what the circumstances may
be. Also, it can be stressful for healthcare professionals to withdraw or limit any kind of life
prolonging procedures. The authors apply the principlist approach to grapple with the
difficulties involved in end-of-life decision-making (although distributive justice as related
to resource allocation can be viewed as part of principlism, it is not discussed in this
chapter). They argue that in terms of autonomy, the patient’s values must be respected;
however, the patient may not be fully capable of making his or her own decisions, and the
substitute decision maker (SDM) may not necessarily know the patient’s values.
Considering a variety of difficulties involved in this decision-making process, the authors
argue for shared decision-making by several agents, such as healthcare professionals and
ethics representatives, in addition to the patient and his or her SDM. Shared decision-
making pursues a balance of benefits and burdens, which may secure the patient’s best
interests. Such an approach may appear to have an emphasis on beneficence more than on
autonomy. But, as is the bioethical standard now, the authors’ argumentation portrays
beneficence as what is good for the patient based on his or her values (when known). Hence,
autonomy trumps, unless neither the past nor the present values of the patient can be
known (in which case, autonomy may be irrelevant).
In chapter 3, Russell argues that ethical considerations involved in mental health and
addiction settings do not stand alone but co-exist with clinical, legal, organizational and
other considerations. Seven examples involving ethical complexities are presented in the
beginning to illustrate issues arising from the care of those with mental illnesses and/or
addictions; these issues are addressed later in the chapter. These examples are not as
dramatic as may be often displayed to the general public through media, but are rich with
issues encountered in daily healthcare practice, education and management. In these
examples, we encounter patients as well as a wide range of other agents, such as their family
members, a landlord, a judge, a clinical director of an organization, and others who are
Introduction to Bioethics in the 21st Century
3
related to the patient through their mental health and addiction problems or otherwise.
Following discussion of being humane, being a person, being a community member, and
being a care provider, all of which comprise ethical considerations, the author proceeds to
discuss why other factors matter ethically. Among these are science, technology and clinical
factors, law and regulations, organizational contexts, and systemic factors, such as stigma
and discrimination, the social determinants of health and the health care system.
In chapter 4, Putoto and Pegoraro discuss resource allocation, which is among the most
important and pressing issues in healthcare today, both in developed and in developing
countries. As resources are limited, we must make a difficult choice to achieve the goal of
efficient and effective healthcare. Rationing, defined by the authors as “the distribution of
resources between programmes and persons in competition”, needs to be done explicitly
and at various levels, i.e. from policy making to individual care. However, as the authors
argue, we are far from reaching a consensus in terms of who decides and what the guiding
strategies should be. Several approaches to rationing are possible. Experiences of a few
jurisdictions are classified into three models. The first model, which is employed in Oregon
(United States), explicitly identifies a list of treatments to be publicly funded. The second
model, which is employed in the Netherlands and Sweden, adopts some principles to
identify available treatments or priorities in the provision of healthcare. The third model,
which is employed in New Zealand and Great Britain, relies on specific guidelines
regarding treatments, and the rationing is done at the local and individual levels. However,
as the authors indicate, none of these models are without problems, and no matter what
model we use, there will always be ambiguities. More discussion on rationing is required
regarding resource allocation.
In chapter 5, Ravez analyzes ethical criticism of employing procreation technologies. He also
presents his proposal regarding the issues arising from these new technologies for couples
who want to have a bio-child. From his review of literature, particularly that written in
French, he classifies ethical criticism of medically assisted procreation (MAP) into three
types: medicalization of procreation, the dissociation of biological and social filiation, and
the controversial status of the embryo. Ravez recognizes that these criticisms are not without
counter arguments and may not necessarily be limited to MAP. Moreover, these criticisms
may dismiss the effectiveness of these new technologies which may enable a couple to
satisfy their legitimate desire to have a bio-child. He claims that we should not deny the
suffering of sterile couples and proposes a framework to address the ethical issues involved
in MAP. According to him, first, we must listen to couples who are suffering from sterility
and discern how their sterility may or may not relate to their suffering. Second, we must
respect the complexity of life. Having a child cannot be reduced to a simple biological
phenomenon but involves various other important elements, such as family relationships
and psychological aspects. Third, these new technologies should be understood as a means
to help the sterile couple have children (rather than preselect or enhance their children, for
example). The framework urges us to acknowledge the suffering of those with sterility;
concomitantly, it provides certain requirements to ethically regulate MAP.
In chapter 6, Zahedi-Anaraki and Larijani discuss ethical issues related to stem cell research
and its potential clinical applications. As stem cells have the capacity to differentiate into a
variety of cells which may be employed for therapeutic purposes, research has held much
hope and enthusiasm for their positive contribution to the treatment of currently incurable
illnesses. At the same time, such research, particularly that employing embryonic stem cells,
has been criticized as it involves ethical challenges, some of which are related to personhood
Bioethics in the 21st Century
4
and human dignity. The chapter begins with definitions and characteristics of several types
of stem cells. The ethical issues discussed in this chapter include human dignity in relation
to the instrumentalization and destruction of human embryos, safety concerns in clinical
applications of stem cell use, informed consent for conducting procedures involving stem
cells, slippery slope arguments regarding the creation and use of human embryos, resource
allocation and commercialization of stem cell therapies. In addition, the authors refer to
legislation and guidelines concerning stem cell research by national and international
regulatory bodies as well as positions expressed by religious authorities, such as in
Christianity, Judaism and Islam. The authors conclude by indicating the need for research
on alternatives to embryonic stem cells, such as induced pluripotent stem cells, for realistic
regulations in relation to stem cell research, for control of commercialism, and for more
engagement of the public.
In chapter 7, Nie argues against oversimplification and dichotomy regarding views of
cultural differences between China and Western countries. More specifically, he argues
against the popular view that Chinese medical practice traditionally endorses no or indirect
disclosure of personal health information to patients, unlike Western medical practice. He
argues that China had a tradition of direct disclosure to the patient, unlike some Western
traditions, and that the majority of Chinese people today wish to know the truth regarding
their medical condition. Nie suggests that this historical and sociological reality is ignored in
“the cultural differences argument”, which results in the widely accepted stereotype of
China as being very different from Western countries in this respect. According to Nie,
healthcare professionals in China are in fact making efforts to move toward honest and
direct disclosure of the patient’s condition. He argues that the shift of attitudes in favour of
full disclosure may not be a mere imitation of current Western practice but rather a return to
traditional Chinese medical practice. More generally, he rejects cultural stereotypes, and
endeavours to explore cross-cultural bioethics with more attention to the normative and
shared aspects of ethics and to the complexity and internal heterogeneity of each culture.
In chapter 8, Pyrrho illustrates ethical issues involved in nanotechnology, which may
include numerous technological possibilities that may impact on a wide range of industries.
What seems troublesome to begin with is the lack of consensus regarding the definition of
nanotechnology, other than that it deals with nanoscale particles. More importantly, it
concerns the chemical and physical properties originating from the size of these particles.
Without more conceptual clarity on nanotechnology, different players understand it
differently. Despite inevitable uncertainties, the authors believes that it is important to
analyze and discuss potential ethical issues involved in this promising technology before the
actual scientific advances take place. They discuss autogenous and heterogenous ethical
implications of nanotechnology. The former concerns the scientific consequences of
nanotechnology, whereas the latter concerns its bearing on cultural, social, economic,
environmental and political matters.
In chapter 9, King, Whitaker and Jones illustrate scientific advances that call for speculations
in relation to their potential technological applications. Such technology may involve serious
ethical issues. While some speculations may become real in the near future, others may be
highly unlikely, such as perfectly tailored prophylactic medication for an individual based
on his or her genetic data. Hence, the authors question whether it is worthwhile for
bioethicists to engage in speculative bioethics where the issues are based on mere
possibilities of consequences resulting from potential technologies. Speculative ethics may
be a provocative term. In this chapter, genomic medicine, nanotechnology, regenerative
Introduction to Bioethics in the 21st Century
5
medicine, and cryonics are discussed, with much space given to cryonics as an extreme
example involving speculation. Criticism toward ethicists’ engagement in speculative ethics
relates to epistemological problems and moral consequences of these problems, e.g. being
less attentive to current ethical concerns that should be addressed in the present. Still, some
critics support the positive role of speculative ethics in guiding the direction of science. The
authors oppose such a defense of speculative ethics, arguing that one cannot consider all
possibilities and that one cannot determine which possibilities are worth ethical
consideration. The authors conclude that bioethicists should be cautious about ethical
engagement with speculative matters, although it may not always be easy to discern
whether these are scientific facts or fiction.
3. Acknowledgements
Thanks are due to Ian Gallant and Luljeta Pallaveshi for their technical assistance in editing
this book.
4. References
Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. (2009). Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 6th ed. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. ISBN-10: 0195335708, USA.
Rudnick A. (2001). A meta-ethical critique of care ethics. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics
Vol. 22, No.6, (September, 2001), pp. 505-517, ISSN 1386-7415, eISSN 1573-0980.
Rudnick A. (2002). The ground of dialogical bioethics. Health Care Analysis. Vol.10, No. 4, pp.
391-402, ISSN 1065 3058, eISSN 1573-3394 .
Rudnick A. (2007). Processes and pitfalls of dialogical bioethics. Health Care Analysis,Vol.15,
No.2, (June, 2007), pp. 123-135, ISSN 1065 3058, eISSN 1573-3394.
2
End of Life Treatment Decision Making
Juan Pablo Beca and Carmen Astete
Centro de Bioética, Facultad de Medicina,
Clínica Alemana-Universidad del Desarrollo,
Santiago
Chile
1. Introduction
Every human being has a personalized life and generates meaning which is subjective and
depends on cultural facts, beliefs, faith and biographical experiences. End of life could mean
a long period of a human life, but end of life decisions are near death decisions. Death is the
loss of biological life and it can be verified. Nevertheless it can be seen as a mystery and is
open to different points of views. What is unquestionable is that our human life is finite and
therefore it will always come to an end. Death is not only inevitable but a part of each
individual life or the last chapter of each personal biography. To be conscious about one’s
own life’s finitude is a unique quality of the human person as a historic and temporal entity.
To comprehend its intrinsic dignity and to find deep meaning to human life, it is important
to internalize and accept life’s finitude and the certainty of death. When this is achieved, it
may be easier to die in peace. Callahan says that end of life and death should be more
acceptable for those who have accomplished their personal life projects and moral
obligations (Callahan, 1995). It is still socially inappropriate to talk about end of life or death.
This also holds for physicians and other health care professionals.
Death and dying are not the same. Dying is commonly not a instant but rather variable,
complex and frequently lengthy. End of life may take place at any age and may occur
because of a variety of physical conditions, chronic or acute illness, degenerative diseases or
accidents. Many times dying occurs with much pain and suffering, with a personal
emotional and spiritual crisis, anxiety and moral distress. This generates various questions
and problems for those who are leaving life and for their loved ones. No matter what their
personal beliefs might be, everyone faces the mystery of life and death with doubts or
questions that have no definitive answers. This is a perennial issue that is not expected to
change with 21st century technology, hence this chapter will not focus on technological
aspects of the ethics of end of life.
Most patients at the end of life receive health care, but it is commonly provided without
clear objectives and with insufficient knowledge of their wishes and hopes. Care givers are
usually very able in their technical skills but confused about what is the best for each
particular patient. We are all aware of the many changes in medicine in the 20th century,
from earlier when nothing very effective in treating illness could be done, to our days when
we are able to cure many diseases and to prolong life for days, months or even many years,
although the disease has not been cured. This progress has led medicine to focus on curing
Bioethics in the 21st Century
8
and to neglect its historical mission of caring for those who suffer and for those who are in
their dying process with the exception of palliative medicine. Many authors have analyzed
this divergence of the efforts for curing and for caring. One of the more clear-cut studies was
the Hastings Center project to re-establish the goals of medicine (Hanson & Callahan, 1999),
where two of the four are: ….cure and care of those with a malady, and the care of those who
cannot be cured … and ……the pursuit of a peaceful death …… A high proportion of patients at
the end of their lives receive treatments that do not benefit them in terms of healing, relief of
suffering or personal wishes achievement, and their distress and agony are extended. It is
not clear why it has been so hard to improve health care at the end of life.
Situations that patients, families and care givers have to deal with when they care for
patients who are at the end of life are numerous and variable. Relevant issues are the need
for controlled pain, anxiety and other symptoms; how to know the patient’s wishes, fears
and hopes; which is the best way to respect his or her values and advance directives if they
exist; how to respond to emotional and spiritual needs; how can family and other loved ones
be supported; and how can care givers be helped in relation to their own distress. Each one
of these and related issues require specific answers and difficult decisions have to be made.
There are no easy, precise or general answers. The aim of this chapter is to analyze the
complexity of end of life decision making and to suggest some ways to improve it, so that it
can benefit patients and their relatives. Four representative situations will be described, to
be kept in mind while reading this chapter. Then different types of decisions and related
challenges will be discussed, as well as by whom and how they should be made (euthanasia
and medically assisted suicide will not be considered in this discussion). Suggestions on
how to improve end of life decisions will be made. The underlying assumption here is that
the topic is in part an ethical matter as end of life decisions commonly involve conflicts of
values, such as prolonging life vs. reducing suffering.
2. Four representative cases
The following situations that are presented raise questions about the end of life decisions
that had to be made and the problems that health professionals, patients and family
members had to face. Readers should keep these situations in mind while reading through
the rest of this chapter.
2.1 Situation 1
A 68-year-old patient who suffered from gastric cancer diagnosed eight months earlier
presented multiple peritoneal and hepatic metastases, despite several rounds of chemo and
radiotherapy. He was an independent professional, married with two sons, two daughters
and eight grand children, all of whom were very close. He understood his disease and
accepted his near death based on his strong religious faith. After his last admission to
hospital, he decided to be cared for at home and his general condition quickly deteriorated.
He was nearly emaciated, despite being on partial parenteral feeding. Four years earlier, due
to cardiac arrhythmia that was refractory to medication, the patient had a cardiac
pacemaker implanted, regulated to go on if his own frequencies fell below 70 beats per
minute. Given the patient's terminal status, some in the caring team expressed their doubts
about the pacemaker’s effects during his dying process. The patient had mentioned his
intention to donate his pacemaker after death, but had not asked for its deactivation. The
cardiologists were not sure about the effect of the pacemaker in a possible prolongation of
End of Life Treatment Decision Making
9
the patient’s final time. Nevertheless, they opposed deactivation, which they considered as
ethically uncertain. The family was initially in favour of the deactivation, but ultimately
decided against it because of the specialists’ uncertainty. The condition of the patient
progressively deteriorated into a state of stupor and later into a coma. This moribund phase
lasted for ten days, with a cardiac frequency invariably fixed at 70 beats a minute, which is
explained by the action of the pacemaker. Although physicians and family members
decided based on what they felt was the best on clinical and ethical grounds, the patient had
an artificially prolonged agony and the family suffered deeply during this period.
2.2 Situation 2
A 46 year old previously healthy industrial manager had a severe car accident while driving
alone on a highway. After emergency measures were carried out at least one hour later by
the rescue ambulance personnel, he was transferred in extremely poor conditions,
unconscious and with visible multiple fractures to a small community hospital. He was
intubated and after initial hemodynamic stabilization he was transferred by helicopter to a
tertiary care hospital. At admission he was unconscious, with very low blood pressure,
severe metabolic acidosis, and rapidly developed multisystemic failure needing mechanical
ventilation. His fractures were immobilized and two days later he was connected to dialysis.
His neurological assessment demonstrated deep coma, some occasional seizures, and the
serial CAT scans showed extensive demyelization lesions and cerebellum and basal ganglia
lesions, all of them secondary to a prolonged ischemic encephalopathy. After five days with
no change, the neurologists made clear that the patient’s recovery would not be possible and
that in case of survival he would go into vegetative state or another similar condition.
The patient’s wife, his two adolescent sons and his mother were informed about the almost
impossible chance of recovery and about the prognosis in case of survival. The possible
courses of action, including withdrawal of treatments, were discussed with them and with
the neurologist in an ethics consultation meeting. There was neither a living will nor other
expressions of the patient’s preferences in case of being near death with risk of severe
neurological damage. His wife said that she was convinced that if he could choose he would
decide to stop all treatments because he would not want to live with such severe
neurological damage. The critical care medical staff, although very uncertain about
withdrawing treatments, agreed to her demand. After some hours, and giving his family
some time to be with him privately and for the administration of sacraments by a catholic
priest, mechanical ventilation was discontinued.
2.3 Situation 3
A 60 years old woman was a widow with only one daughter who was married with a two
year old son. She had severe disseminated lupus that started many years before, with
progressively worsening recurrences. She also had poorly controlled celiac disease and was
undernourished. She lived alone and had to sell her small clothing industry as she was not
able to run it anymore. Her physical condition had deteriorated because of generalized
muscle and joint pain, weakness and extended skin lesions. She became a very isolated
person, in spite of having good medical care, well controlled medication, psychological
support and the necessary domestic assistance. She had a good but not very close
relationship with her daughter, and she had not established a good bond with her grandson.
She was admitted to hospital with severe lupus relapse, with pneumonia and in initial renal
failure with some signs of encephalopathy. After her dehydration and metabolic state were
Bioethics in the 21st Century
10
stabilized and the infection had been controlled she developed progressive renal failure
that required dialysis. She was informed that this was a necessary procedure now, which
was possibly indefinite in time, and that dialysis could be done as an ambulatory service
three times a week. She apparently understood the information but did not agree and
refused dialysis. The attending physicians were disappointed, regarded her decision as a
result of mental confusion and asked her daughter to decide. The daughter made clear
that her mother had for a long time considered her quality of life as very poor and was
not willing to accept more treatments, although she had never written a living will nor
formally assigned a proxy. She also said that the only other family member that could
know the patient’s preferences was her brother, but accepted that it was she who had to
represent her mother’s wishes. She said that she believed that one should fight to be alive
but that life cannot be forced by others as an obligation, and that she thought that her
mother shared this idea. She consulted with her uncle and the case was submitted to an
ethics consultation. Finally she decided to support her mother’s refusal of dialysis or any
other new treatments, allowing the progression of disease. She said that although it was
extremely difficult and sad for her, she had to respect her mother’s wishes even if she
didn’t entirely agree with them.
2.4 Situation 4
This was a 2 ½ year old female infant on mechanical ventilation since her first day of life
because of a generalized hypotonia with no muscle reflexes, no swallowing capacity and no
spontaneous breathing movements. She could only move her eyelids. She was conscious
and could establish eye contact when she was awake. She was fed by a nasogastric tube and
several weaning trials had failed.
She was the first baby of a young couple of low socioeconomic and educational level, but
they had enough understanding about their daughter’s unrecoverable condition. They had
established a close attachment and visited her every day in the Children’s Hospital ICU.
First muscle biopsies revealed a generalized muscle fiber atrophy which is suggestive of a
mitochondrial myopathy. The ethics committee was consulted about treatment limitation
and suggested repeating the muscle biopsy in order to have a complete genetic diagnosis as
an essential requirement. The committee recommended that only then could a treatment
withdrawal be decided with both parents, to allow the baby’s death under proper sedation
and to provide support for her family. The parents declined consent for further invasive
studies or treatments, arguing that they only wanted to avoid all suffering for their baby,
that they were not prepared to stop assisted ventilation, and that they ultimately expected a
miracle.
3. End of life decisions
Advances in medicine, medical technology, diagnostic procedures, antibiotic therapies, life
support treatments and other interventions in critical care medicine in the last few decades
have produced many new possible decisions and problems that physicians have to face
when they are dealing with terminally ill patients. For each possible intervention or
treatment and for each problem patients go through, there are concrete decisions to be
made. This is not only a problem in critical care medicine or in the treatment of acute or
terminally ill patients, but also when care givers deal with chronic or degenerative diseases
at any age, or when elderly people come close to their final stage in life.
End of Life Treatment Decision Making
11
In order to consider clinical decisions when a patient appears to be entering the final stages
of his or her life, clarity is required in relation to diagnosis and prognosis. After these have
been clarified, it becomes necessary to determine if the patient has no real possibility to
recover and therefore is in his or her final stage. Only then should end of life decisions be
made, focused on what can be regarded as the best for the patient or, in other words, trying
to find out what would be the patient’s best interest. This is a difficult question to answer as
there are many possible ways or courses of action that can be regarded as good and
legitimate ways to benefit these patients (recognizing the primacy of patient choice when
known).
For each patient who is facing possible death, the amount of care decisions may be
numerous, from nursing care and diagnostic procedures to the more complex
management or procedures in intensive care. Although a great majority of end of life care
decisions involves limiting intensive care or treatments in order to avoid prolonging
suffering, we will first note other decisions that should take place before that. The first is
the need for clear information provision to the patient or surrogate about his or her
condition, diagnosis, prognosis, chances of survival and possible handicaps or extended
rehabilitation time needed if he or she survives. This is a problem in itself as it has to be a
truth telling process but it also has to be compassionate and appropriate to the patient’s
emotional and cognitive capacities that are sometimes diminished. In bioethical terms,
information provision should balance the patient’s right to know and comprehend his or
her situation with the physician’s duty not to harm him or her by increasing stress or
anxiety through inadequate or unnecessary information. Some patients may prefer not to
be informed, which should be respected as their right. Occasionally, if the patients are
emotionally fragile or partially incapacitated, family members should be asked before
informing him or her, at least in some cultures. In other words, this requires kind and
proficient communication. Family members or relatives may also have to receive
information, but not necessarily the same as the patient. Biographic facts that are private
should be confidential but sometimes some family members need to know more details or
exact information in order to make their own decisions. Often patients are incompetent
because of their prior condition, or as part of the acute state of their disease or treatments,
including due to sedation. Sometimes, incapacitated patients will not have appointed
somebody as a proxy with a durable power of attorney. Therefore information frequently
has to be given to their families as surrogates, as in situation 3, or in relation to pediatric
patients, as in situation 4. A complex decision is to establish who can best substitute the
patient for his or her decision making. This means establishing who would best know and
respect the patient’s values and wishes. For this decision it is necessary to be acquainted
with the family, with its dynamics and the roles of each of its members, which is
commonly unknown when there is no family physician who has known the patient and
the family for long.
Before describing specific decisions, it is important to note general decisions that patients
and families face. In a terminal or near death situation, should the patient be admitted to a
hospital, nursing home, another kind of institution, or stay at home with appropriate care.
These are crucial decisions that involve social features, resources and family care and all of
them should be based on patient wishes. It is far easier if he or she decides, or when they are
incapable if they have formally expressed their wishes through advance directives. In many
social groups and cultures, the usual situation is that patients’ wishes are unclear or
unknown and that their relatives have to express what they think the patients would have
Bioethics in the 21st Century
12
chosen. At this stage, physicians are not part of this decision, but they do have the
responsibility of treatment planning e.g. if the decision is to care for the patient at home.
The particular decisions to be made at the end of life of patients are mainly related to what is
known as “treatment limitations”. The first and clearest of these limitations is the patient’s
refusal of treatment, which is frequent in cases of cancer with metastasis, organ transplant or
even kidney failure, when these conditions are experienced as an end of life situation.
Patients’ rejection of treatment should be considered as right and therefore should be fully
respected, based on the principle of Autonomy, unless their capacity is unclear or impaired.
The rationale of limiting treatments is to avoid what is known as “treatment obstinacy”,
which is the approach of doing everything possible to prolong life and avoid death,
regardless of its burdens, suffering and costs (Real Academia de Medicina de Cataluña,
2005). Treatment limitation is based on futility and proportionality judgments, which
conclude that more interventions will only prolong the dying phase, extending agony and
increasing suffering. In different ways, this was the main problem in all four cases presented
above. It means not starting any new treatment or procedures, or withdrawing some of
them. This cannot be decided in bloc, as each treatment, whether more or less complex, has
its own purpose and therefore should also require a particular decision. In these highly
sensitive conditions, minor interventions such as an intravenous line, a feeding tube or a
biochemical test acquire special meanings for patients and family members. Often,
physicians are not aware of these meanings and of the great anxiety that they can produce.
It is also important to note that these kinds of decisions are not to be taken as one single and
definitive decision, because this is a continuous and evolving process where the patient’s
condition, symptoms and needs may change every day and even within hours. During the
course of this stage, both patients and their families require physicians’ and other
professionals’ support and guidance.
The decisions of treatment limitation usually begin with a Do-Not-Resuscitate order, which
means not to do what is routinely established as emergency protocols in cases where the
heart stops beating. Another limitation decision, if the patient is already in hospital, is to
decide not to admit him or her to intensive care units. Other decisions are to not perform
surgical procedures, either major surgeries or minor ones such as gastrostomy or
tracheotomy, and not to start vasoactive drugs, antibiotics or other treatments. In these
cases, a consistent decision should be to also not perform more laboratory or imaging tests.
Other decisions, such as not starting hemo-dialysis or assisted ventilation, are usually more
difficult to make, both for professional caregivers and for family members. All these
decisions have been described as withholding treatments, but they also can be decisions to
stop or to withdraw these or other life support treatments. For many of those involved in
end of life decision making, it is more complicated and stressful to decide to withdraw
rather than to withhold treatment. Even if the intention of both are in the patient’s best
interest, and we know that there is no significant moral difference between them,
withholding and withdrawing treatment decisions are experienced as different. Perhaps the
most difficult (withdrawing treatment) decision is to stop mechanical ventilation, because
death may occur shortly after it is performed, and inevitably many will feel it is the cause of
death. This was the hard problem faced in situations 2 and 4. Discontinuing assisted
ventilation is associated with many fears and myths, such as that it is a sort of euthanasia, or
that it is illegal or risky for physicians who could be taken to court for it. In a similar way the
deactivation of cardiac pacemakers is a complex and difficult decision as occurred in
situation 1. Another special situation that has been widely discussed after the Terri Schiavo
End of Life Treatment Decision Making
13
and Eluana Englaro cases is the withdrawal of artificial nutrition and hydration (A.S.P.E.N.,
2010). These procedures are perceived as a mandatory duty of basic humane care by some or
as an unnecessary technical intervention by others.
The decisions described above do not mean abandonment of the patient or that “there is
nothing to do”. Decisions of treatment limitation can be part of actions that favor the
patient’s wellbeing, in order to make possible a peaceful death. Therefore, end of life
decisions include the planning of efficient symptom and pain control plan with all the
necessary medication and sedation.
Other kinds of decisions are related to the patient’s spiritual needs, as severe illness and the
state of being near death cause a personal spiritual crisis that is frequently unrecognized.
Spirituality is understood as the compilation of hopes, fears, faith and values that guide
one’s plans and meaning of life and death. It involves the spiritual or existential suffering
that includes hopelessness, feeling like a burden to others, loss of sense of dignity and loss
of will to live. It includes but is not restricted to the patient’s religious needs (Chochinov &
Cann, 2005; Sulmasy, 2006). The patient’s spiritual needs have to be defined by him or
herself. But physicians and other health care professionals have the responsibility to make
sure that these needs are recognized and evaluated, and that patients are offered the
appropriate responses to them. To include spiritual and emotional support as a substantial
part of end of life medicine centered on the care of the patient and his or her family will
considerably facilitate the patient’s peaceful death.
When addressing the topic of end of life decision making, it is necessary to consider that
these decisions sometimes have to be made when it is not possible to know the patients’
values and wishes. This will always occur in neonates with untreatable conditions, but also
in children when their parents have to make decisions on their behalf, as in situation 4. In
incapacitated adults because of advanced Alzheimer or other neuropsychiatric diseases,
decisions will also have to be made by proxies, but patients’ previous values should be
respected. Some patients and their families need professional assistance in communication
in order that they can better understand their disease and prognosis, and then express their
doubts and preferences. This is what is referred to as a guided and assisted interpretive
patient physician relation model (Emanuel & Emanuel, 1992).
Decisions for end of life care are influenced by multiple factors related to patients, their
families and social environment, cultures, religion, available resources, health policies and
more. Decisions may change according to each patient’s age, capacity, emotional condition
and understanding of diagnosis and prognosis. Decisions may also change if it is a chronic
or acute disease and in cases of added complications to previous conditions, even more so if
they occur after prolonged admissions to hospitals. Also, decisions are dependent on family
fears, hopes, guilt or interests. One should also consider differences between family
members’ points of views. Decisions related to similar situations may differ in different
cultures, for example in Anglo-Saxon, Latin-American, European or Asian environments,
where notions about meanings of human life and about death and dying can differ. Cultures
influence decisions of patients, families and health professionals. Their religious thinking
can determine what they want for themselves or for their loved ones when they are
approaching their final stage in life. Whether they believe in eternal life or not, in re-
incarnation or in some form of transcendence based on their faith, has crucial influence over
their decisions. Decisions also largely depend on the economic situation of patients and
families, especially if they have to pay for final care by themselves without state or
insurance coverage. Health policies may greatly determine the kind and amount of care
Bioethics in the 21st Century
14
people will receive at the end of their life, according to hospital guidelines and available
resources. Last, but not least, decisions of quantity and kind of care depend to a great extent
on physicians and other professionals’ recommendations, which are also influenced by their
own cultures, values, experiences and personal sensibilities.
Another crucial issue for end of life decision making is to establish if the care and treatments
given to the patient are effective or futile, and if they are proportionate or not. These
determinations, sometimes defined as the likelihood of benefit cannot be established as
exact determinations. Technical and medical assessment for futility can be based on medical
evidence and experience, but proportionality of burdens or costs are non-medical appraisals
that should also be considered.
Before describing problems of end of life decisions, it is necessary to define what we
understand by euthanasia. Although it is not a focus of this chapter, it is part of an ongoing
debate. Different countries and cultures have dissimilar notions, social meanings and
legislations about this matter. What many people understand by euthanasia and what some
European legislations have approved, refers to well defined procedures to induce death in
specific circumstances of terminal patients. The terminology frequently used, of direct or
indirect, voluntary or non voluntary, and active or passive euthanasia, causes confusion.
Therefore, it is appropriate here to clarify that (medical) euthanasia should only be
understood as procedures that intentionally and voluntarily produce the patient’s death,
because of an incurable disease and unbearable suffering. It is therefore direct and voluntary
(Institut Borja de Bioética, 2005). This is different from accepting death as a foreseeable but
inevitable consequence of limiting futile or disproportionate treatments in order to avoid
suffering and therapeutic obstinacy. The ethical grounding of this is the moral difference
between producing and allowing death, and the well known doctrine of double effect.
Therefore, treatment limitation should not be confused with euthanasia.
4. End of life decision-making problems
Decisions related to patients who are in terminal conditions because of acute or chronic
diseases, as well as to those who are ending their lives with different degenerative
conditions, can be difficult and problematic. These problems concern in different degrees
patients, their surrogates, physicians and other health professionals. A list of these issues is
shown in Table 1. Decisions are focused on patients and their families’ views about the
meaning of life, the dying process and death itself. In some way, at least in the western
world, we live as if we are immortal, not recognizing our finitude. Difficult as it is to admit
to any serious disease, it is more difficult if its chances for recovery are rather low. In such
a situation many patients go into a personal existential crisis, questioning their life
achievements, developing complex fears and hopes. Some of them expect to have time
enough to express their wishes, to achieve some reconciliation with family members, to
express their gratitude to their loved ones and to pray according to their religion. Other
patients, with the same diagnosis and clinical situation, prefer not to know about their
condition, and therefore disregard information and deny the illness or its gravity. Some
want to extend their lives as much as possible, while others wish to have a short disease,
because they accept their death more readily or because they fear the disease and its
treatments. A personal approach is required. Imagine a 68 year old male with lung cancer
and initial metastasis. His younger daughter is planning her wedding to take place in two
months. He will most likely struggle to be alive at least for his daughter’s wedding, and
End of Life Treatment Decision Making
15
then to be able to see her with her new family, hopefully giving birth to her own children.
In this situation the patient, his daughter and the whole family will have the same
aspirations. In contrast, with the same diagnosis in another patient of the same age, but a
widower, retired and living alone, the patient may refuse treatment and expect the course
of his disease to be as short and painless as possible. A different situation is that of the
parents of a 5 year old son with deep brain damage because of birth asphyxia, who now
has a severe pneumonia on mechanical ventilation, with added multiresistant sepsis.
Some parents would accept that death, sad as it is, may be best for their child, while
others may request disproportionate therapies. Other problematic decisions are organ
transplant or abortion decisions, which are influenced or determined by cultures and
religions (The Lancet, 2011).
1. Patients’ and families’ views of death
2. Health professionals’ views of death
3. Human life regarded as an absolute value
4. The right to refuse treatment
5. Patients’ capacity
6. Surrogate’s decision capacities
7. The meaning of the duty to care
8. Quality of life
9. Fears of limiting treatments
10. Specific situations
Table 1. Main issues in end of life decisions
Physicians and other healthcare professionals such as nurses, physiotherapists, and
psychologists have views that influence information and guidance for patient or proxy’s
decisions. Perhaps our own biases are inevitable as we inform patients not only through
verbalization but also through our non verbal communication. And these biases in some
way determine the emphasis on prognosis, severity of the expected symptoms for the near
future, quality of life if the patient survives, and available courses of action (Gilligan and
Raffin, 1996). Examples are the issues presented in situations 3 and 4. It is difficult not to be
directive when informing patients and their relatives. It is important to recognize that health
care professionals are members of the same societies as their patients, although they do not
necessarily share the same culture, religion or beliefs. Therefore they may have similar
uncertainties and doubts. But it is even more challenging for health professionals, as they
may experience the death of their patients as a failure, both personally and of their
professions. This is why physicians often feel that even if they cannot cure a patient they
have the duty to prolong his or her life as much as possible. As part of the denial of their
patient’s impending death and because of the difficulties they have addressing family
members, intensive care residents try hard to keep patients alive, at least until the next shift.
Many times physicians are not prepared to limit treatments, arguing that their role is to
prevent death and that they should not play God, by shortening life (although arguably they
do so by prolonging life).
Bioethics in the 21st Century
16
Physicians and relatives often excessively prolong the agony of patients. Many end of life
treatments unduly prolong suffering. This is therapy obstinacy which is not a benefit but a
harm for the patient. A frequent reason to do so is viewing human life as an absolute value.
The notion of the absolute does not allow any grades and therefore life should be considered
a fundamental and not an absolute value. Still, if or when prolonged agony is worse than
death, our moral duty is to avoid suffering rather than to postpone death.
If the above issues are clearly understood, one can recognize and respect patients’ right to
refuse treatment, which is contrary to the paternalistic tradition of health care. Patients’
rights are based on autonomy, which is easier to understand in relation to elective
treatments or to informed consent to research. It is more challenging when terminal patients,
whose lives can be prolonged, refuse ordinary treatments. This may be because the patient
does not want to live anymore in what he or she views as extremely poor conditions, as in
situation 3. But it also may be the consequence of fears or of not having full understanding
of prognosis and of the treatment, as occurred with the parents’ decisions in situation 4.
There may be no problem if the refusal is for non-crucial procedures, but serious conflicts
might arise when it is for treatments that are considered medically necessary. Imagine
patients refusing feeding tubes, drainage or oxygen masks that are simple procedures that
mitigate symptoms and do not involve much risk. The conflict may be more challenging if
family members agree with these kinds of refusals, but may worsen when family members
refuse treatment for patients who have not even been asked about it. In some cultural
environments, such as in Latin America, this occurs often because families feel that asking
patients about treatment options can be a great emotional burden (to patients) that should
be avoided.
Patient decisions about their treatment rely on their right to decide. This right depends on
each person’s capacity. At times the assessment of capacity will not result in a yes or no
answer. If the patient was incapacitated long before the end of life situation, there will be
no problem and all his or her decisions have to be made by their proxy. A common
situation is that of partially capable patients who now may be less able to understand
their diagnosis and prognosis. Other cases may involve previously healthy and normal
adults who now have a critical disease with uncertain or very poor chances of full
recovery. In these circumstances, although they were previously able to express their
desires, they may now not be able to do so. The problem is how to establish whether the
patient is permanently or even temporarily incapacitated (Drane, 1985). Capacity implies
not only cognitive but also emotional qualities and patients in a critical condition may
have some degree of emotional difficulty to make decisions about their end of life
treatments (Gilligan & Raffin, 1996). It is necessary to evaluate capacity for each decision
in itself. Sometimes patient or family requests appear to be unreasonable or may even be
against the law. This would be the case if they demand to abruptly stop all treatments,
transfer a patient when it is not possible because of his needed life support requirements,
limit treatments when recovery is still likely, ask for the administration of lethal drugs,
and other extreme demands. Asking for disproportionate treatments can also be
considered as an unreasonable demand. Sometimes asking for more treatment, when
there is no chance of recovery and death is likely to occur within the next few hours or
days can be considered unreasonable, although it may be understandable. Examples of
these situations are demanding ECMO in cases of advanced lung fibrosis, mechanical
ventilation in advanced Lou Gehring’s disease, or more chemotherapy in final stages of
End of Life Treatment Decision Making
17
cancer. In all these cases, the conflict between families and physicians may become severe.
This should not be seen as disrespect of autonomy but as the limitation of autonomy,
because of the patient’s partial incapacity or because of unreasonable requirements that
would compromise medical integrity.
Assessment of patient’s capacity for end of life decision making is not sufficient. Decisions
may rely, at least partially, on surrogate decision makers. In some cultures, a proxy can be
formally nominated or designated, but in others many family members may honestly think
that they have the right to make decisions for capable patients. Stress and anxiety of those
who have to decide in the name of their loved ones is strong and unavoidable, which makes
it easier for them to avoid treatment limitation choices. Decisions or requirements coming
from a spouse, son or daughter who are in severe emotional distress are questionable.
Surrogates’ cognitive and emotional capacities should be assessed. Decision making may
conflict with a family’s values, sensibilities and interactions. Examples of these situations are
common, especially when one fairly dominant member of a family, sometimes with
personal emotional problems or guilt, strongly demands unreasonable treatment or
procedures. This can be very common in large families, in cultures where an extended
family feels that they can also participate in decision discussions, and in very dysfunctional
families. In such cases psychiatric evaluation and support can be helpful.
Other issues concern physicians and other health professionals or caregivers. They all share
the moral duty to care. Some of them believe that their responsibility is to always provide all
possible treatment to every patient. But the real duty to care is the commitment for the
patient’s good or best interest, and there are situations where the best for the patient is not
to prolong his or her life. Situation 1 and 4 are examples of this. The aim should be not a
longer life but a better life. These situations are complex and include many emotions and
sometimes severe disagreements among professionals and between them and family
members.
The previous paragraph relates to quality of life. Quality of life is a subjective judgment.
When somebody says I don’t want to live any more, he or she may be saying I don’t want
to continue living in this condition or with these symptoms. Many people would initially
say they would not accept chemotherapy or live with paraplegia or even with a
colostomy, but most patients in these conditions want to continue to live. These and other
limitations will certainly decrease their quality of life but they cannot be the only reason
to withhold or to withdraw treatments. Nevertheless, there are conditions which common
and reasonable people would never like to experience. Examples are a permanent
vegetative state, advanced Alzheimer disease, severe neurological damage without self
consciousness, and patients in unbearable pain with no response to analgesia. Quality of
life, even if it is subjective, should be one of the considerations for treatment decisions at
the end of life.
Different kinds of patients may require different responses for similar situations. This is so
with age differences as decisions on newborns, infants, children or elderly people may
differ. Decisions when faced with scarcity of resources, also differ. Imagine deciding to
refuse a potentially life saving new surgery, to stop vasoactive drugs or dialysis, to
deactivate a cardiac pacemaker (Goldstein et al., 2004 & Mueller et al., 2003) or to withdraw
mechanical ventilation (Campbell, 2007). One of the most challenging decisions is the
withdrawal of hydration or nutrition in vegetative states. Specific end of life decisions are
listed in Table 2.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
18
Treatment limitation decisions
Do Not Resuscitate Orders
No more diagnostic procedures
No more lab tests
Withholding new treatments
Withdrawal of hemodialysis
Discontinuing antibiotics
Discontinuing vasoactive drugs
Discontinuing mechanical ventilation
Withdrawal of artificial nutrition
Patient and family support decisions
Analgesia and sedation
Comfort procedures
Companionship
Favoring a private room or space
Emotional support
Spiritual support
Family bereavement support
Table 2. End of life treatment limitations and support decisions
5. Who should make end of life decisions?
Up to the second half of the twentieth century, the question who should make end of life
decisions had a simple and clear answer. Physicians had to decide, as they were supposed to
know what was best for their patient. This paradigm has changed, rejecting paternalism, as
patient autonomy has been endorsed. Also, decisions that were few and relatively
straightforward are now numerous and increasingly complex because of the rapidly
growing number of medical procedures. Nowadays it is not the attending physician who
has the power and responsibility for making decisions. Decision making is now sometimes
in many hands, each one with their own capacities and limitations (Karnik, 2002). The more
agents take part in decision-making, the more chances of conflict which in these highly
sensitive situations is difficult and distressing. A list of agents involved in end of life
decision making is shown in Table 3.
The default decision maker is the patient, based on his or her right to accept or refuse
treatments. This has been socially recognized and established in most contemporary
health legislation as part of human rights. The bioethical basis for this is the principle of
autonomy, which in health care means that everybody has a presumed right to decide
what can be done to him or her, and that nothing should be done to him or her without a
formal consent. However, the faculty to act with autonomy depends on capacity, on the
full comprehension of the clinical condition, of prognosis and of the possible medical
choices. Some patients are not autonomous since they lack minimum capacity, as occurs
with infants, younger children, patients who are severely brain damaged, have dementia
or are unconscious, and with those who are fully sedated. However, sometimes it may be
difficult to determine the patient’s capacity. Elderly patients are sometimes treated as
End of Life Treatment Decision Making
19
incompetent even if they are at least partially capable. Cognitive and emotional capacities
are required, as well as freedom, which means the absence of any sort of domination or
coercion which also may include some forms of intended compassionate guidance.
Patients facing critical disease or terminal diseases are living a personal crisis, and many
times feel alone, anxious or frightened. Therefore, their complete freedom to decide
autonomously may be questionable. But that doesn’t mean that they are not able to make
decisions for their treatments and medical care. When they cannot express their
preferences competently, other means have to be found in order to fully respect patient
values and preferences in end of life care.
Patients
Surrogates
Family members
Attending and other physicians
Other healthcare professionals
Institutional ethics committees
Ethics consultants
Institutional authorities
Judges
Table 3. End of life decision making agents
If the patient is not competent and therefore cannot make his or her own decisions, the best
way to proceed is to find out if he or she has previously expressed his or her wish. Although
it has been widely promoted in the U.S. and in many other countries, only a minority of
people have written living wills where they make known their wishes regarding life
prolonging medical treatments, and state the kind of care they would accept or refuse if not
able to decide for themselves. These advance directives (living wills) should be known to
family members and to caring physicians, but this does not always happen. These
documents, although helpful, are not definitive, as they are not very specific and at times
only state that the patient would not like to receive extraordinary life support measures or
unduly prolonging treatments. Another limitation is that these living wills are established
when the patient is not ill and thus is not facing the situation of approaching death. The text
may have been written years before and patients could have changed their views or
preferences since then. Therefore, living wills should be followed with judgment, as a guide
to respect patient values and hence autonomy.
Sometimes patients might have appointed a proxy using a durable power of attorney. Such
surrogates have the responsibility to assure that the patient receives end of life care
according to his or her preferences. In these cases it is the proxy’s responsibility to fully
respect the patient’s values, and to reject interventions he or she feels the patient would not
Bioethics in the 21st Century
20
have authorized if the patient were capable to decide. A surrogate needs to be objective and
unbiased, which is not easy as they are usually close friends or relatives who are
emotionally involved. The capacity of the surrogate has to be evaluated. When there are
discrepancies between medical recommendations and the proxy’s choices, problems may
emerge which have to be resolved through dialogue.
If the patient is not capable and has not appointed a proxy, then in some jurisdictions it is
the family’s role to represent him or her in decision making. A difficulty is that many
families are large and diverse, so then it becomes necessary to decide who within the family
will act as the patient’s surrogate. If the patient is married, his or her spouse may substitute
unless there is some clear impediment to that. For minor, parents may do so, although there
are special problems when parents disagree in their choices or when their wishes are not
clearly in the child’s best interest (McNab & Beca, 2010). Another problematic situation is
that of elderly patients with an absent or incapacitated spouse, and several sons and
daughters who may differ in their opinions. In these cases, difficult as it may be to
accomplish, it is best to appoint one of them as their spokesperson, making sure that all of
them are involved in the decisions that are made. In all these situations, the decisional
capacity of those who take part in decision making should be evaluated. Unreasonable
requests that are not in the patient’s best interest, or that do not respect the patient’s
preferences, do not have to be followed automatically and sometimes should be discussed
and appealed if needed.
The capable patient is the main agent for end of life decisions. A formal proxy or family
members are substitutes for incapable patients. This does not mean that patients or proxies
are the only decision makers. Historically, physicians were the main decision makers in
medical care, which has radically changed in the last decades, but they continue to have an
important role in deciding which treatments or procedures will be made available to
patients. Physicians have not only the responsibility of providing complete and clear
information but also a duty of guidance. Patients or surrogates may not have the capacity to
decide by themselves based only on clinical information. They need guidance which means
that attending physicians, the different involved specialists and residents, have to suggest
the best courses of action. Their guidance has to be non directive and as unbiased as
possible; therefore, physicians should acquire and develop these communication and
guidance skills (Yeolekar et al., 2008).
There is a wide network of physicians, residents and specialists, which includes intensive
care specialists, neurologists, cardiologists, surgeons and infectious disease specialists,
among others. This is similar with other healthcare professionals. Nurses are specialized and
teams include physiotherapists, psychologists, audiologists, clinical pharmacists, different
technicians, social workers and others. Each professional has a distinct appreciation of the
patient’s problems and what can be done to help him or her in the best way. Not
infrequently, patients and relatives establish good communication with the professionals
and trust their suggestions. It is common that non medical health professionals and other
care providers know more than physicians about the patient’s life, hopes, fears and wishes,
as well as about relevant issues. These professionals often play a significant role in the
decision making process in end of life patients, and this role needs to be acknowledged,
encouraged and supported by physicians.
Therefore, the decision making process involves the interaction of several agents rather
than a single decision by only one decision maker. This is a crucial notion that will be
End of Life Treatment Decision Making
21
developed further in this chapter. Depending on the complexities of each situation, more
decision agents may contribute to better decisions. When there is a great deal of
uncertainty or doubts, and when there are discrepancies between professionals’
suggestions and patients’ or proxys’ wishes, institutional or clinical ethics committees and
clinical ethics consultation can be helpful. Ethics committees are multidisciplinary groups
whose objectives are to propose guidelines in their institutions, to offer continued
education in bioethics for staff, and to analyze complex situations ethically. Situations are
presented to committees by physicians, other professionals, patients or families. The
analyses are conducted using deliberation, and suggestions are made. The method that
each committee uses may be different, but it is important that the method is specified.
One of the common methods is principlism, based on how a decision respects and
harmonizes the four principles of biomedical ethics: Autonomy, Non Maleficence,
Beneficence, and Justice (Beauchamp & Childress, 2001). Another widely used method is
casuistic analysis, which emphasizes the weight of clinical facts, quality of life, patient
preferences and contextual features (Jonsen et al., 1998). In Spanish and Latin-American
committees, a commonly used method is deliberation, as explained by Diego Gracia. It
starts with defining an ethical referential frame and continues with the analysis of
the clinical situations, the added social or contextual facts, the possible courses of action,
and it ends with suggestions and their ethical reasons (Gracia, 2007). No matter which
method a committee uses, their analysis should be multidisciplinary, including partners
such as diverse health professionals, philosophers, chaplains, social workers, lawyers and
more.
Clinical situations with ethical problems occur often in many hospitals, but only a few are
presented to an ethics committee. The reasons for this may be that it is time consuming, it
may be delayed, and physicians may fear being ethically judged. As a consequence, many
informal inquiries are submitted to committee members, who then cannot use a proper
method of analysis. As an alternative, individual ethics consultations are used, particularly
in the US. Formal ethics consultations are less frequent in Europe and have only been
recently reported in Latin-America. Ethics consultations are complementary to the
committees and should not replace this institutional ethical deliberation entity. They
constitute bed-side clinical bioethics with the purpose of helping to identify and analyze
ethical problems of single situations. Ethics consultations, either realized by a single
consultant or by two or three members of an ethics committee, assist in decision making in
situations with ethical uncertainties, and they can also diminish the moral distress of all
involved. Ethics consultation can be conducted by a single consultant or by a team on call.
Consultants can analyze each situation with the involved professionals and care givers, with
patient families and with patients as much as possible. This has the disadvantage of the
absence of multidisciplinary deliberation. Other limitations are that consultations are
extremely dependant on each consultant’s communication skill, the consultant’s biases
compassion and tolerance. Therefore, ethics consultants’ competencies have been
established, in addition to the requirement to be able to comprehend clinical features
(Aluisio, 2000). Clinical ethics consultants sometimes become mediators when there are
discrepancies between staff, patients’, and families’ points of view.
Not only patients, surrogates, physicians and other health care providers, institutional
ethics committees and ethics consultants have a role in decision making at the end of life.
Sometimes hospitals or healthcare institutions have their own guidelines that have to be
Bioethics in the 21st Century
22
followed. Health insurance companies may have specific policies that constrain patient
care, in relation to assessments, treatment and more. In some countries, some decisions
are established by each legislation and in some cases the final decision may be made by
judges.
End of life decisions are practical decisions that involve moral judgments. Such applied
ethics is uncertain. Some degree of uncertainty is part of many clinical decisions. This may
be why clinical and ethical decisions about care are difficult and stressful. So who should
make end of life decisions? There should not be a single decision maker. All parties that
have been mentioned have a role in the decision making process. Some of them, such as
ethics committees or clinical ethics consultants, are expected to use a specific method to
analyze situations and to offer suggestions. Decisions are a matter of shared decision
making based on an open and tolerant dialogue between all the mentioned parties.
6. How can End of Life decision making be improved?
The question is whether decision making can be improved and if so how. First, decisions
should always be focused on what is best for the patient. This means treatment of pain,
anxiety and other symptoms, together with fulfilling the patient’s needs and wishes as much
as possible. End of life decisions should actively pursue a peaceful death. To improve these
decisions, it is important to recognize that there cannot be only one method, guideline or
decision algorithm, but some suggestions will be offered here.
The focus should always be the patient’s “good”. This is not a scientific or technical issue.
Medical facts are necessary but not sufficient for this. In order to know what is best for each
patient, his or her whole biography, values, fears, hopes and preferences have to be
considered. Knowledge of social, family, economic and other contextual features is also
important. Involvement in decision making of all those who know, love and care about the
patient is needed. The aim of end of life care should thus focus on effective palliative care.
Decisions should focus on better physical, emotional and spiritual care, and by no means
any sort of patient abandonment.
In a strict sense the patient’s best interest should be determined by him or herself. This is not
possible if the patient is entirely or partially unconscious, which is common when they are
in their terminal stage. Therefore the aim is to respect as much as possible what he or she
expressed when they were able to do so. When patient have written living wills or have
formally appointed a proxy, there is far more knowledge of their preferences, even if the
exact conditions or symptoms were not known or anticipated when they expressed their
wishes. The basis of this is respect for Autonomy. Hence, a suggestion to improve end of life
decisions is to promote that people write their preferences in their own way or using living
wills. But, valuable as it may be to have more written living wills, it is even more important
that all adults talk about death and dying within their families and, if possible, clarify the
care they would like to receive if they have an incurable terminal condition and are not able
to decide for themselves.
Another way to improve end of life decision making is to increase ongoing efforts to
improve clinicians’ communication skills. Their training at undergraduate and postgraduate
levels as well as in continuous education programs should develop these competencies that
are the basis for getting to know the treatments patients wish for their end of life care.
Health care professionals should also be trained to provide emotional support to patients
and families. Physicians should also develop their own understanding of the meaning of
End of Life Treatment Decision Making
23
death, respect the different views that patients and families may have, and acquire the
necessary proficiency for symptomatic rather than curative treatment.
It has been suggested that surrogates could be supplied with empirical information on what
patients in similar circumstances tend to prefer, allowing them to make empirically
grounded predictions about what the patients they are involved with would want (Rid &
Wandler, 2010). Relevant anecdotal reports could also be very useful for surrogates. When
families take part in decisions on behalf of their loved ones, they will likely have doubts and
experience stress. Therefore another suggestion for improvement of the quality of decision
making is to support and guide surrogates.
A particularly helpful way of improving family participation in decision making is to
provide personal counseling for those who are more involved and to conduct special
meetings with the patient’s family, other significant others and caregivers. Counseling and
family meetings may be conducted by attending physicians or other staff and are typically
led by social workers, at least in North America.
Not all end of life situations involve ethics committees or ethics consultants, but the most
challenging ones may have a better outcomes if they are consulted. Therefore, a suggestion
to improve these decisions in places where there are no clinical ethics committees or
consultants is to train in bioethics a group of professionals in order to establish such
consultations.
A special and particularly difficult situation occurs when patients who are in nursing homes
have a life threatening illness. Whenever possible they should be supported to communicate
how they would like to be treated. The majority of people in this situation, particularly in
some countries, do not have written advance directives nor have they expressed their
treatment preferences. Furthermore, their relatives or proxies may not be available when
decisions have to be made. It is not the nursing home staff or caregivers’ responsibility to
decide what may be adequate and proportionate treatment in each situation. In such
situations, it may be helpful to delineate in advance what physicians and non-physician
health professionals together with the patient’s family regard as the best compassionate care
for each patient. If the person is partially capable, his or her capacity should be enhanced if
possible, to better know what his or her preferences are. Such pre-determination addresses
admission to a hospital or critical care unit, treatment of new diseases or complications,
chemotherapy or surgery, artificial nutrition procedures, other support and more.
Interesting tools for this purpose are the Physician Orders for Life Sustaining Treatments
(POLST) forms that are offered to improve the quality of care that people receive at the end
of their lives. POLST are based on effective communication between health professionals,
patients in nursing homes and their families. These forms are available in different
languages (Oregon POLST program).
Another suggestion to improve end of life decisions is to advocate that they be made in a
timely manner, as they are often made after prolonged and avoidable suffering. In order to
have these decisions made on time, the possibility of having to make them should be
anticipated, preferably at the time of patients’ hospital admission or soon after their
diagnosis and prognosis have been established.
It is important to remember that end of life decisions are complex and that decision makers
will have to take part in lengthy and/or complex processes. It is important to note that
everybody involved has specific roles in these processes. Physicians have to determine the
diagnosis and the possible courses of action, other health professionals share a role in
support and guidance, the patient will have to consent to or refuse treatments, family
Bioethics in the 21st Century
24
members or surrogates input the patient’s values and preferences (when known), and ethics
committees or consultants have expert advising and mediating functions. These are not
isolated and independent roles, as it has to be a shared decision making process. End of life
decisions will only be (clinically and ethically) good decisions if they are truly shared
decisions that respect all points of view in order to fully address patients’ best interests
(assuming that is primarily determined by patients’ capable choices, if known).
7. Conclusion
Advances in medical knowledge, technology, diagnostic procedures and treatment
alternatives in the last few decades have produced new clinical and ethics problems, many
of them related to end of life decision making. The different decisions to be made at end of
life should be based on the patient’s best interests, preferences, values and expressions of his
or her wishes. With a benefit-burden analysis, the aim ought to be the best treatment for
pain, anxiety or other symptoms, and the pursuit of a peaceful death rather than the
prolongation of life if that is accompanied by agony (most religions accept reduction of such
suffering).
End of life decisions are mainly related but not restricted to withholding or withdrawing
specific treatments. The aim is to avoid therapeutic obstinacy and patient abandonment, and
to include in end of life care emotional and spiritual support for patients and their families.
The process of decision making is associated with different views about the meaning of
human life and death, and with patients’ and surrogates’ rights. Relevant problems are
related to the evaluation of decision capacities, differences between caregivers and patients
or families, and diverse moral or legal concerns.
Decisions should be made by various agents, including the patient, and proxies or family
members as needed. Physicians and the other health care professionals have relevant
responsibilities, and ethics committees or ethics consultation have facilitation and
mediation roles. The key is that it has to be a shared decision making process with respect
for all points of view, addressing what is best for the patient and leaving out other
interests (note that justice such as in relation to resource allocation was not discussed
here).
In order to improve end of life decisions we suggest: encourage people to write their living
wills; support and guide surrogates; and promote timely decision making. In health
professional education, clinicians should be trained to acquire adequate communication
skills, emotional and moral strength, and at least basic knowledge of bioethics.
9. References
A.S.P.E.N.(2010). Ethics Position Paper. Nutr. Clin.Pract, Vol. 25,No.6 (December 2010),
pp.672-679, eISSN 1941-2452, ISSN 0884-5336.
Aulisio, M.P.(2000). Health care ethics consultation: nature, goals and competencies. A
position paper from the Society for Health and Human Values-Society for Bioethics
Consultation Task Force on Standards for Bioethics Consultation. Ann. Intern. Med.
Vol.133, No.1,(July 2000), pp. 59-69, ISSN 0003-4819 , eISSN 1539-3704.
Beauchamp, T.L, Childress J.F. (2001). Principles of Biomedical Ethics, Fifth edition. New York,
Oxford University Press, ISBN 0-19-514332-0.
End of Life Treatment Decision Making
25
Callahan, D. (1995). Setting Limits: Medical Goals in an Aging Society. Washington DC,
Gerogetown University Press, ISBN 9780878405725.
Campbell, M.L. (2007). How to Withdraw Mechanical Ventilation. AACN. Adv. Crit. Care,
Vol.18, No.4,(Oct-Dec 2007), 397-403, ISSN 1559-7768, eISSN 1559-7776.
Chochinov, H.M., Cann B.J. (2005). Interventions to enhance the spiritual aspects of dying. J.
Palliat. Med., Vol.8, Suppl.1, S103-15, ISSN 1096-6218. eISSN 1557-7740.
Drane, J. (1985). The many faces of competency. Hastings. Center. Rep, Vol. 15, No.2, (April
1985), pp.17-21, ISSN 0093-0334.
The Lancet Editorial. (2011). Religion, organ transplantation, and definition of death. Lancet,
Vol.377, No.9762, (January 2011), pp.271, ISSN 0140-6736, eISSN 1474-547X.
Emanuel, E.J., Emmanuel L.L.(1992). Four Models of the Physician-Patients Relationship.
JAMA Vol. 267, No.16 (April 1992), pp. 2221-2216, ISSN 0098-7484, eISSN 1538-
3598.
Gilligan, T., Raffin TA. (1996). End-of-life discussions with patients. Timing and truth-
telling. Chest Vol.109, No.1 (January 1996), pp.11-12, ISSN 0012-3692, eISSN 1931-
3543.
Goldstein, N.E., Lampert, R., Bradley, E., Lyn, J., Krumholtz, H.M. (2004). Management of
implantable cardioverter defibrillators in end of life care. Ann. Intern. Med, Vol.141,
No.11, (December 2004), pp.835-838, ISSN 0003-4819, eISSN 1539-3704.
Gracia, D. (2007). Procedimientos de decisión en ética clínica. Madrid, Triacastela, ISBN 978-84-
9584840.
Hanson, M.J. & Callahan, D.(1999). The Goals of Medicine. The Forgotten Issues in Health Care
Reform. Washington DC, Georgetown University Press, ISBN 9780878408450.
Institut Borja de Bioètica (Universidad Ramon Llull) 2005. Hacia una posible despenalización de
la eutanasia.
Available from: http://ibbioetica.org/eutanasia/auta_cast.pdf
Jonsen, A.R., Siegler, M., Windsale, W.J. (1998). Clinical Ethics, 4th ed. McGraw-Hill Health
Professions Division. ISBN 0-07-033120-0, New York, U.S.A.
Karnik A.M., (2002). End of life Issues and Do-Not-Resuscitate Order: Who Gives the Order
and What Influences the Decision. Chest, Vol. 121, No.3 (March 2002), pp.683-686,
ISSN 0012-3692, eISSN 1931-3543.
Mc Nab, M.E., Beca J.P. (2010). Existen Límites en la Decisión de los Padres sobre el
Tratamiento de sus Hijos? Rev Chil Pediatr Vol. 81, No.6, pp.536-540. ISSN 0370-
4106.
Meisel, A., Synder, L., Quill, T. (2000). Seven legal barriers of end-of-life care: myths,
realities and grains of truth. JAMA Vol.284, No.19, (November 2000), 2495-2501,
ISSN 0098-7484, eISSN 1538-3598.
Mueller, P.S., Hook C.C., Hayed, D.L. (2003). Ethical analysis of withdrawal of pacemaker or
implantable cardioverter-defibrilator support at the end of life. Mayo Clinic
Proceeding, Vol.78, No. 8, (August 2003), pp. 959-963, ISSN 0025-6196, eISSN1942-
5546.
Oregon POLST Information. Available from:
www.ohsu.edu/polst/programs/oregon-detalis.htm
Bioethics in the 21st Century
26
Real Academia de Medicina de Cataluña. Obstinación Terapéutica. Documento, 2005.
Available from:
http://biblio.upmx/download/cebidoc/Dossiers/distanasia0312.asp
Rid, A., Wendler, D. (2010). Can we improve treatment decision making for incapacitated
patients? Hastings Center Report, Vol. 40, No. 5, (Sept-Oct 2010), pp. 36-45, ISSN
0093-0334.
Sulmasy, D.P. (2006). The Rebirth of the Clinic. An Introduction to Spirituality in Health Care.
Georgetown University Press, Washington DC, U.S.A. ISBN 15890 10957
Yeolekar, M.E., Mehta, S., Yeolekar, A. (2008). End of life care: Issues and challenges. J
Postgrad Med, Vol. 54, 173-5. ISSN 0022-3859
3
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses
and Addictions
Barbara J. Russell
Centre for Addiction and Mental Health
and University of Toronto’s Joint Centre for Bioethics
Canada
1. Introduction
1.1 Overview
The general public learns about mental illnesses and addictions primarily from mainstream
media, including news reports, television programs, and movies. The stories presented
usually centre on sensationalism or danger such as those about young women at life-
threatening stages of anorexia nervosa or people labelled as “psychopaths.” Or the stories
appeal to our feelings of sympathy or empathy such as those about people with untreated
mental illnesses sleeping on subway vents during winter or a person with moderate
dementia who finds greater companionship with someone other than their spouse. These
reports and programs often oversimplify the ethical nature of these situations by
dramatically pitting one value against another: self-determination versus life, public safety
versus rehabilitation, quality of life versus non-abandonment, and happiness versus loyalty.
Distilling situations down to one or two values can be motivated more by the ongoing
competition for the public’s attention and/or economics than by the demands of concise
reporting.
However, mental illnesses and addictions are complex, as those who live with a mental
health or addiction problem and their families can attest. The high incidence of mental
health and addiction problems and their disruptive and lasting impact on people’s lives,
families’ sustainability, communities’ well-being, and employers’ productivity are publicly
acknowledged more often now. In recent years, more and more governments (civic,
provincial/state, national) and employers have become interested in listening to those with
first-hand experience of these conditions and to those who have developed holistic,
integrative ways to diagnose and offer treatments and supports earlier and longer.
Ethical complexity is not limited to crises and strong emotions. It exists in everyday,
seemingly routine questions, experiences, and situations. The cases in section 1.2, below,
help illustrate the wide diversity of ethically complex, “real world” situations that those
living with a mental health or addiction problem, their families and friends, professional
healthcare workers and their managers commonly face. Accordingly, the selected cases
involve a variety of participants, interests, contexts, histories, health problems, options, and
values. The healthcare ethics literature---which is quite extensive now---and educational
workshops and courses encourage their readers and participants to increase their
understanding of a particular situation or question and they offer various theories, concepts,
Bioethics in the 21st Century
28
and approaches to help make ethically defensible decisions. This chapter has similar
objectives: first, to broaden and deepen readers’ understanding of ethically relevant aspects
in living with a mental health or addiction concern; second to increase the understanding of
ethically relevant aspects in offering, managing, and accessing healthcare services; and
third, to increase readers’ abilities to determine which options or responses to a particular
issue or situation are and are not ethically sound.
With this said, though, it is not just “soundness” or basic justification that will be
emphasized here. Too often decisions can be merely adequate ethically or minimally ethical.
The appropriate goal is strongly ethical decisions and responses. Whether treating spina
bifida, colitis or alcohol dependence, clinicians and healthcare organizations do not talk
about providing merely adequate or merely acceptable therapies. In terms of the “technical”
aspects of the programs and treatments they offer, their language is peppered with
adjectives such as high quality, incomparable, excellent, leading, the best, and world-class.
Why then settle for ethically “okay” or ethically adequate analyses and conclusions about
these same interventions? A healthcare treatment or service cannot be described as first-rate
or promulgated as “the standard of care” if its related ethical features have been simplified
or minimized. The level of attention to and engagement with an intervention or service’s
ethical features directly and proportionately impacts its quality.
Two other considerations contribute to ethically strong health care practices and services.
Health and healthcare are not about decisions and choices only. They are also and
inescapably about human interactions, whether it is the person’s interactions with her
family, teachers, or employer, or her interactions with her healthcare team, or the
interactions among her interprofessional and interagency workers. In his book, Ethics and the
Clinical Encounter (2004) and as a philosopher who spends a lot of time in hospitals, Richard
Zaner insightfully explores and questions the formal-informal and multivalent-ambiguous
interactions that occur routinely between patients and professionals. “How” we are with
one another matters a great deal ethically. Arthur Frank, a well-known sociologist whose
scholarly interests include the meaning of illness and interactions with professionals and
institutions, suggests, “We should speak less of ethics as some activity or substantive
content that appears to stand alone and more of ethical relations” (2004, 357). In the case of
Omar, below, if the defensible option is transferring him to an outpatient program, how this
is explained remains important ethically. If the explanation about the pending discharge
from hospital and transfer to a community program is condescending, dismissive, and
implies the decision is non-negotiable, Omar’s defensiveness, anger, and non-cooperation
should surprise no one. Unethical language, tone, and demeanour can transform what
seems, at the time, to be a good option---all things considered---into a poor and
unpersuasive option.
Frank cautions against excessive emphasis on decision making when he states that:
“Being ethical… has less to do with making a single decision than with initiating a
process–--often a very slow process---of a person or persons coming to feel that how
they acted was as good as it could have been, given the inherent impossibility of the
situation (Ibid, 355-6).
Although “inherent impossibility” is meant to refer to healthcare situations typified by
complicated machinery, invasive procedures, and life-threatening events (e.g., in intensive
care units, in operating rooms, and in emergency departments), Frank’s point holds true for
long-term mental illnesses and substance use problems, too. Accordingly, this chapter’s
second noteworthy consideration is participants’ characters or who they are, from both the
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
29
perspectives of important people in their lives and from their own perspective. In modern
bioethics discussions and analyses, virtue ethics as an ethical theory has tended to rely on
Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (350 B.C.) and contemporary philosopher Alasdair
MacIntyre’s After Virtue (first published in 1981). More recently, philosopher Lisa Tessman
has insightfully examined the durability and praiseworthiness of character virtues in
progressively oppressive and harsh situations and societies. Burdened Virtues: virtue ethics for
liberatory struggles (2005) is a welcome rehabilitation of virtue theory such that it is highly
relevant for mental health and addictions settings because unfortunately these settings can
be restricting, stigmatizing, and marginalizing.
The remainder of this chapter starts with a description of seven cases and then describes
ethically salient concepts and values for mental illnesses and addictions’ questions, issues,
and situations. Admittedly, some of these concepts are meaningful for any illness, injury or
health condition. Nonetheless, certain ethical concepts are especially meaningful for serious
mental health and addiction problems. Concluding this chapter by identifying and applying
ethical values relevant to each of the opening seven cases might be the expected ending. The
experiences of a newly-minted ethicist explain why the actual conclusion is somewhat
different.
Daniel Sokol (2007) wrote a perceptive editorial piece in the BMJ describing his first days
and weeks as an ethicist in a large general hospital in London. Surrounded by innumerable
procedures, treatments, and appointments as he accompanies a nephrologist, Sokol observes
that, “My proximity to the patients, instead of highlighting the ethical commitments,
obscured them” (670). It took awhile before he could see beyond what was urgent and close.
With time, he began to see the underlying ethical quandaries, unasked questions, and
troubling assumptions. His personal experience underscores an ability or skill that is critical
for strong ethical analyses and responses: awareness or discernment (Holland, 1998;
Nussbaum, 1985).
In this light, the section on ethical concepts and values is followed by four sections
describing other considerations that bear significantly on what constitutes a strong
ethically defensible decision or response for mental health and addictions issues and
questions. These four sections cover clinical, legal, organizational and systemic factors
that cannot be ignored or dismissed by those endeavouring to understand and respond
well ethically. In healthcare, ethics does not stand alone…. an unfortunate notion that can
be reinforced when ethics specialists dramatically “parachute in” to meet briefly with a
clinical team and the patient/family and leave just as quickly. Moreover integrating all
five aspects means that ethics never trumps everything else (Russell, 2008). It is both naïve
and impractical for an ethicist to say, “Just do what is most ethical to do in this situation.”
Therefore this chapter’s concluding section re-visits the opening cases and identifies their
ethical, clinical, legal, organizational, and systemic considerations and analyzes what
qualifies as strongly ethical decisions and, as per Frank’s wisdom, ethically strong
interactions and characters.
Stylistic note: Many people consider the term “mental illness” to include addictions. In this
chapter, however, they routinely will be referred to separately to ensure that addiction
problems are not overlooked. Instead of “substance dependence, misuse, and abuse,” the
wordaddiction is used to help reduce this chapter’s length. Ethical worries about the
word will be discussed in section 6.1. Recently, however, various professionals have
recommended “addiction” be used in the future DSM-V, the diagnostic manual of North
American psychiatry. Different words are used to refer to those living with a mental health
Bioethics in the 21st Century
30
or addiction problem, such as patient, client, consumer, and survivor. “Client” will be used
most often in this chapter because it portrays a reasonable balance in the power and
interests between the individual and healthcare professionals and organizations and
because most people with these health problems access treatments while living in the
community.
1.2 Prototypical cases
The following cases illustrate the ethical complexity of everyday practices and interactions
in mental health and addiction settings. It is accidental and unintentional if any case is
identical to a real event or person. The cases, however, have been written to be
representative amalgams of common situations and issues. All names are hypothetical and
used for easier reading and to underscore the human and personal dimensions.
Case 1: Noticing that “Sergei” looks flushed, talks rather loudly and directly, and his breath
smells mint-y sweet, the community health clinic nurse asks him whether he has had a few
drinks this morning. He chuckles, shifts nervously on the examining table, and says, “Well,
not really.” “Nothing?” she responds. He looks down at the floor and says “No.” This is
Sergei’s fourth visit for recurring back and leg pain and stiffness. Test results and
recommendations from a hospital-based specialist have just arrived. She proceeds to test
and document his reflexes, blood pressure, pulmonary-stomach-bowel sounds, heart rate,
and temperature.
As she walks down the corridor to see the next patient, the nurse suddenly wonders
whether Sergei, who is 46 years old and immigrated with his wife and 2 children from
Russia five years ago, drove to the clinic “under the influence” and whether he drinks and
drives regularly. She vaguely recalls that he presented the same way at a previous
appointment. There is provincial legislation that requires physicians to notify the
Transportation Ministry if they believe a patient has a medical condition that makes his or
her driving dangerous. The nurse asks herself, “The doctor who will talk with Sergei about
the specialist’s report… should I tell her about what I am thinking or will she make her own
decision when she sees him?”
Case 2: About 2 weeks ago, “Ana Li” was admitted to the mental health unit from the
emergency department (ED). Ana Li’s mother brought her to the ED because Ana Li was
experiencing hallucinations, not thinking clearly, and becoming more and more upset and
frenetic. Since admission, Ana Li has resumed taking previously prescribed medications for
bipolar disease (she is 19 years old and was assessed as having the capacity to legally
consent to treatment). Although she has attended a few of the unit’s weekly group activities,
sustained or in-depth discussions with her are not yet possible so psychotherapeutic options
have not been offered thus far.
During this morning’s team review of all their clients, one member mentions Ana Li’s
continuing hypersexual statements and wishes, and asks whether anyone else worries she
will act on them. He suggests her status should be changed from “voluntary” to
“involuntary” for awhile and she be restricted to the unit because she may trade sexual
“favours” in return for cigarettes from co-clients or someone she meets on or near the
hospital grounds. Another team member shakes her head and says, “The Mental Health Act
is more interested in preventing major harms like suicide or assault, not casual sex.”
Another team member immediately adds, “But we have to be realistic about this. Hasn’t
each one of us remarked how ‘drop dead gorgeous’ Ana Li is? Plus if there’s unprotected
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
31
sex, then we are going to be dealing with a sexually transmitted disease or even a
pregnancy.”
Case 3: One of the organization’s clinical directors has been working there for almost three
months. By introducing new initiatives, he has two goals for today’s monthly meeting with
the clinical managers and professional heads: (1) to move the program more quickly to the
forefront of contemporary mental health and addictions practices, and (2) to be a role model
for continuous innovation. One initiative will require at least one home visit for all new
referrals in order to understand more quickly and thoroughly clients’ individual lived
experiences, available supports, and enduring barriers to recovery. The second initiative
involves hiring a peer support worker to be a member of each clinical team. Peer support
workers serve as unique resources and supports to clients because they have personal
knowledge both of living with a mental health or addiction condition and of some of the
different ways that family and friends, the healthcare system, the legal system, and social
service organizations may and may not contribute to recovery. The director is unsure
whether his plans will be met by eagerness, defensiveness, or stony silence.
Case 4: A judge rules that “Jane,” who is 68 years old, should not be jailed as punishment for
assaulting her landlord when he said she would be evicted in seven days if her apartment
remained a fire hazard and malodorous. The landlord fell trying to dodge Jane’s fists and a
resulting cut required an emergency department visit and six sutures. The judge’s ruling
diverts Jane to a psychiatric facility for treatment of a mental health condition that results in
extreme hoarding behaviour. Review Board hearings are scheduled after the first six months
of hospitalization and then every twelve months. Jane is not swayed by her Legal Aid
lawyer’s advice that she not testify at the first hearing because her nervousness and anger
may persuade the Board to not change the order. She testifies and is very nervous, quite
disorganized in her responses, and uses some clearly racist language. The Board does not
change the mandatory hospitalization order. The next hearing is in one month. Her clinical
team believes Jane has improved from her participation in eleven months of behaviour
therapy, trauma counselling, and medications, such that they will recommend conditional
discharge into the community. Yet a few team members worry that her lawyer will let her
testify and her nervousness and inflammatory comments will again persuade the Board to
continue the hospitalization order.
Case 5: “Omar” has lived with moderately severe schizophrenia for 30 years; he’s now 52
years old. He has lived in different group homes and subsidized housing, has not been close
with most of his family since young adulthood, and relies financially on a modest
governmental disability program. Omar has inconsistently taken and sometimes
discontinued taking various typical and atypical antipsychotic medications for different
reasons: the bothersome and discouraging side effects, not wanting to depend on drugs, and
simple forgetfulness. Emergency hospitalizations have been required from time to time in
order to re-commence or revise medications to reduce distressing thoughts and
hallucinations as well as to re-connect him with the community mental health agencies in
and near his town. Omar’s general health is poor: pulmonary and cardiovascular problems
due to chronic smoking and, as a likely result of long-term antipsychotic medications,
diabetes, which has been poorly controlled.
Police officers bring him to the psychiatric emergency after finding him asleep in a cold alley
on a night when the temperature dips nears freezing. He is hospitalized to resume his
Bioethics in the 21st Century
32
psychotropic medications and to try to find a housing facility that offers a modest level of
supervision. Since hospitalization, Omar’s leg and foot ulcers unfortunately have increased
in size and depth despite antibiotic administration. Efforts to keep the ulcers clean and
bandages on and clean typically have resulted in arguments between nursing staff and him.
The standard of care for the diabetic ulcers now requires debriding and deep cleaning,
which will need to done at a nearby tertiary hospital by a specialist. Two weeks ago, Omar
agreed to the proposed debridement. On the morning of the appointment, however, he tells
the staff member who will accompany him to the hospital, “There is no way I am going to
any hospital.” Over the next few days, his assigned nurses explain the benefits of the
specialist visit and debridement. He eventually agrees again to go because “I don’t want to
lose my foot.” The visit is scheduled for the following week. A week passes. Today when a
staff member says “Omar, it’s time for us to head over to see the specialist about the sores
on your foot and leg,” he replies, “No thanks. I don’t want someone digging around my foot
and leg. I’m staying here.”
Case 6: The concurrent disorders (comorbid addiction and mental illness) program is
organizing a special day-long workshop to increase community-based physicians’,
therapists’, and addictions workers’ knowledge and support for families with a member
who has gambling or prescription opioid problems. Four smaller community-based services
were invited to help organize the workshop as a way to increase collaboration among the
organizations. To attract more physicians, therapists, and addictions workers, two
prominent speakers have been invited and the venue will be at one of the area’s nicer hotels.
Representatives from each partner organization are discussing ways to cover the costs of the
hotel’s food and beverage services, room rental, and the speakers’ travel expenses. Setting
the registration fees high enough to cover the costs will likely discourage too many workers
at smaller agencies or programs from attending. One of the representatives suggests
contacting the regional pharmaceutical representative and a local brewery representative to
make a financial donation. Another representative suggests having a raffle for a “fancy spa
weekend” as a way to increase the number of registrants.
Case 7: “Sandra” and her partner permit her older brother “Edward” to move into their
home while he looks for somewhere affordable to live near his new job. Since she uses many
of the household practices they grew up with, Sandra knows her home is a place of comfort
and love for him. He promises to see his therapist every three weeks and to have a
community physician renew his psychiatric medication before there are only ten pills left. It
is important to hear him explicitly commit to seeing the therapist and taking the
medications because in the past, he has become so ill that he often verbally abused and
threatened those with whom he lived, such as a favourite uncle and his family.
Five months later, Sandra contacts the physician---whose name she finds on the prescription
bottle---to ask if crushing the pills into Edward’s food decreases their efficacy. She had
started doing this two months ago when she learned that Edward had stopped taking the
pills because he believed he no longer needed them and subsequently became angry when
she reminded him of his earlier promise. Since then, whenever Sandra has found a new
prescription slip for the psychiatric medications in Edward’s room, she has had it filled by
the neighbourhood pharmacist. Yet whenever the physician asks Edward at their
appointments whether he is taking the psychiatric medications and feels they are helping,
Edwards always says he is taking them as prescribed and they seem to help. The physician
refrains from telling him about the conversations with his sister and her actions because he
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
33
believes that the medications, residing in a home environment, and the sister’s involvement
are in Edward’s best interests.
2. Foundational ethical considerations
A familiar claim by those working as ethics specialists in hospitals and those teaching
healthcare ethics is “It’s ethics all the way down.” Ethics involves what should matter or
what should be valued and based on such values, what should be our aspirations,
behaviours, and relationships. The word “should” is important here; in philosophical
settings, “should” represents the normative element of ethics. There is a critical difference
between what is valued and what should be valued. We must ask what are the reasons to
value something and whether they are defensible or justified reasons. It is important to
underscore that not all values are ethical, though everything that is ethical is based on
values. This distinction is often disregarded in healthcare ethics.
Healthcare is informed by a host of values, including self-interest, economics (which can
include efficiency and productivity measures), reputation, relationships, and politics (i.e.,
power). For example, a decision to generate added revenue by charging to train community
workers can be justified by economics. To justify it ethically, though, the added revenue
would have to be used, for instance, to provide more recreational activities for clients’
enjoyment and rehabilitation. If the additional monies were used to increase the agency’s
profile as the area’s “go to” agency, then its justification would be focused on politics
and/or reputation. Further examination would be required to determine if a better
reputation will or will not contribute to achieving the agency’s ethically defensible goals.
2.1 Being humane
It seems obvious that illnesses do not detract from being a human. Yet being a human, that
is a member of the homo sapiens species, is not the same as being humane. “Being humane”
typically means thinking, behaving, and interacting in certain ways. In the context of mental
health and addictions programs and services, being humane warrants discussion because it
may be what is first sacrificed when units are busy and staff levels are low.
Much has been written in the ethics literature and the nursing literature about the
importance of caring and compassion: 21,246 articles and 1,285 articles respectively are
listed when these key words are used with CINAHL, a primary nursing database. It is
important, however, to distinguish between caring/compassion and respect because they
are made manifest by different actions. If a close friend of someone unable to leave his home
due to a relapse of his depression arranges an outing that will be as “easy” as possible to
accept, this is an act of caring. Prior to deciding whether to go, if the depressed person
listens carefully to what has been arranged and why specific arrangements have been made,
this is an act of respect. If a case worker has a few toys in his office to occupy clients’
children and does not keep clients waiting more than five minutes beyond their
appointment time, he has been, respectively, caring and respectful. As Frank incisively
points out, “Being ethical… is never anything that one has” (2004, 356). It is something one
does or strives to do. Skilfulness is relevant to ethics, just as it is to nursing and case
management, in terms of astutely discerning what is required and how it can best be
accomplished. Ineptness should not be repeatedly forgiven simply because the person had
good intentions.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
34
Being humane should also include generosity and welcome, two qualities often
overlooked in everyday interactions. Generosity is not about money. Instead it is a
philanthropy of spirit and hope wherein people are pro-the Other. Yet this generosity
does not equate to strident self-sacrifice and Puritanism. It involves giving but it can be in
small, subtle ways. While generosity is a giving or contributing to, without expectation of
return, welcome is a taking in wherein the presence of the Other is appreciated. The
history of mental health and addictions work and settings includes far too little generosity
and welcome. This constitutes an ongoing challenge for contexts in which police powers
can be employed: how to once again be seen as generous and welcoming after a client has
lost some basic civic rights and freedoms (e.g., involuntary hospitalization, use of a
seclusion room)? Welcome and generosity can fade in the wake of efficiency measures,
bed flow pressures, staff shortages, and management by statistics; operations may
improve economically, but not ethically.
Finally, being humane means relationships are inescapably important, given that human
beings are social creatures. In health care settings, ongoing attention must be paid to
honouring and maintaining appropriate boundaries between clients and staff. This can be
especially challenging because workers utilize various methods to examine and influence
highly personal and intimate aspects of clients’ behaviours. Moreover clients may not
have many affirming and reliable relationships, often due to their illnesses’ symptoms,
which, in turn, cause family and friends to disengage. Healthcare workers may believe
compassion justifies them filling this relational void by taking on the role of friend,
family, or confidante. This erroneous belief increases the likelihood of enduring boundary
crossings or repeated boundary violations. It is not surprising that medical and nursing
books and curricula routinely discuss maintaining appropriate professional relationships
and avoiding inappropriate personal relationships, boundary crossings and boundary
violations.
Being humane can be most challenging when staff work with individuals who are
diagnosed as having a personality disorder. While the resulting behaviours seriously test
the therapeutic alliance, too often the label of “difficult client” or “difficult patient”
predetermines all activities and it becomes a self-fulfilling prophesy (Hilfiker, 1992;
Knesper, 2007; Lauro et al., 2003). In the case of those diagnosed with sociopathy, public
rhetoric has often labelled these people as “criminally insane.” Since they appear not to be
motivated by common morality, these individuals may be judged to be less than human.
When working with clients with personality disorders, healthcare workers must avoid such
moral judgments. Healthcare and health professions’ mandate is to help preserve and
restore health and well-being and alleviate suffering, irrespective of inferences about a
person’s goodness or badness (Pouncey & Lukens, 2010). With this said, though, employers
must provide effective forums and measures to alleviate a worker’s fear of a specific client
and to prevent or address dislike of or negative feelings towards certain clients (e.g.,
someone convicted on infanticide). The concept of countertransference is well-known in the
psychiatric and psychological fields. It is a professional’s response to a client’s behaviours or
statements such that the professional shifts into an inappropriate role (e.g., parent,
disciplinarian, rescuer). Psychiatry and psychology textbooks and courses teach ways to
prepare for, recognize and effectively address countertransference. Similar attention to the
psychological responses of other allied health workers is needed because their negative (or
sometimes unchecked positive) feelings and attitudes can obstruct clients’ recovery.
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
35
2.2 Being a person
Personhood or being a person is a longstanding concept in academic communities,
regardless of whether it is political science, sociology, theology or moral theory. Much
debate has been generated because of its political, legal and ethical significance: those who
legitimately qualify as “persons” must be accorded a certain level of attention, respect, and
assistance while “non-persons” can be accorded less. Various philosophers have developed
different definitions of personhood. For instance, British philosopher John Locke held that a
person was a being with a complex, psychological conscious that continued over time.
Focusing on consciousness, cognition, and affect meant that as time passed, people with
progressive dementia would become different people compared to their former selves and
when certain defining abilities faded, non-persons. Alternative definitions have been
offered; for example Rosfort and Stanghellini hold that personhood is “the identity of an
embodied self, which is embedded in a coexistence with other selves through time” (2009,
286). Grant Gillett (2002) appeals to a cumulative and evolving narrative of “my life” while
Bruce Jennings (2009) posits the “memorial person” wherein someone with advanced
dementia remains a person and connected with her earlier years through the memories of
those around her.
Farah and Heberlin (2007) present various theorists’ definitions of personhood to
demonstrate that consensus in defining such a potent concept still does not exist yet. In fact,
Tom Beauchamp (1999) recommends discontinuing efforts to refine the moral or
metaphysical attributes of personhood. He favours working on concepts that more directly
capture the lived reality of daily life. In the case of mental illnesses, clinician, family,
employers, and the general public’s interest can be focused on psychiatric diagnoses,
impairing symptoms and behaviours so much that individuals are de-personalized.
Hospital and governmental agencies’ operational and administrative practices can
depersonalize, too.
De-personalization is ethically indefensible because the individual is not recognized as
unique (Peterneliji-Taylor, 2004; Sierra et al., 2006). Instead forms and computer programs
can average or homogenize clients such that they become “another case of X” or as Flanagan
et al. note, “the medical chart.” De-personalization silences such that the individual’s unique
perspective, lived history, and hard-won expertise are not sought or are ignored. Moreover
“othering occurs in relationships between the powerful and the powerless, where
vulnerabilities are exploited and where domination and subordination prevail” (Peterneliji-
Taylor, 133). French philosopher Emmanuel Levinas’ work counters de-personalization by
morally and positively privileging the Other and his presence-to-me (Burns, 2008; Nortvedt,
2003; Standish, 2001). Simply put, if I am in the presence of someone else, I am automatically
and inarguably obliged to respond to him and respond in certain ways.
Respect is one of the most popular concepts employed to avoid de-personalization in mental
health and addictions settings. Too often, however, determining what actually demonstrates
respect in a particular situation with a particular person or group of people receives scant
attention. Instead a kind of basic civility is considered sufficient. But it is not, especially
when healthcare institutions and clinicians are expected to provide high quality treatment
and care. Preventing de-personalization of individuals with mental health and addictions
problems requires Levinas-ian active engagement with them and equal acceptance plus a
kind of existential attention and presence. Processes for information disclosure, clinicians’
truth telling, and obtaining informed consent can dominate routine interactions with clients
and their families such that little consideration is given to clinicians and staff being with
Bioethics in the 21st Century
36
clients and families. The effect is eroded personalization of clinicians and staff as well as of
clients and families. In other words, healthcare workers also become interchangeable, “all
the same,” and regrettably for those they serve, forgettable.
2.3 Being a member of a community
In mental health and addictions, considerable focus is paid to people’s rights and freedoms.
This makes sense because it is so common for others to intervene to limit individual
freedoms and obstruct the exercise of rights. Ethics related justification for such interference
typically comes from safety concerns, either for the individual herself or for others.
However a hidden, but common, concern is the existence of double standards wherein those
with suspected or diagnosed mental health problems are not permitted to do certain things
while the rest of society are. Some examples help make this point. Restrictions on sexual and
intimate activities between hospitalized clients are often excessive. The only permitted
activities are those deemed socially responsible, such as not engaging in “casual sex” or
“risking a pregnancy.” And yet a common freedom is for people to decide how sexually
active they will and will not be. Moreover women are permitted in many countries to seek
an abortion, especially before the third trimester, so it is discriminatory to summarily hold
that women with mental health concerns must always act so that pregnancy avoided. A
more ordinary example of double standards involves medication regimens. Exercising,
eating balanced meals, getting sufficient sleep, and drinking enough water contribute to
feeling and performing well. Most people do not engage in such activities consistently. In
general, people are non-compliant. Yet those who have mental health problems are expected
to be highly compliant with their medications and non-compliance is summarily often
assumed to reflect abnormally impaired thinking abilities and motivations.
The notion of citizenship moves people with mental illnesses “beyond the mere allocation or
management of financial or physical resources and implies instead a form of moral
assistance that calls for their full participation” (Perron et al. 2010; 108). Rights and freedoms
associated with citizenship are ethically very important. But what is often disregarded is
whether a person belongs within general society and within different sub-groups that are
meaningful to him. Belonging here emphasizes that the person is a valued and equal
member such that if he is absent, he is missed and he owes other members certain things just
as they owe him. He is acceptedas is,” both in terms of recognizing inescapable human
fallibility, inconsistency, strengths, aspirations, and all that has led him to be who he is here
and now. This goes beyond emphasizing the provision of quality services to those with
mental health and addiction worries. Citizenship and belonging focus on membership
within a particular network of relationships. Discrimination and marginalization can result
in the person being “not of us” and outside the community or relegated to its impoverished
and lonely margins, both of which are existentially cruel.
Another often overlooked communal factor focuses on expectations. Too often the general
public expects too much of people with mental illnesses and addictions because they do not
give adequate weight to the impact of the social determinants of health, stigma and the often
discouraging chronicity and relapse of these illnesses. On the other hand, society can be
overly paternalism and sympathetic such that too little is expected. Opportunities are not
taken to encourage and applaud people’s perseverance, kindnesses, resourcefulness, and
lived expertise. Instead focus can be merely about psychological and behavioural symptoms
of the illness and the prescribed therapies and treatments, not about the kind of person he is.
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
37
He becomes defined by the illness. This ethically troubling reductionism explains why many
eschew language such as “he is autistic…” or “schizophrenics are…” and instead speak
about “those who are living with depression” or “he has a borderline personality disorder
diagnosis or traits.”
2.4 Being a caregiver/provider
There is empirical evidence that family and friends provide significant assistance and
support for those with mental health and addiction problems. This often presents practical
challenges if applicable legislation regarding personal health information prohibits
disclosure to family members without the client’s explicit consent. In most instances, mental
illnesses are not yet curable; they are long-term health concerns. This means that family and
friends are even more important in supporting someone through expected relapses. Some of
these relapses can be highly damaging to these relationships: for instance, dementia often
results in aggressive behaviours as well as dis-inhibition (e.g., undressing, frequent
swearing, sexual remarks). Mental illnesses can result in frightening behaviours such as
verbal, psychological, and physical aggression, loss of property (e.g., if a person has
gambling problems or drives while impaired), and more. Therefore, family members may
require emotional and psychological help to deal with their fears and distress as to the
shared impact of the person’s mental illness or addiction. Family members can become
secondary “sufferers” of a particular illness or addiction.
The unique nature of psychiatrists’ and therapists’ work “[places] additional ethical
demands on practice” (Radden & Sadler, 2010, 59). Meaningful therapeutic engagement
requires entering into the inner lives of clients, examining and often times challenging
clients’ interpretations, beliefs, self-image, fears and hopes. Clinicians may learn details that
no other person in a client’s life knows. In the name of safety, healthcare workers are
permitted, often expected, to use governmental or police powers that will violate
fundamental rights and freedoms. Accordingly, professionals’ characters are very
important. Radden and Sadler identify a considerable number of characterological virtues
and offer detailed explanations as to why they are essential to the routine or everyday work
of psychiatrists and therapists. The needed traits include trustworthiness, self-knowledge,
integrity, empathy, warmth, sincerity, authenticity, unself-ing, “respect for the patient and
the healing project,” and more (Ibid, 136).
In forensic settings, a common concern is divided loyalties wherein professionals and
healthcare teams are expected to prevent the individual from harming others and violating
civil or criminal laws, and yet work with the person to build a therapeutic alliance to help
recover from the illness or disorder. When clinicians are asked to assess a person for the
court’s purpose, it is essential that the person understand that the clinician is acting for the
benefit of the court, not for her benefit. In this case, the overarching fiduciary responsibilities
of physician-client or nurse-client are suspended to a certain extent. If the psychiatrist or
therapist is unable to have a different relationship with the client in doing this assessment, it
is ethically wise for him to decline to do the assessment. The general public often does not
appreciate the inherent tensions between healthcare systems’ and clinicians’ roles and the
judicial system and lawyers’/police roles, especially when the public’s fears and biases are
exploited by the media or by political interests. Yet the value conflict between these two
systems is ethically necessary, as discussed in the sections below.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
38
3. Why science, technology, and clinical factors matter ethically?
Compared to many physical medicine interventions and programs, mental health and
addiction services and treatments face added challenges that have ethical import. The
following three issues clarify these challenges.
3.1 Our knowledge about mental illnesses and addictions
As Schmidt et al. note, “Definitions of mental illness tend to contain two aspects: a
normative element and a functional element. Normative definitions delimit abnormal
behaviour in light of what is typical, usual, or the norm…. [while] maladaptation suggests
some diminished capacity to function relative to the average” (2004; 10). Yet authoritative
statements of knowledge and fact are fewer in psychiatry and psychology than in physical
medicine. Individual experience and subjectivity still inform most psychiatric diagnoses.
Scientific uncertainty continues, as illustrated by briefly describing the evolution of
psychiatric classifications.
In 1948, the World Health Organization created the International Classification of Diseases
(ICD). In 1952, the American Psychiatric Association (APA) published the Diagnostic and
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM), a short glossary of different psychiatric
disorders based on psychoanalytic theory. This was considered a positive first step because
various disorders were identified and publicized for the practice community’s use. Yet the
DSM-I was not widely embraced because the disorders were relatively broad, the
descriptions quite brief, and many practitioners were not Freudians. Sixteen years later,
DSM-II was published, but the changes did not significantly resolve the first version’s
limitations. However DSM-III (1982) was different. It was reputedly not theoretically
grounded. Instead, its diagnostic categories were based on observed and reported
behavioural symptoms. It garnered praise from the psychiatric community because its
multiple axes of contributing problems represented the disorders’ complexity more
accurately. Moreover, the categories and diagnostic criteria had higher inter-rater reliability
(Pincus & McQueen, 2002; Schmidt et al., 2004; Wilson & Skodol, 1994). DSM-III-R (1987)
included various clarifications and corrections. While DSM-IV (1994) was much like its
predecessor, how it was created was particularly noteworthy: expert teams’ consensus about
each disorder was augmented by input from the psychiatric community at large as well as
those involved in revising the ICD. DSM-IV also was based on scientifically stronger
empirical (as opposed to anecdotal) evidence. Although DSM-IV-TR (2000) reflected no
major revisions, it did provide various clarifications.
During this period, an anti-psychiatric movement emerged in the United States. One of its
best known proponents is the psychiatrist Thomas Szasz (2009; 1976; 1961). He contends that
very few disorders are brain-based or organic. Instead, the majority of DSM-IV disorders
reflect personal preferences that do not comply with social norms. As a result, these people
experience difficulties in daily life. Those who feel that the harms of “mis-fitting societal
norms” outweigh the benefits can, if they wish, seek assistance from other people to reduce
or eliminate such difficulties. But since the maladies are not physiological, says Szasz, it
makes no sense to seek physicians’ and medical programs’ assistance.
The anti-psychiatry movement endures today. In fact, some individuals and advocacy
groups embrace the term “madness” as one way to counter what they believe is psychiatry’s
and medical institutions’ illegitimate and hegemonic power and authority (Foucault, 1988;
Wilson & Beresford, 2002).
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
39
The epistemic process of typological knowledge creation is often called nosology, or medical
classification/categorization. Nosology continues to be an issue in mental health and
addictions work because the questions still remain: “What makes something a mental [or
addictive] disorder? and, Does this something form a category?” (Schmidt et al.; 11). In 2012
or 2013, the APA will publish the DSM-V. It will include a new framework or approach:
dimensions, rather than mainly categories. There will be two general kinds of dimensions.
First, clinicians’ diagnoses will take into account the severity of symptoms, rather than
mainly their presence or absence. Second, there will be “cross-cutting” symptoms, such as
anxiety and suicidality, which occur in many illnesses. As a result, some disorders are
expected to be de-listed and some new ones listed. In other words, some people will no
longer have a psychiatric diagnosis, some people’s diagnoses will be refined, and some will
be newly diagnosable. Professional debate about the advantages and disadvantages of this
new approach has been pronounced (Banzato, 2004; Collier, 2010; Helzer et al., 2007;
Kraemer, 2007).
A similar debate is in progress in addiction treatment and care. Is an addiction to alcohol,
tobacco, illegal drugs, or prescription drugs some type of disease, or a personal choice, or
something else? The most popular alternative to the disease paradigm considers addictions
to be more complex: they are the combined result of biological, psychological, and
sociological factors. Researchers and practitioners differ as to which paradigm they believe
is most accurate. But the ethical implications of this difference are real. People who develop
cancer, psoriasis, or glaucoma are generally not considered ethically culpable for the loss of
important abilities or for requiring publicly funded health services. If alcoholism is deemed
to be a disease, then the alcohol dependent person may not be blamed for “having it.” This
is a welcome correction to the traditional moral condemnation of people with drinking
problems. If responsibility follows causation, then a biopsychosocial explanation presumes
something different. People’s physiology, psychology, and social environment are
presumed to be self-controllable and modifiable, albeit not totally. They are also presumed
to be modified by other peoples actions and inactions. Accordingly, if there are negative
consequences, culpability for what could have been changed must be shared, rather than
resting solely with the individual. The locus of responsibility relative to having an addiction
matters ethically because it connects with the ethical concept of fairness. This concept of
fairness, and more specifically equality and equity, helps determine the amount of publicly
funded versus privately funded services individuals with an addiction problem should be
able to access.
3.2 Treatment and care
Those who are not psychiatrists, psychologists, or addictions therapists may not realize how
very diverse available treatments and therapies are. For instance, there are more than two
hundred psychotherapies, clustered, for example, as cognitive behaviour therapy, family
therapy, mindfulness, art therapy, psychoanalysis and more. This increases the uncertainty
and complexity of finding the therapy that will benefit a particular person most or at least
sufficiently. In the case of psychopharmacological treatments, they have had a checkered
history. In the 1950s, new medications were hoped to provide effective and sustainable relief
of illnesses’ disabling symptoms... a promising change from the seeming unending-ness of
psychotherapeutic counselling and from the irreversibility and extreme invasiveness of
psychosurgeries. In addition to the physiochemical benefits, medications could also be
Bioethics in the 21st Century
40
administered without a client’s cooperation or consent. This was not possible for
psychotherapies. They could not be beneficial if the person was not in the appropriate stage
of change and was not willingly engaged, irrespective of whether she or a substitute
decision maker had consented.
The first generation of antipsychotic medications or “typicals” unfortunately caused too
many people very serious and irreversible side effects such as tardive dyskinesia. The next
generation of antipsychotic medications, the “atypicals,” were expected to cause fewer side
effects. While second generation drugs have helped many people, the long-term effects are
discouragingly negative. For instance, individuals diagnosed with schizophrenia may
develop diabetes due to some of these medications (Amiel et al., 2008; Lowe & Lubos, 2008;
Muench & Hamer, 2010). Yet it takes years and millions of dollars to develop a new
pharmacological treatment that can offer meaningful improvements, not just in terms of
biochemical or physiological measures, but in terms of quality of life measures as well. The
negative effects of medications, such as significant weight gain, slowed thinking, and
sluggishness, help explain in part why people discontinue using them, only to find that they
relapse into a serious state that may require emergency or involuntary hospitalization.
From the outset, funding of research of mental illnesses and addictions has been
disproportionately low compared to funding of research of physical illnesses. In 2004-2005,
for example, the Canadian Institute of Health Research devoted 7.5% of its $700 million
budget to mental health and addiction (Senate Standing Committee, 2008). Yet
approximately 20% of Canadians have a mental health problem during their lives. In the
same year, the U.K. spent 6% of its £ 950 million governmental health research funds on
mental health (Kingdon & Nicholl, 2006). In 2011, the American National Institutes of
Health will allocate only 4% of its budget to the National Institute of Mental Health
(National Institutes of Health, 2010). Consequently, available treatments and therapies are
often less reliable and less specific than those for various medical problems. Moreover, more
research funds are spent on pharmacological interventions compared to psychotherapeutic
or alternative interventions, in part because the pharmaceutical industry spends almost as
much as governments on healthcare research (World Health Organization, 2004). This
means that new or more effective psychotherapies are less likely to be developed and that a
proportion of research funds are used for economic purposes, namely improving a
medication’s competitive marketability and profitability.
3.3 Daily practice models
Different clinics and hospitals offer markedly different addiction and mental health
treatments and programs (Finney & Moos, 2006; Futterman et al., 2004). For instance, one
addictions program’s work may be guided by harm reduction principles. Familiar examples
of a harm reduction approach are safe injection sites and methadone maintenance programs
for ex-heroin users. Another program’s work, however, may be guided by an abstinence
model of treatment. Furthermore, what counts as harm reduction can differ considerably
among clinicians (Miller et al., 2008). They may calculate the benefits and harms of a
particular activity differently; for instance, providing information about different settings
for alcohol consumption and their relative risks. Just as importantly, though, clinicians’
opinions may differ regarding the morality of said activity. For example, accepting a client’s
decision to begin taking taxis during weekend drinking binges as harm reduction may seem
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
41
to condone the client’s wilful drunkenness. Some clinicians believe this clearly violates their
professional ethos; others do not (Miller; 2008).
Models of care for mental health settings are also diverse: for instance, strengths-based,
empowerment-focused, recovery, trauma-informed, custodial, rehabilitative, and sanctuary.
As a result, how clients are seen and engaged by clinicians and teams will vary. A strengths-
based approach, not surprisingly, attends to clients’ positive abilities to deal with and
improve their health and circumstances. An empowerment approach emphasizes correcting
historic and current power imbalances---typically profound imbalances---between people
with a mental health or addiction problem and professional caregivers and their institutions
or between these same people and society at large. The ethical concepts of agency, self-
determination, voice, and liberation resonate with empowerment. A recovery approach
focuses on a person’s valuations, aspirations, interpretations, and pace and it adopts “the
long-view” wherein recovery is acknowledged to be an ongoing and unfolding journey. As
shown in Gagne et al. (2007) and Ontken et al. (2007) in relation to recovery, focal ethical
values are narrative integrity, resilience, commitment, and fallibility.
It is ethically important to identify and understand the practice model relevant to a
particular treatment situation because inherent ethical values can vary. In terms of a specific
program’s model of care, an ethics-related goal should be coherence among the model’s
foundational values, staff-client interactions, and the kinds of therapies and care offered.
However, models can become out-dated as more is learned about what helps clients
maintain and regain important activities and relationships, as other programs and systems
change, and as certainty increases regarding what qualifies as mental illnesses and effective
interventions.
Psychiatry, psychology, and case management qualify as “forensic” when they are applied
to and used in our justice system. These include scientific and theoretical analyses of
criminal behaviour, clinical and institutional/communal efforts to prevent or deter law-
violating behaviour, risk assessments and diagnoses for judicial proceedings, and police
psychology. Ethically critical to this work is separating understanding why a person
behaved in a certain way---in terms of “nature and nurture”---and morally judging him or
her. Conflating nature and nurture or conflating biological processes and socializing
processes typify anti-psychiatry’s worries.
4. Why law and regulations matter ethically
It is sometimes said that mental health and addictions services and settings are dictated by
laws and legal institutions, be they the courts, legislatures, regulatory agencies, prisons and
jails, or the police. A common concern is that society uses its various powers for its collective
interests to the detriment of individual or minority interests. This concern is historically
accurate in many countries in terms of how they have responded to individuals with mental
health or addiction problems. Too often, these responses were dictated by social norms for
acceptable behaviours and appearances. If the behaviours or appearances violated these
norms and rules, common responses were punishment, social expulsion, controlled
quarantine, surgical interventions, and even death. However, there were often
compassionate individuals and religious-based groups that countered societal edicts by
offering agapic assistance and places of sanctuary to people seen as innocent sufferers of
cravings or disordered thinking.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
42
4.1 Rights and duties regarding decision making and consent
Personal decision-making typically is one of the first ethical concerns in healthcare settings
or issues, in large part due to the courts and legislatures. Today, healthcare involves many
therapies and procedures, even in economically disadvantaged or developing nations. Most
medical and nursing training programs now include seminars and discussions about clients’
legally-protected rights to start, modify, or discontinue any intervention or service and the
ensuing duties of professionals to honour such decisions. Valid consent---which authorizes a
professional to act---is obtained when the person is informed about the particular
intervention’s benefits, risks, and burdens compared to other options, has the requisite
capacity to make this decision, and is not being pressured, coerced or manipulated to
decide.
These three components of the consent process can be obstructed or compromised by the
nature or symptoms of mental illnesses and addictions. First, being informed. Healthcare
workers frequently overlook this component when clients decline recommended treatments.
This is why the consent process is shared: if a treatment is declined, the reason may be that
personally irrelevant, non-meaningful, or unintelligible information has been
unintentionally provided. Timely disclosure and intelligible explanations are among
clinicians’ routine duties. As per the clinical section above, our understanding of the nature
and causes of mental health and addiction problems is relatively limited, though it is
increasing. Accurate diagnoses can take considerable time and prognoses may be quite
uncertain. Available therapies and treatments may be scientifically promising, but still lack
sufficient high quality research studies to be able to provide highly reliable and nuanced
details to patients. Consequently, clinicians can find it difficult to provide clients with
individualized and useful information about their illness, prognoses, and personally
beneficial treatments.
The second component of a valid consent process is having “enough” mental capacity to
decide. When clients decline treatments, this component can garner disproportionately more
attention from clinicians than the other two components. Governmental legislation often
stipulates specific criteria that, if not met, mean the person lacks the legally required abilities
to make his or her own health-related decisions. Two criteria often comprise legislated
standards: (1) is the person able to understand the information, and (2) is he able to
appreciate the consequences of having versus not having the intervention. These abilities
can be undermined by mental illness or addiction. But no set of assessment questions or
exercises qualifies yet as the validated set for accurate assessments. Consequently, different
clinicians may assess a person differently in terms of having or not having capacity for a
particular decision. Importantly, however, legislation and court rulings typically hold that
someone who has a mental health or addiction problem can still have the needed capacity to
consent to or decline a recommended therapy. In other words, depression, mania, paranoia,
or hallucinations do not, in and of themselves, void the needed abilities to make treatment
or other health-related decisions.
The third component is voluntary-ness. Certain therapies and care can involve social,
environmental, and bodily control (e.g., group counselling, behaviour modification,
protective devices). Coercion therefore is an ongoing possibility. Moreover, some mental
health problems can result in a lack of self-control (i.e., mania, dis-inhibition) or in
heightened fears (e.g., paranoid schizophrenia, having a history of trauma or abuse). This
means that the invasiveness, demanding-ness or restrictive-ness of certain treatments may
be very unwelcome, even though they can benefit the person in other ways. Furthermore,
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
43
despite an appropriate substitute decision maker consenting to treatment on behalf of
someone lacking capacity, it will still be traumatic and damaging to the therapeutic alliance
whenever a treatment is administered against the person’s will (e.g., with Security staff
present, by forced injection, by forced application of a protective device to prevent self-
injury). Accordingly, before deciding whether an intervention fits with the person’s prior
expressed wishes and best interests, a substitute decision maker must understand not just
the type of treatment recommended, but also how it will be administered and what will be
the individual’s likely experience of “being treated.”
4.2 Rights and duties regarding privacy and confidentiality
Governmental legislation about the collection, use, and sharing of personally identifiable
health-related information is common today. These acts, statutes and regulations protect
citizens’ right to privacy regarding their health, minds, bodies, and related activities by
delineating professionals’ and organizations’ duties to keep such information as confidential
as possible and yet use it effectively and efficiently. To preserve clients’ and families’ trust,
limits to confidentiality and any legally required duties to report should be discussed as
early as possible by healthcare workers. Later in this chapter, stigma and discrimination will
be discussed in detail but suffice it to say that the need to protect mental health and
addictions related information is especially important. The consequences of a person’s
employer and insurer learning that he or she has or has had a mental health or addiction
problem can be significant and irreversible. This need to protect this information, however,
can unintentionally frustrate, even damage, professionals’ interactions and relationships
with patients’ families.
While many healthcare organizations include family-centeredness among their corporate
values, this is more complex in mental health and addictions settings because family may
have knowingly or more often, unknowingly, contributed to the person’s poor health. Too
often, family members emotionally, psychologically, and/or physically abuse one another.
Yet research and testimonials show that people recover and sustain a good quality of life
because of familial support. More strongly put, family support can be a protective factor
(Cleveland et al. 2010; Ivanova & Israel, 2006; Korol 2008; Piko & Kovacs, 2010). Negotiating
this quandary requires healthcare workers to have strong communication, interactive and
assessment skills. Clinicians and healthcare organizations must be proactive in instituting
practices to safeguard clients’ privacy and to balance the competing interests of clients and
their families without losing their trust or compromising their relationships further.
4.3 Rights and duties regarding safety
The political philosophy concept of parens patriae means that a legitimate government serves
much like a patriarchal parent or father to its citizens. It is thus responsible for their general
well-being and safety, and at times must make decisions that contravene their immediate
wishes. A citizen may be in danger of being harmed such that those formally delegated
powers to fulfill the government’s duty (i.e., such as police and medical professionals) are
expected to intervene on his behalf. So too if the citizen is harming or posing a serious threat
to another innocent citizen. Governmental representatives may act unilaterally to stop or
prevent such harm, especially if the potential victims may lack the abilities or resources to
protect themselves.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
44
Mental illnesses and addictions can result in serious risks to the individual: suicide, self-
neglect (e.g., poor hygiene), self-harm (e.g., cutting, pulling out hair, repetitive scratching).
Governmental powers to hospitalize, restrain, seclude, or treat against a person’s wishes,
when her behaviours are due to mental illness, are often legally set out in mental health
legislation. The same legislation will specify who is legally obligated to forcibly act against
the person’s wishes when other people could be harmed or at risk of harm by her due to the
mental health problem. If there is no actual or suspected mental health problem, then the
individual would be dealt with according to applicable civil or criminal laws. Questions
about the kind (physical only or psychological too?), the probability, the urgency or
imminence (within the next few days or longer?), the seriousness or significance (life-
threatening, disabling and/or dignity-threatening?) arise when such legislation is written or
revised. While mental health legislation in most jurisdictions agrees that governmental
intervention is warranted when death or serious physical harm is likely, there is
disagreement as to whether other harms should be unilaterally and forcibly prevented.
Similar questions arise in healthcare settings when healthcare workers, family members and
the police try to decide whether to invoke their government-delegated powers.
Governmental legislation should try to strike a balance between the safety of the individual
and others and the magnitude and duration of restrictions imposed upon the individual.
Which rights and freedoms enjoyed by other citizens will she lose and for how long? What
are the least invasive and limiting options? These questions probe whether the response to
her harmful behaviour focuses on maintaining safety or on punishing undesirable
behaviours.
4.4 Institutional mechanisms
Punishment is a worry for mental health facilities because their competing goals include
keeping individual clients safe and keeping others safe. There are four theories of
punishment: retributive theory, deterrence theory, rehabilitative theory, and restorative
theory. The last three of these theories happen to resonate with various clinical paradigms.
Such coherence can unintentionally link punishment with clinical interventions. It is crucial
for clinicians and teams to focus on the behaviours and decisions that relate to the health
problem for which the client is seeking therapeutic help. Interventions and accompanying
interactions must not be punitive.
A recent judicial trend is the creation of “mental health courts” and “drug treatment courts.”
Their objective is to divert those who have been found guilty of violating certain laws, albeit
as non-violent crimes, away from prisons and jails. The mitigating factor in this sentencing
is that these people broke a particular law because of a mental illness or addiction. The fact
that someone has a mental health or addiction problem does not mean that all his or her
actions and choices are determined by the problem. To qualify for “medical diversion,” the
law-breaking actions have to be the result of the health problem; for instance, the person’s
judgment was impaired because he or she was intoxicated or responding to paranoid
thoughts or to threatening internal voices. Accordingly, a judge decides whether the person
should be diverted to an appropriate health facility to receive treatment and care for the
mental health or addiction problem. Historically, judicial systems have provided no or
minimal mental health and addictions treatment because punishment and control were the
priorities and funding was inadequate. Focused, integrated, and sustained treatment in
hospitals’ programs is expected to help these individuals return to the community more
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
45
quickly and not re-offend. Those who are directed to mental health and drug treatment
courts usually can choose to have their cases heard in “regular court” with the possibility
that if found guilty, jail, prison or probation is next. However it has been found that those
who agree to be diverted into the health system may be under its auspices longer than if
they had been in jail or prison. It can seem that diversion is harsher and thus less fair. This
harkens back to the lack of highly effective, of easily sustained therapies or of adequate
community services to justify a conditional discharge.
Therapeutic jurisprudence is a concept first coined by David Wexler, a professor of law and
psychology, in a 1987 NIH conference paper (Corvette, 2000). He held that judicial systems
and processes can be beneficial or harmful to those who break civil or criminal laws. Being
held responsible, treated fairly, assisted in exercising rights to a fair hearing as well as others
having duties to follow the impartial rule of law are considered to be psychologically and
existentially affirmative of the individual as an equal member of the community. Moreover,
the judicial system can help mediate injustices experienced in the public realm: “Therapeutic
jurisprudence is normative. It suggests that to the extent possible, consonant with due
process and justice values and goals, undesirable effects should be avoided or minimized
and positive effects should be maximized” (Ibid, 103). Therapeutic jurisprudence fits with
mental health courts and drug treatment courts to a degree. These court settings bring
together employees of two major societal endeavours: the judiciary and healthcare.
Nevertheless, caution is warranted. Various legal scholars and academics worry that these
employees’ roles will illegitimately merge such that role boundaries are crossed. In other
words, the judicial employees will weigh in too far---beyond their knowledge and training--
-into the work of the healthcare employees and vice versa (Dickie, 2008; Moore, 2007; Nolan,
2003). Furthermore, benefits vary between women and men. This, in turn, warrants
increased study as to different stakeholders’ views about the meaning as well as the effects
of these courts and their processes (Hunt et al., 2007; Moore, 2007; Shaffer et al., 2009).
Similar debates have arisen when legislatures have considered amending existing mental
health laws to include community treatment orders. These orders, often called involuntary
community treatment, are meant to organize a mixed set of supportive community services
so that a person can leave the hospital and live safely in the community as a less restrictive
option. If, however, the community providers and agencies do not fulfill their
responsibilities and it is possible that the person will become unsafe as a result, then he can
be forcibly re-hospitalized forthwith. At issue is how to ethically evaluate this option: solely
on probable consequences (e.g., fewer urgent hospitalizations, shorter hospitalizations)? At
present, not enough is known as to why community treatment orders are associated with
certain positive outcomes. Are they due to the ongoing availability of comprehensive
supports or is it due to the ever-present threat of the client being re-hospitalized against his
will? (Burns & Dawson, 2009; Hunt et al., 2005).
Mental health and addictions settings encounter another challenge in the guise of advance
directives. Advance directives have been discussed for years in the context of physical, acute
care medicine. Medical advance directives permit people to designate who will be their
healthcare decision proxy and/or to provide guidelines for subsequent decisions when they
no longer have the capacity to decide on their own behalf. Empirical evidence shows that
psychiatric advance directives, or “crisis cards” in the U.K., reduce the frequency and length
of emergency hospitalizations. They also increase clinician-client trust (Srebnik & Russo,
2008; Sutherby et al., 1999). Yet discussions about psychiatric advanced directives’
usefulness often ignore a critical detail: can directives be invoked before persons satisfy
Bioethics in the 21st Century
46
legislated criteria to be deemed incapable? Or can they be invoked only after they are
assessed as lacking capacity? The “after” scenario is not too ethically or legally controversial
because the directive actually constitutes client participation in the care plan and establishes
relevant “prior expressed wishes” (Bogdanoski, 2009; Srebnik et al., 2005; Swanson et al.,
2006). Dubbed “a Ulysses contract” after the Greek fable about Ulysses, the “before”
scenario is definitely controversial. If there are legislated standards and court rulings to
protect decision-making by capable citizens, then it could prove difficult, perhaps legally
impossible, for citizens to waive their right to such decisional protection.
5. Why organizational context matters ethically
In the early decades of bioethics inquiry, academic and professional scrutiny and debate
centred on the work of researchers using human subjects and “bedside” or “front line”
practitioners. The issue that expanded this focus to include administrators, management
and executives, and Board members was, I believe, the galloping costs of healthcare services
that were not adequately reimbursed by governmental and private insurance plans. In the
United States, Medicare’s and Medicaid’s decision in the 1980s to shift from reimbursing as
per diagnostic Related Diagnostic Groups and to capitated managed care costs confirmed
the immense impact of management on client-professional relationships. Moreover,
increasing annual deficits made the business of healthcare an issue for everyone, from
patients, practitioners, hospitals, commercial employers to governmental health ministers.
All economically developed nations now experience demand exceeding healthcare supply,
despite increasing budgets. Continued technological advances are typically more costly and
citizens’ confidence that “new” and “more” produces better health outcomes is often short-
lived.
An “organization” will herein be defined as a designated group of specially trained or
skilled people working towards a shared goal or purpose. As such, a rural adolescent drug
counselling office consisting of three addictions workers and an office administrator
constitutes an organization, as does each discrete unit within a psychiatric hospital, as does
the hospital as a whole. Organizational considerations are not the concern or responsibility
of only executive management; they are the responsibility of virtually all staff members.
5.1 Organizational factors
Organizational considerations in healthcare fall into four general categories, each of which
warrants a brief explanation as to its relevance for ethical practice in mental health and
addictions settings. One category is the ethics of the organization’s mission or mandate. The
purpose of an organization, irrespective of whether it has been formally and explicitly
described or it is implicit in its regular activities, establishes to whom the organization is
responsible and accountable and for what… and to whom it is not responsible. More simply
put, a mandate sets out the groups of people to whom the organization must respond with
“Yes, we can help you” and to whom it can respond legitimately with “You will have to
look elsewhere for assistance.” In contemporary healthcare, healthcare organizations have
often developed a set of values to guide how their mission and strategic goals are
accomplished. A point in this chapter’s introduction bears repeating here: some values are
intrinsically ethical (e.g., being trustworthy, relieving suffering). Other values may be
instrumentally ethical (i.e., financial stewardship so as to maximize number of clients
served).
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
47
A second category is the ethics of how a healthcare organization is governed: what should
be the guiding operational standards and according to whom? Governance will be both
internal and external. Examples of external governance include accreditation standards,
employment and occupational health regulations, applicable government legislation,
funding regulations, professional Colleges’ codes of practice, and the organization’s Board
of Trustees/Directors. Examples of internal governance include negotiated labour contracts,
a code of employee conduct, quality-safety committee, any document that details patient
rights as well as the largest and most endemic “repository” of internal governance, written
policies and procedures.
Another general organizational ethics category for healthcare settings is the ethics of
resource acquisition, allocation, and disposal. Here, “resources” applies not just to money,
but also to staff, beds, counselling sessions, equipment, physical space, and professionals’
time. How resources are obtained is ethically important, as evidenced by debates about
seeking funds from pharmaceutical and gaming corporations or about recruiting nurses and
professionals from countries sorely lacking in qualified personnel. Allocation of resources,
as mentioned earlier, is the most well known organizational ethics issue in health care: how
to allocate resources fairly, even if there is just “soft” scarcity, is challenging and often is
informed only by an implicit utilitarian calculus. Prioritizing access to and provision of in-
patient or out-patient services occurs routinely and includes wide-ranging decisions such as
which medications to include or exclude from a hospital formulary, how to respond to “VIP
requests” for access, and how many times a hospitalized client or his substitute decision
maker can decline a community bed without consequence. Resource “disposal” first came to
attention vis-à-vis discussions about the environmental impact of what was being discarded
by tertiary, acute care hospitals. Yet closing or reducing services can mean staff layoffs and
reduced hours. Refreshing all computer hardware can mean deciding whether to donate the
replaced computers to a remote school or a community centre serving people living with
addictions problems. “Disposal” decisions involve ethics-related values such as who will be
harmed versus benefited, who should help identify alternatives and applicable rationales,
and who is responsible for making the final decision.
The last category is the ethics of an organization’s culture and climate. Understanding what
culture and climate are and their impact has been a favoured topic in business ethics and
business literature for some time. Culture is reflected in what is considered acceptable
versus unacceptable behaviour and interactions. It is so ingrained and presumed to be
“right” that it does not need to be written anywhere. Culture will include norms for how
hard staff should work, what counts as humour, what questions can and cannot be asked
out loud, and how much is decided by committees versus individuals. Climate is a
metaphoric word to capture the organization’s current mood: is it optimistic, such that
trying something new without administrative permission is a safe thing to do? Or is it
suspicious, such that “not rocking the boat” is well advised? Or is it celebratory such that
being a little less productive for awhile is acceptable?
In virtually all ethics related questions involving clients, organizational considerations will
implicitly or explicitly impact their treatment, care, and interactions with co-clients, staff,
family members, and outside parties. In some instances, staff responses will be ethically
weaker or stronger because of these considerations. Some everyday examples include
practices and policies about smoking restrictions, searching clients’ belongings, hospitalized
clients’ intimate and sexual behaviours, clients’ use of illegal substances during the therapy
period, staff responses when clients may be driving impaired, staff obligations or lack
Bioethics in the 21st Century
48
thereof if a pregnant client uses illegal substances, and so on. Policies and practices must
balance competing, often conflicting, interests and responsibilities. As noted by Winkler
(2005), depending on how policies are developed and implemented, they can minimize the
power and resource imbalances among staff as well as between clients and staff. Or they can
exacerbate them. As memorably explained in Skorpen et al.’s (2008) article about smoking
rooms in a psychiatric facility, clients can try to find ways to regain power and equal status.
On a separate but related point, safety initiatives will be ethically grounded. However,
safety can become the “sun” that blocks out all other considerations, or “a trump card” that
silences all other interests and voices. Depending on a healthcare facility’s culture and
climate, it may be politically unwise to suggest that safety measures are causing more
burdens and disadvantages than anticipated.
Busy clinics and hospitals may operate unintentionally in ways that traumatize or re-
traumatize clients. Many people who develop a mental health or addiction problem have
experienced serious trauma, be it physical, emotional, and/or psychological abuse. If a
medical office or health clinic’s practices are impersonal, coercive, or disrespectful, the
person may find them even more distressful and stressful because her past experiences of
being silenced, pressured, or shamed are remembered and reinforced. Moreover programs
and units may operate with such allegiance to “the rules” that professional judgement and
integrity fade. Having integrity requires some modicum of inner struggle, according to
scholar Stephen Carter (1996). In other words, having integrity is praiseworthy because it is
hard to achieve. Therefore if healthcare workers’ motives for acting as they do come from
“following the rules,” then they might be commended as being capable rule followers, but
this is divorced from being professional or having integrity. As noted in the introduction,
reasons for acting may not be based on ethics-related values, but instead on other
considerations such as self-interest, convenience, power, or fatigue.
5.2 Forensic programs and services
The ethical challenges and complexities of forensic healthcare programs and settings are
numerous and significant, as reflected throughout this chapter. In the case of forensic
services, care is needed to avoid unintentional “creep” of the police and prison system into
the therapeutic system. Language is an obvious marker of such ingress: clients or patients
have privileges that they can lose, regain, and exercise. Yet the word “privileges” evokes
imperialism and parentalism because privileges are granted by one party to another. If an
empowering or strengths-based approach is adopted instead, clinicians could refer to a
client’s “responsibilities” or “actions” as set out in the court or review board order. There
would be consequences, positive and negative, if she fulfills or does not fulfill her
responsibilities, rather than the moralizing or infant-alizing rhetoric of “consequences to
reward good behaviour.” To help balance the power relations more equitably, her clinical
team and the program management would also have various responsibilities to fulfill.
Another example is contraband, wherein clients are prohibited from having certain
qualifying items with them in the hospital. But “contraband” is a familiar police and drug
enforcement word related to smuggling. It does not belong in a healing environment (recall
that the person was diverted from the prison or jail system). Alternative wording could be
“unsafe items” or “prohibited items,” which are accurate descriptions but far less polarizing.
Ethics texts written for psychologists and psychiatrists usually include a chapter on ethically
defensible ways to formally assess a person for court such that the person does not
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
49
mistakenly presume the clinician has her best interests in mind. As noted above, health
workers may struggle to maintain the appropriate balance between offering therapy and
following a court’s legitimate demands. It is essential for programs to proactively and
openly examine their routine practices. These forums will help support workers to deal with
the to-be-expected moral distress of meeting competing commitments (Austin, 2001; Morse,
2008; Pouncey & Lukens, 2010). Moreover understanding clients’ actual experiences of these
situations, rather than just working from assumptions, is important because the significant
power differential between clinician and client can progressively erode professional
commitments.
6. Why systemic factors matter ethically
Since moving from a large tertiary, acute care hospital to working at a large mental health
and addictions hospital, systemic factors have figured prominently in my ethical analyses
and recommendations. Like Sokol, I gradually became aware of these factors’ impact on the
daily lives of clients, families, and healthcare workers alike as I listened to more and more
personal stories: someone who can only afford substandard housing and worries bedbugs
will soon infiltrate their belongings, a recreational therapist frustrated that clients are not
welcome at a community gym, and rural parents whose employer-paid insurance plan caps
psychotherapy for their behaviourally aggressive child at ten sessions per year. Systemic
factors are implicit in a community or society’s ongoing activities that occur just outside the
walls of a private practice, clinic, or hospital. Three kinds of factors are particularly relevant
to defensibly determining normative responses or, in other words, “what should happen.”
Moreover these factors ground any health and healthcare decision in the reality of a
particular society or community. Sidestepping these factors in ethics-related analyses can
result in ineffective responses or assigning responsibilities disproportionately.
6.1 Stigma
The first ethically weighty factor is stigma. There are many definitions of stigma, but Jo
Phelan and Bruce Link (2001) offer a nuanced characterization. They suggest that it has four
components, which appropriately captures its complexity: (1) human differences are
identified and labelled, (2) these differences are linked to negative qualities, (3) those who
are different become “Them” as separate from “Us”, and (4) the person’s or group’s social
status declines and unfair discrimination occurs. Those who make up society’s majority,
captive to the seeming truth of “bell curve statistics,” commonly presume that what is
common constitutes what is “normal” and what is uncommon constitutes what is not just
rare, but also what is morally abnormal. As described by historical accounts of societies’
treatment of those whose thinking was unusual, this treatment has traditionally been fear-
based and repressive. Furthermore, if people’s thoughts were accompanied by behaviours
and appearances that violated social etiquette and norms, the collective responses included
dismissive marginalization, controlled quarantine, or forced treatment. Historically, mainly
charitable or faith-based institutions endeavoured to care for and about people with mental
illnesses until the past fifty years or so in North America and Europe. Yet stigma remains a
contemporary problem. For example, based on its 2006 Senate report on mental illnesses and
addictions and available services, Out of the Shadows at Last, Canada’s Mental Health
Commission launched “Opening Minds,” a ten-year anti-stigma/anti-discrimination
initiative.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
50
Social or communal stigmatization and discrimination----related to ethics concepts of de-
humanization and injustice----help explain why most people are initially reluctant to seek
psychiatric and psychological testing because of the enduring harms of being labelled as
having a mental health or addictions problem. Families, too, delay seeking information and
help from clinicians and programs, often relying primarily on the Internet’s anonymity and
non-judgemental-ness. Keeping health problems secret limits access as well as limits offers
of needed, physical, psychological, relational, educational, and economic support. Yet
stigma and discrimination go beyond the general public’s response to those living with a
mental health or addiction problem. Studies have also revealed that many mental health and
addictions workers unconsciously and consciously stigmatize and discriminate against their
own clients despite their day-to-day interactions with them (Flanagan et al., 2009; Liggins &
Hatcher, 2005; Ross, 2009; Schulze, 2007). There is also evidence that mental health and
addiction workers themselves are stigmatized by working in this field of healthcare
(Gouthro, 2010; Halter, 2008; Stuhlmiller, 2005).
Discrimination of individuals with mental health and addictions problems can be more
subtle, but can be just as unfair. It is important to examine whether double standards are
being presumed or relied upon. Clinicians and teams may want to restrict client activities
that would be permitted in general society. For example, a residential program may decide
to permit residents to engage in consensual, non-exploitative intimate behaviours in their
private rooms, but expect these behaviours to reflect “highly responsible” or “meaningful”
activity. Or the program may have a search policy that presumes residents to be more
dangerous and more devious than has been actually experienced. Media stories and
mainstream television and movie companies sensationalize rare disorders and behaviours
as well as behaviours that result in criminal charges or convictions. For instance, programs
and healthcare workers’ attention can be disproportionately directed to people’s use of
illegal drugs compared to their tobacco and alcohol use. Yet smoking and drinking alcohol
cause more death and serious co-morbidities than marijuana, or even heroin.
Language is slow to change, too. Someone in treatment for, say, cocaine addiction is said to
“test dirty” on a urine drug screen (Radcliffe & Stevens, 2008; Rose et al., 2005). Urine
screens for people with diabetes, however, are described as “testing positive” or “negative.”.
As “addicts,” “schizophrenics” or “sex offenders,” people are reduced to a particular illness
or behavioural category. There has been a move within the addictions field to talk about
substance dependence, misuse, and abuse… rather than always about addictions. Hofman et
al’s 2003 study of inner city women who were IV-drug users and used outreach health
services far less than male IV-drug users in the same area revealed the women’s ongoing
efforts to fulfill familial and communal responsibilities plus retain a sense of respectability.
The criticism of healthcare workers’ continued use of the demeaning and paternalistic terms
“compliance” and “non-compliance” is about stigma as well (Acosta et al., 2009; Bissella et
al., 2004; Proulx et al., 2007; Stewart & DeMarco, 2010). Because of stigma, discrimination,
negative side effects, and human nature, it should not surprise us that people do not follow
prescribed regimens at the high level of “compliance” needed. As noted by a systems and
client advocate, those receiving health services do not set a personal goal of “being more
compliant” with their treatment (Jennifer Chambers, 2010; personal communications).
Instead, they set more meaningful goals such as getting sustainable employment, feeling
well enough to help with a son’s homework, or having more faith in one’s hard-won
wisdom.
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
51
6.2 Social determinants of health
Being healthy does not rely solely on physiology, genetics, and lifestyle choices. Social and
cultural factors also have significant impact (Lauder et al., 2007). While the World Health
Organization (2003) identifies several social determinants, three are of particular ethical
import for mental health and addictions contexts: housing, unemployment and poverty, and
social isolation. The percentage of people who are homeless and have a mental illness, while
difficult to accurately determine, is estimated to range from 20% to up to 50% in various
studies of Canadian, U.K. and American cities (Hwang, 2001; Meltzer, 2008; National
Coalition for the Homeless, 2009; Neale, 2008; Senate Standing Committee, 2006). The
relationship between unstable and inadequate housing and mental illness and addictions is
considered to be bi-directional. In other words, sub-standard housing contributes to onset or
relapse just as mental illness and addictions contribute to loss of adequate and reliable
housing. Reflective of continued discrimination, “NIMBY” or “not in my back yard” is a
common community response, opposing governmental or private agency housing initiatives
for people with persistent health concerns, such as mental illnesses and addictions.
People with mental health and addictions problems are at increased risk of living in poverty
(Canadian Mental Health Association, 2007; Hudson, 2005; Wilton, 2004). Schizophrenia, for
instance, usually manifests in late adolescence or young adulthood, which means
educational efforts are disrupted. Lack of post-secondary education usually results in being
less competitive in the job market. Stigma means that finding suitable employment is more
difficult---even though many countries have legislation prohibiting discrimination based on
health conditions---and once employed, people must often be diligent to keep their mental
health or addictions history secret. Governments may offer financial assistance to those
unable to work due to a physical or mental disability, but the amount of support typically
provides for a low standard of living.
Psychiatric hospitals were once known as “asylums” because they were considered safe
havens from the uncertainties and rigors of daily life. But too many became immense
institutions of sturdy walls and high fences in which people with mental health problems
lived out their lives separated from the community. Exclusion is anathema to human health
and well-being. Moreover, some mental illnesses, such as autism, paranoia, and personality
disorders, involve reduced abilities to understand or trust other people and this, in turn,
undermines relationship-building. Add public prejudice and the consequences for many
people with mental health problems are isolation and marginalization (Baum et al., 2010;
Elisha et al., 2006; Morgan et al., 2008 and 2007; Smith & Hirdes 2009).
6.3 Health and social systems writ large
The third systemic factor that is ethically noteworthy is our social and health systems. Three
issues help illustrate the tangible impact of these systems on the therapies available and the
recovery realized. First, ethically worrisome conflicts of interest can exist. When a
government sells alcohol and operates gambling venues (e.g., casinos, lotteries), this runs
counter to its public health mandate (Andresen, 2006; Livingstone & Adams, 2011; Walker &
Jackson; 2011). Even if a government only regulates commercial sales of these items and
activities, their coffers receive immense sums of money from luxury taxes on alcohol,
gambling, and cigarettes. As evidenced by the “Big Tobacco Settlement” in the United
States, only a few of the 48 states in the class action suit directed a substantial part of their
proportion of the $235 billion settlement to smoking prevention and treatment. The other
Bioethics in the 21st Century
52
states assigned their settlement portion to deficit reduction, infrastructure needs, and more
general uses (Johnson, 2004).
Another systemic issue is the historic and continued unfair insurance coverage or
reimbursement for non-physician and non-hospital therapies. For instance, Canadian
provincial and territorial governments’ health insurance plans tend to not reimburse
psychotherapies or alternative treatments provided by non-physicians in the community,
but do reimburse physician-provided/prescribed and/or hospital-based treatments. In most
cases, psychologist/therapist and psychological measures are either paid by employer
insurance plans or out-of-pocket (Parker & Burke, 2005). These plans usually cap their
coverage at low levels. In fact, the U.S. Congress passed the Mental Health Parity and
Addiction Equity Act in 2008 to help address this inequity by requiring federal health plans
to reimburse mental health services on par with medical health services.
Systemic considerations contribute to “revolving door situations,” which are usually and
unfairly identified as “revolving door patients.” These situations centre on health gains,
made by someone while receiving the intensive and publicly provided services in a hospital,
dissipating quickly once he returns to the community which may lack certain services, or
have insufficient services, or have services that are neither easily understood nor effective.
Continuity of care and comprehensiveness of services falter. As a result, he soon requires re-
hospitalization to receive more intensive and comprehensive therapies. Returning to home
may mean that the benefits prove unsustainable and re-hospitalization is likely. This
repetitive cycle is particularly concerning if the illness is such that it is not physiologically
possible to return fully to the pre-crisis levels of functioning. Health system reform and
social system reform appear on most countries’ election platforms, but reform is difficult to
achieve given the programs’ immense complexity and the perpetual expectation of
increased funding.
7. Conclusion
7.1 Cases revisited
How can these various recommendations and cautions deepen and refine our
understanding of the cases at the opening of this chapter and shift our responses from what
is minimally ethical to what is optimally ethical?
Case 1: First, the nurse should verify what the applicable legislation states in terms of which,
if any, healthcare professional is responsible for reporting what, to whom, and based on
what evidence. If the legislation does assign responsibility, is it to just a physician or to any
healthcare worker who has direct contact with a client? If to a physician only, is the nurse
legally expected to notify the physician? Is the responsibility framed as obligatory or
permissible? In terms of evidence, is it in the form of a professional assessment or a mere
belief or opinion? Answers to such questions should guide the nurse in terms of what she
says to the physician and what she and/or the physician say to Sergei.
Even if there is no applicable legislation, this remains a possible health concern that the
physician should broach supportively with him. Alcohol dependence rates are highest in
Russia, therefore it is more likely that he, too, has a substance use problem, or at the very
least, may be experiencing some personal challenges for which he is misusing alcohol to
cope. If the physician and/or nurse conclude they do have a legal duty to report, it remains
their decision as to whether they actually will contact the Ministry. They may decide instead
to talk first with Sergei, learn more about his drinking pattern and motivations, and inform
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
53
him of their legal obligation to report. In so doing, they are weighing the likely
consequences to Sergei, his family members (who may be in the car when he is impaired),
and the general public. They may also believe openness and support will help preserve their
therapeutic relationship with him and increase the likelihood that if he is misusing alcohol,
he will pursue treatment and/or counselling. If the clinicians report Sergei to the Ministry
and the Ministry decides to revoke his licence, they should be willing to support---if they
have relevant corroborating information regarding his successful efforts to control the
medical condition that resulted in dangerous driving---a license re-application in the future.
Case 2: A team member should find out exactly what the Mental Health Act states. It is
careless and unprofessional to rely on unfounded assumptions and beliefs. The harmfulness
of sexually transmitted diseases (STDs) is subject to debate. For instance, some STDs are not
reportable under any provincial or state public health regulation, some are reportable only
in certain jurisdictions, and some STDs are reportable in every jurisdiction. Moreover, is
involuntary hospitalization the least restrictive preventive measure? The team may be
illegitimately presuming that Ana Li herself considers pregnancy or an STD something to
prevent. Paternalism needs to be tempered as do any moral judgments about “unwed
mothers,” “inadequate mothering,” or promiscuity. It is unclear whether Ana-Li lacks the
capacity to be making decisions about measures to reduce the likelihood of STDs,
pregnancy, or about engaging in sexual activity. Hypersexuality alone does not imply
incapacity. The team must share their concerns with Ana-Li and do so in a sensitive and
mature way. It should not be assumed that all team members are experienced and skilled
enough to talk about sexuality and intimacy.
If, however, she is found to lack the capacity to make decisions about such preventive
measures, the team should turn to her mother to make the related medical decisions. The
team will need to be more skilful in their discussions with Ana Li’s mother so that it will be
the client’s values that are respected. It is to be expected that parents and young adults will
differ about the meaning and risks of intimate activity and pregnancy. Admittedly single
parenthood tends to be difficult financially and otherwise, but this is often due to societal
constraints, rather than the individual’s apathy. Diligence is needed to not lapse into double
standards wherein most parents are given considerable latitude yet those with mental health
problems must reach a far higher standard. It would not be surprising if a team member
suggests early notification of a local child protection agency because of the possibility that
Ana-Li could become pregnant and unable to care for a child. However this is a “rush to
judgment” and may reflect prejudice and disrespect. Moreover, once the call to the agency is
made, it cannot be “unmade” and Ana-Li’s name may be recorded in its system indefinitely.
This could be stigmatizing and may negatively affect her in the future.
Case 3: The program clients’ health should improve and be sustained longer by having peer
workers’ support and advice and by having staff understand how their homes (or more
often, “housing”) contribute to or erode their well-being. Team members should benefit
professionally as well, because peer workers’ knowledge can help counter over-reliance on
the medical model and home visits help members identify and tailor services better to
clients’ circumstances and thus be more effective. But clinical considerations---which relate
to ethics because they are about meaningful benefits for those involved---do not exhaust this
case. A peer support worker can be a very special role: for instance, it may be designed such
that workers do not “do” therapy or provide treatment. Nor do they fill in for absent family
or friends, helping to occupy clients’ free time. Instead, peer support workers have their
Bioethics in the 21st Century
54
own expertise and ways to support clients in being as healthy as they wish. Team members
may unintentionally induce peer support workers to take on their work and thereby violate
role boundaries. Peer workers themselves may be attracted unconsciously to the seemingly
greater authority of the professionals, especially if the workers work side-by-side with the
clinic or hospital staff. These are organizational considerations.
Ethically, power, authority, and voice are involved here which means that client trust of the
team and workers is at stake, just as is the trust between the team and the workers. The
initiative about home visits is ethically complex because some clients may prefer to keep
their homes private, away from the team’s “medical gaze.” Other clients, however, may
appreciate home visits because of the convenience, plus it may help equalize the power in
their relationship with team members. Team members may not appreciate this implicit loss
of power. And if client lives in a risky area of town, team members may be reluctant to visit
alone, but program resources may be heavily strained if staff make home visits in pairs.
Nonetheless, equity of access to healthcare services demands proportional efforts (greater
efforts if access is harder) to reach those living in inhospitable areas due to poverty resulting
from having a serious mental illness or addiction, compared to efforts to reach those living
in safer areas. Neither initiative should be unilaterally imposed on clients, despite how
clinically sensible the initiatives seem. The director, managers, and leads should seek input
from a representative group of clients to ensure that both initiatives fit clients’ circumstances
and needs well. Furthermore, since the director is new to the program, he must act in
trustworthy ways in the hope that all his staff will genuinely commit to his overarching
vision, of which the two initiatives are representative.
Case 4: It may not be ethically sufficient for someone with good oratory skills to speak on
behalf of Jane. Given the historical treatment of individuals with mental health problems,
providing them opportunities to use their own “voice” can signal respect and a better
equalization of power. Moreover, the team should not assume that their therapeutic
relationship with Jane is more important than her relationship with the lawyer. Exercising
one’s legal options and participating in the judicial system are valuable citizenship rights.
The team may also be presuming incorrectly that the lawyer did not explain to Jane the
possible pros and cons of her testifying and how the Board would likely interpret her
remarks. Moreover, Jane may have decided that the benefits of speaking---to affirm her
courage to “stand before” those who will judge her case and to have them listen to her---
outweigh the possible risks. Team members may be ascribing to an erroneous stereotype
wherein Legal Aid lawyers are believed to be less skilled than Crown attorneys and
corporate lawyers. At the outset of Jane’s hospitalization, the team should have discussed
with her what their responsibilities are to her, to the Review Board, and to her lawyer, and
any competing, possibly conflicting, commitments. Leaving such conversations until just
before a Board hearing is inappropriate. The team should encourage Jane to see them and
her lawyer as available resources to her to help her return to the community, but refrain
from telling her what she should do to receive a conditional release.
Case 5: Is Omar revoking his consent when he says he does not want to go to the specialist?
If “yes” but the team ignores the revocation because debridement is “clearly in his best
interests” and his ulcers are debrided, this would constitute assault. What if the team
concludes that at the time he says he does not want to go, he lacks the capacity to decide
against debridement? Does his prior agreement when he had capacity still apply? This
situation illustrates the telling difference between consent to treatment---a decisional
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
55
activity---and cooperation with treatment---a physical and behavioural activity. Trying to
take him to the specialist’s office may result in an escalating situation of angry words, raised
voices, threatening statements and then a “code” has to be called. This may damage the
therapeutic relationship such that when Omar regains capacity, he may decide that
returning to his home as quickly as possible is his best immediate option. Furthermore,
Omar’s refusal to go to the hospital may reflect many people’s common reluctance and
vacillation about seeing medical practitioners and therapists. Understanding clients’
statements and behaviours should not be reduced just to medical considerations (i.e., non-
compliance) or legal considerations (i.e., lacking capacity). Rather, it is crucial to see clients
first as everyday people with many similar habits, preferences, and interests as everyone
else. In other words, Omar’s wish to not go to the specialist may be the response of most
people who must go to big hospitals or have non-healing ulcers debrided. Those who are
not in a hospital would just phone the specialist’s office and ask for a later appointment. But
Omar is in the hospital. The clinical team are now involved and may be unknowingly
making it their care plan, rather than his care plan.
Case 6: Money can compromise organizational and personal integrity and reputation alike.
The representatives should generate a variety of ideas to cover the costs without sacrificing
the number who will attend or who can attend. The considerable profits of pharmaceutical
and alcohol businesses means they have ready resources to increase their name recognition
and brand loyalty. The agency representatives should find out what are the kinds of
restrictions or limits academic healthcare institutions---which have long worried about
conflicts of interest, unbalanced content, and reduced credibility---have instituted in terms
of financial support from commercial enterprises and use these as guidelines. Moreover, it is
worthwhile investigating whether the industries have set their own detailed guidelines for
donations. As illustrated by the Code of Ethical Practices of Canadian research-based
pharmaceutical companies (Rx&D, 2010), industries may want to avoid perceptions of
excess and undue influence in order to protect their corporate reputation. In terms of the
lottery, will it increase attendance enough to cover the spa’s cost? Can the lottery be
replaced by a draw wherein all registrants receive just one ticket? If the spa weekend is of
modest value, it is unlikely to lure those with gambling problems. And much time will pass
between registration and the draw, which means immediate gratification from winning, a
risk factor of problem gambling, is almost impossible.
Case 7: Keeping secrets is risky, whether the secret-holder is the person with the health
problem, a family member, or a clinician. In the short-term, the benefits of secrets may
outweigh harms. Nonetheless, it can become more and more difficult to keep them. The
harm of nondisclosure may increase as time passes. The “right time” to break the silence
about the secret may never appear, but Edward’s health problem is long-term. Moreover,
what explains his continued visits to the physician? And what explains the seeming
inconsistency between taking the renewed prescriptions and yet not having them filled?
Qualitative studies have revealed that people have sound reasons for what appears initially
to be noncompliance with the recommended treatment.
In terms of Sandra and her partner, they should not be expected to keep their home open to
Edward indefinitely. Women continue to fulfill most of the demands of family and home life
in most societies, a continued sign of societal discrimination. It is thus inappropriate for the
physician to presume that Sandra and her partner still want to or should have Edward
reside with them. To address this quandary ethically, the physician should let Sandra know
Bioethics in the 21st Century
56
that it is not, and was not, legally or ethically appropriate for him to take advantage of the
secret administration of the prescription medication. He can suggest that Sandra explain to
Edward what she has done and why and be supportive if she is worried that Edward will
react in a threatening or unsafe way. The physician should invite Edward to his office to
discuss what has happened, why and provide information and resources to help Edward
remain as healthy as he wishes. In the spirit of not abandoning his patient and since it is
possible that the physician-patient relationship will be broken, the physician should be
prepared to offer Edward the names of other clinicians with whom he can find therapeutic
support and access medical treatments.
7.2 Wrap-up
In summary, people and their communities are complex. Problems with our cognitive and
emotional abilities have profound effects. Understanding and defining human cognition and
emotions and their interconnections continues to evolve in psychiatry, psychology,
neurology, and neuroscience. Moreover, recent research and clinical advances in neurology
and neuroscience have led to the emergence of neuroethics, the newest field within bioethics
and one focused on the human brain and nervous system. In a sense, science and what is
traditionally known as the medical complex have - rightly or wrongly - not yet assumed in
relation to mental health and addictions the authoritative position they have in physical
medicine and acute care settings.
Foundational ethical commitments and values remain relevant: for instance, the person’s
own wisdom and perspective, the community’s obligations to all its members, the duties
and limits of the state’s intervention in individual and familial lives, a holistic view of
factors contributing to individual and group well-being, and the immense, lasting harms of
discrimination and stigma. Therefore, ethical understanding, engagement, and assistance for
people’s mental health and addiction problems, requires in-depth and broad analyses,
multi-faceted and integrated responses, “the long view” and abiding commitment, non-
replication of past power imbalances and moralization, and a defensible role or place for
law and legislation.
8. References
Acosta, F, Bosch, E, Sarmiento, G, Juanes, N, Caballero-Hidalgo, A & Mayans, T. (2009).
Evaluation of Noncompliance in Schizophrenia Patients Using Electronic
Monitoring (MEMS) and its Relationship to Sociodemographic, Clinical and
Psychopathological Variables. Schizophrenia Research, Vol. 107, Nos. 2-3 (February
2009), pp. 213-7, ISSN 0920-9964.
Amiel, J, Mangurian, C, Ganguli, R & Newcomer, J. (2008). Addressing Cardiometabolic
Risk During Treatment with Antipsychotic Medications. Current Opinion in
Psychiatry, Vol. 21, No. 6 (November 2008), pp. 613-8, ISSN 0951-7367.
Andresen, M. (2006). Governments' Conflict of Interest in Treating Problem Gamblers.
CMAJ, Vol. 175, No. 10 (November 2006), pp. 1191, ISSN 1488-2329. Aristotle.
(2009). Nicomachean Ethics, World Classics Library, ISBN 019283407X, Des Moines
Austin, W. (2001). Relational Ethics in Forensic Psychiatric Settings. Journal of Psychosocial
Nursing & Mental Health Services, Vol. 39, No. 9 (September 2001), pp. 12-7, ISSN
0279-3695.
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
57
Banzato, C. (2004). Classification in Psychiatry: the move towards ICD-11 and DSM-V.
Current Opinion in Psychiatry, Vol. 17, No. 6 (November 2004), pp. 497-501, ISSN
0951-7367.
Baum, F, Newman, L, Biedrzycki, K & Patterson, J. (2010). Can a Regional Government's
Social Inclusion Initiative Contribute to the Quest for Health Equity? Health
Promotion International, Vol. 25, No. 4 (December 2010), pp. 474-82, ISSN 0957-4824.
Bissella, P, May, C & Noyce, P. (2004). From Compliance to Concordance: barriers to
accomplishing a re-framed model of health care interactions. Social Science &
Medicine, Vol. 58, No. 4 (February 2004), pp. 851–62, ISSN 0277-9536.
Bogdanoski, T. (2009). Psychiatric Advance Directives: the new frontier in mental health law
reform in Australia? Journal of Law & Medicine, Vol. 16, No. 5 (May 2009), pp. 891-
904, ISSN 1320-159X.
Burns, T & Dawson, J. (2009). Community Treatment Orders: how ethical without
experimental evidence? Psychological Medicine, Vol. 39, No. 10 (October 2009), pp.
1583-6, ISSN 0033-2917.
Canadian Mental Health Association. (2007). Poverty and Mental Illness. Retrieved from
www.ontario.cmha.ca/backgrounders.asp?cID=25341.
Carter, S. (1996). Integrity. HarperPerennial, ISBN 9780060928070, New York.
Cleveland, M, Feinberg, M & Greenberg, M. (2010). Protective Families in High- and Low-
Risk Environments: implications for adolescent substance use. Journal of Youth &
Adolescence, Vol. 39, No. 2 (February 2010), pp. 114-26, ISSN 0047-2891.
Collier, R. (2010). DSM Revision Surrounded by Controversy. CMAJ, Vol. 182, No. 1
(January 2010), pp. 16-7, ISSN 1488-2329.
Corvette, B. (2000). Therapeutic Jurisprudence. Sociological Practice, Vol. 2, No. 2 (June 2000),
pp. 127-32, ISSN 1522-3442.
Dickie, I. (2008). Ethical Dilemmas, Forensic Psychology, and Therapeutic Jurisprudence.
Thomas Jefferson Law Review, Vol. 30, No. 2 (Spring 2008), pp. 455-61, ISSN 1090-
5278.
Elisha, D, Castle, D & Hocking, B. (2006). Reducing Social Isolation in People with Mental
Illness: the role of the psychiatrist. Australasian Psychiatry, Vol. 14, No. 3 (September
2006), pp. 281-4, ISSN 1039-8562.
Finney, J & Moos, R. (2006). Matching Clients' Treatment Goals with Treatment Oriented
Towards Abstinence, Moderation or Harm Reduction. Addiction, Vol. 101, No. 11
(November 2006), pp. 1540-2, ISSN 0968-7610.
Flanagan, E, Miller, R & Davidson, L. (2009). “Unfortunately, We Treat the Chart:” sources
of stigma in mental health settings. Psychiatric Quarterly, Vol. 80, No. 1 (March
2009), pp. 55-64, ISSN 1573-6709.
Foucault, M. (1988). Madness and Civilization: a history of insanity in the age of reason. Random
House, ISBN 067972110X, New York. Frank, A. (2004). Ethics as Process and
Practice. Internal Medicine Journal, Vol. 34, No. 6 (June
Futterman, R, Lorente, M & Silverman, S. (2004). Integrating Harm Reduction and
Abstinence-Based Substance Abuse Treatment in the Public Sector. Substance Abuse,
Vol. 25, No. 1 (March 2004), pp. 3-7, ISSN 0889-7077.
Gagne, C, White, W & Anthony, W. (2007). Recovery: a common vision for the fields of
mental health and addictions. Psychiatric Rehabilitation Journal, Vol. 31, No. 1
(Summer 2007), pp. 32-7, ISSN 1095-158X.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
58
Gouthro, T. (2009). Recognizing and Addressing the Stigma Associated with Mental Health
Nursing: a critical perspective. Issues in Mental Health Nursing, Vol. 30, No. 11
(November 2009), pp. 669-76, ISSN 1061-2840.
Halter, M. (2008). Perceived Characteristics of Psychiatric Nurses: stigma by association.
Archives of Psychiatric Nursing, Vol. 22, No. 1 (February 2008), pp. 20-6, ISSN 0883-
9417.
Helzer, J, Bucholz, K & Gossop, M. (2007). A Dimensional Option for the Diagnosis of
Substance Dependence in DSM-V. International Journal of Methods in Psychiatric
Research, Vol.16, No. S1 (June 2007), pp. S24-33, ISSN 1557-0657.
Hilfiker, D. (1992). The Case. Clint Wooder. Second Opinion, vol. 18, no. 2 (October 1992), pp.
42-53, ISSN 0890-1570.
Hofman, N, Strenski, T, Marshall, P & Heimer, R. (2003). Maintaining Respectability and
Responsibility: gendered labor patterns among women injection drug users. Health
Care for Women International, Vol. 24, No. 9 (November 2003), pp. 794–807, ISSN
0739-9332.
Holland, M. (1998). Touching the Weights: moral perception and attention. International
Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 38, No. 3 (September 1998), pp. 299-312, ISSN 0019-
0365.
Hudson, C. (2005). Socioeconomic Status and Mental Illness: tests of the social causation and
selection hypotheses. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry, Vol. 75, No. 1, (January
2005), pp. 3–18, ISSN 1939-0025.
Hunt, A, da Silva, A, Lurie, S & Goldbloom, D. (2007). Community Treatment Orders in
Toronto: the emerging data. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, Vol. 52, No. 10 (October
2007), pp. 647-56, ISSN 0706-7437.
Hwang, S. (2001) Homelessness and Health. CMAJ, Vol. 164, No. 2, (January 2001), pp. 229-
33, ISSN 1488-2329.
Ivanova, M & Israel, A. (2006). Family Stability as a Protective Factor Against
Psychopathology for Urban Children Receiving Psychological Services. Journal of
Clinical Child & Adolescent Psychology, Vol. 35, No. 4 (December 2006), pp. 564-70,
ISSN 1537-4416.
Johnson, C. (2004). The State of the Tobacco Settlement: are settlement funds being used to
finance state government budget deficits? A research note. Public Budgeting &
Finance, Vol. 24, No. 1 (March 2004), pp. 113-25, ISSN 0275-1100.
Kingdon, D & Nicholl, J. (2006). Mental Health Research Continues to be Underfunded.
BMJ, Vol. 332, No. 7556 (June 2006), pp. 1510, ISSN 0959-8138.
Knesper, D. (2007). My Favorite Tips for Engaging the Difficult Patient on Consultation-
Liaison Psychiatry Services. Psychiatric Clinics of North America, Vol. 30, No. 2 (June
Korol, S. (2008). Familial and Social Support as Protective Factors Against the Development
of Dissociative Identity Disorder. Journal of Trauma & Dissociation, Vol. 9, No. 2, pp.
249-67, ISSN 1529-9732.
Kraemer, H. (2007). DSM Categories and Dimensions in Clinical and Research Contexts.
International Journal of Methods in Psychiatric Research, Vol.16, No. S1 (June 2007), pp.
S8-S15, ISSN 1557-0657.
Lauder, W, Kroll, T & Jones, M. (2007). Social Determinants of Mental Health: the missing
dimensions of mental health nursing? Journal of Psychiatric & Mental Health Nursing,
Vol. 14, No. 7 (October 2007), pp. 661-9, ISSN 1351-0126.
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
59
Lauro, L, Bass, A, Goldsmith, L, Kaplan, J, Katz, G & Schaye. S. (2003). Psychoanalytic
Supervision of the Difficult Patient. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, Vol. 72, No. 2 (April
2003), pp. 403-38, ISSN 0033-2828.
Liggins, J & Hatcher, S. (2005). Stigma toward the Mentally Ill in the General Hospital: a
qualitative study. General Hospital Psychiatry, Vol. 27, No. 5 (September 2005), pp.
359-64, ISSN 0163-8343.
Link, B & Phelan J. (2001). Conceptualizing Stigma. Annual Review of Sociology, Vol. 27, No. 1
(2001), pp. 363-85, ISSN 0360-0572.
Livingstone, C & Adams, P. (2011). Harm Promotion: observations on the symbiosis
between government and private industries in Australasia for the development of
highly accessible gambling markets. Addiction, Vol. 106, No. 1 (January 2011), pp. 3–
8, ISSN 1074-3529.
Lowe, T & Lubos, E. (2008). Effectiveness of Weight Management Interventions for People
with Serious Mental Illness Who Receive Treatment with Atypical Antipsychotic
Medications. A literature review. Journal of Psychiatric & Mental Health Nursing, Vol.
15, No. 10 (December 2008), pp. 857-63, ISSN 1351-0126.
MacIntyre, A. (2007). After Virtue: a study in moral theory, third edition, University of Notre
Dame Press, ISBN 9780268035044, Notre Dame.
Meltzer, H. (2008) State-of-Science Review: SR-B6 The Mental Ill-Health of Homeless People
for Mental Capital and Wellbeing: Making the most of ourselves in the 21st century.
Retrieved from www.bis.gov.uk/assets/bispartners/foresight/docs/mental-
capital/sr-b6_mcw.pdf.
Miller, W. (2008). The Ethics of Harm Reduction, In The Book of Ethics: expert guidance for
professionals who treat addiction, Geppert, C & Roberts, L, pp. 41-54, Hazelden, ISBN
9781592854929, Center City (MN).
Miller, P, Linteris, N & Forzisi, L. (2008). Is Groin Injecting an Ethical Boundary for Harm
Reduction? International Journal of Drug Policy, Vol. 19, No. 6 (December 2008), pp.
486–91, ISSN 0955-3959.
Moore, D. (2007). Translating Justice and Therapy: the drug treatment court networks.
British Journal of Criminology, Vol. 47, No. 1 (January 2007), pp. 42-60, ISSN 0007-
0955.
Morgan, C, Kirkbride, J, Hutchinson, G, Craig, T, Morgan, K, Dazzan, P, Boydell, J, Doody,
G, Jones, P, Murray, R, Leff, J & Fearon, P. (2008). Cumulative Social Disadvantage,
Ethnicity and First-Episode Psychosis: a case-control study. Psychological Medicine,
Morgan, C, Burns, T, Fitzpatrick, R, Pinfold, V & Priebe, S. (2007). Social Exclusion and
Mental Health: conceptual and methodological review. British Journal of Psychiatry,
Vol. 191, No. 6 (December 2007), pp. 477-83, ISSN 0007-1250.
Morse, S. (2008). The Ethics of Forensic Practice: reclaiming the wasteland. Journal of the
American Academy of Psychiatry & the Law, Vol. 36, No. 2 (June 2008), pp. 206-17,
ISSN 1093-6793.
Muench, J & Hamer, A. (2010). Adverse Effects of Antipsychotic Medications. American
Family Physician, Vol. 81, No. 5 (March 2010), pp. 617-22, ISSN 0002-838X.
National Coalition for the Homeless. (2009) Mental Illness and Homelessness, (July 2009),
Retrieved from www.nationalhomeless.org/factsheets/Mental_Illness.pdf.
National Institutes of Health. (2010). Summary of the FY 2011 President’s Budget. Retrieved
from
Bioethics in the 21st Century
60
http://officeofbudget.od.nih.gov/pdfs/FY11/Summary%20of%20the%20FY%2020
11%20Presidents%20Budget.pdf.
Neale, J. (2008). Homelessness, Drug Use and Hepatitis C: a complex problem explored
within the context of social exclusion. International Journal of Drug Policy, Vol. 19,
No. 6 (December 2008), pp. 429-35, ISSN 0955-3959.
Nolan, J. (2003). Redefining Criminal Courts: problem solving and the meaning of justice.
American Criminal Law Review, Vol. 40, No. 4 (Fall 2003), pp. 1541-65, ISSN 0164-
0364.
Nussbaum, M. (1985). Finely Aware and Richly Responsible: moral attention and the moral
task of literature. Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 82, No. 10 (October 1985), pp. 516-29,
ISSN 0022-362X.
Onken, S, Craig, C, Ridgway, P, Ralph, R & Cook, J. (2007). An Analysis of the Definitions
and Elements of Recovery: a review of the literature Psychiatric Rehabilitation
Journal, Vol. 3, No. 1 (Summer 2007), pp. 9-22, ISSN 1095-158X.
Parker Jr., F & Burke, L. (2005). Employers, Ethics, and Managed Care. Employee Benefit Plan
Review, Vol. 59, No. 9 (February 2005), pp. 7-11, ISSN 0013-6808.
Piko, B & Kovacs, E. (2010). Do Parents and School Matter? Protective factors for adolescent
substance use. Addictive Behaviors, Vol. 35, No. 1 (January 2010), pp. 53-6, ISSN
0306-4603.
Pincus, H & McQueen, L. (2002). The Limits of an Evidence-Based Classification of Mental
Disorders, In Descriptions and Prescriptions: values, mental disorders, and the DSMs,
Sadler, J (ed.), pp. 9-24, Johns Hopkins University Press, ISBN 0801868408,
Baltimore.
Pouncey, C & Lukens, J. (2010). Madness versus Badness: the ethical tension between the
recovery movement and forensic psychiatry. Theoretical Medicine & Bioethics, Vol.
31, No. 1 (February 2010), pp. 93-105, ISSN 1386-7415.
Proulx, M, Leduc, N, Vandelac, L, Gregoire, J & Collin, J. (2007) Social Context, the Struggle
with Uncertainty, and Subjective Risk as Meaning-Rich Constructs for Explaining
HBP Noncompliance. Patient Education & Counseling, Vol. 68, No. 1 (September
2007), pp. 98-106, ISSN 0738-3991.
Radcliffe, P & Stevens, A. (2008). Are Drug Treatment Services Only for ‘Thieving Junkie
Scumbags’? Drug users and the management of stigmatized identities. Social Science
& Medicine, Vol. 67, No. 7 (October 2008), pp. 1065-73, ISSN 0277-9536.
Radden, J & Sadler, J. (2010). The Virtuous Psychiatrist. Oxford University Press, ISBN
9780195389371, Oxford.
Rose, D, Thornicroft, G, Pinfold, V & Kassam, A. (2007). 250 Labels Used to Stigmatise
People with Mental Illness. BMC Health Services Research, Vol. 7, No. 97 (June 2007),
pp. 1-7, ISSN 1472-6963.
Ross, C & Goldner, E. (2009). Stigma, Negative Attitudes and Discrimination Towards
Mental Illness within the Nursing Profession: a review of the literature. Journal of
Psychiatric & Mental Health Nursing, Vol. 16, No. 6 (August 2009), pp. 558-67, ISSN
1351-0126.
Russell, B. (2008). An Integrative and Practical Approach to Ethics in Everyday Healthcare
in Risk Management in Canadian Health Care, Dykeman, M & Dewhirst, K (eds.), pp.
9-13, Lexis-Nexis Canada, ISBN 978433443988, Toronto.
Rx&D. (2010). Code of Ethical Practices. Retrieved from
Ethics Related to Mental Illnesses and Addictions
61
https://www.canadapharma.org/en/commitment/healthcare/pdfs/2010%20-
%20Code%20of%20Ethical%20Practices_en.pdf.
Schmidt, N, Kotov, R & Joiner Jr., T. (2004). Taxometrics: toward a new diagnostic scheme for
psychopathology. American Psychological Association, ISBN 1591471427,
Washington DC.
Schulze, B. (2007). Stigma and Mental Health Professionals: a review of the evidence on an
intricate relationship. International Review of Psychiatry, Vol. 19, No. 2 (January
2007), pp. 137-55, ISSN 0954-0261.
[Senate] Standing Committee on Social Affairs, Science and Technology. (2006). Out of the
Shadows at Last. Retrieved from
www.parl.gc.ca/39/1/parlbus/commbus/senate/com-e/soci-e/rep-
e/pdf/rep02may06part1-e.pdf.
Shaffer, D, Hartman, J & Listwan, S. (2009). Drug Abusing Women in the Community: The
impact of drug court involvement on recidivism. Journal of Drug Issues, Vol. 39, No.
4, (Fall 2009), pp. 803-28, ISSN 0022-0426.
Skorpen, A, Anderssen, N, Oeye, C & Bjelland, A. (2008). The Smoking Room as Psychiatric
Patients’ Sanctuary: a place for resistance. Journal of Psychiatric and Mental Health
Nursing, Vol. 15, No. 9 (November 2008), pp. 728-36, ISSN 1365-2850.
Smith, T & Hirdes, J. (2009). Predicting Social Isolation Among Geriatric Psychiatry Patients.
International Psychogeriatrics, Vol. 21, No. 1 (February 2009), pp. 50-9, ISSN 1041-
6102.
Sokol, D. (2007). Ethicist on the Ward Round. BMJ, Vol. 335, No. 7621 (September 2007), pp.
670, ISSN 0959-8138.
Srebnik, D & Russo, J. (2008). Use of Psychiatric Advance Directives During Psychiatric
Crisis Events. Administration & Policy in Mental Health, Vol. 35, No. 4 (July 2008), pp.
272-82, ISSN 0894-587X.
Srebnik, D, Rutherford, L, Peto, T, Russo, J, Zick, E, Jaffe, C & Holtzheimer, P. (2005). The
Content and Clinical Utility of Psychiatric Advance Directives. Psychiatric Services,
Vol. 56, No. 5 (May 2005), pp. 592-8, ISSN 1075-2730.
Stewart, D & DeMarco J. (2010) Rational Noncompliance with Prescribed Medical
Treatment. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, Vol. 20, No. 3 (September 2010), pp.
Stuhlmiller, C. (2005). Promoting Student Interest in Mental Health Nursing, Journal of the
American Psychiatric Nursing Association, Vol. 11, No. 6 (December 2005), pp. 355-8,
ISSN 1078-3903.
Sutherby, K, Szmukler, G, Halpern, A, Alexander, M, Thornicroft, G, Johnson, C & Wright,
S. (1999). A Study of “Crisis Cards” in a Community Psychiatric Service. Acta
Psychiatrica Scandinavica, Vol. 100, No. 1 (July 1999), pp. 56-61, ISSN 0001-690X.
Swanson, J, McCrary, S, Swartz, M, Elbogen, E & Van Dorn, R. (2006). Superseding
Psychiatric Advance Directives: ethical and legal considerations. Journal of the
American Academy of Psychiatry & the Law, Vol. 34, No. 3 (September 2006), pp. 385-
94, ISSN 1093-6793.
Szasz, T. (2009). Antipsychiatry: quackery squared. Syracuse University Press, ISBN
9780815609438, Syracuse.
Szasz, T. (1976). Schizophrenia: the sacred symbol of psychiatry. BasicBooks, ISBN
9780465072224, New York.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
62
Szasz, T. (1961). The Myth of Mental Illness: foundations of a theory of personal conduct. Harper &
Row, ISBN 0060141964, New York.
Tessman, L. (2005). Burdened Virtues: virtue ethics for liberatory struggles. Oxford University
Press, ISBN 9780195179156, Oxford.
Walker, D & Jackson J. (2011). The Effect of Legalized Gambling on State Government
Revenue. Contemporary Economic Policy, Vol. 29, No. 1 (January 2011), pp. 101-14,
ISSN 1465-7287.
Wilson, A & Beresford, P. (2002) Madness, Distress and Postmodernity, In Embodying
Disability Theory, Corker, M & Shakespeare, T (eds.), pp. 143-58, Continuum, ISBN
0826450555, London (U.K.).
Wilson, H & Skodol, A. (1994). Special Report: DSM-IV: overview and examination of major
changes. Archives of Psychiatric Nursing, Vol. 8, No. 6 (December 1994), pp. 340-7,
ISSN 0883-9417.
Wilton, R. (2004). Putting Policy into Practice? Poverty and people with serious mental
illness. Social Science & Medicine, Vol. 58, No. 1 (January 2004), pp. 25–39, ISSN 0277-
9536.
Winkler, E. (2005). The Ethics of Policy Writing: how should hospitals deal with moral
disagreement about controversial medical practices? Journal of Medical Ethics, Vol.
31, No. 10, (October 2005), pp. 559-66, ISSN 0306-6800.
World Health Organization. (2004). The World Medicines Situation. Retrieved from
http://apps.who.int/medicinedocs/pdf/s6160e/s6160e.pdf.
World Health Organization. (2003). Social Determinants of Health: the solid facts, second edition.
Wilkinson, R & Marmot, M. (eds.). Retrieved from www.euro.who.int/
data/assets/pdf_file/0005/98438/e81384.pdf.
Zaner, R. (2004). Ethics and the Clinical Encounter. First Academic Renewal Press, ISBN
0788099396, Lima (OH).
4
Resource Allocation
in Health Care
Giovanni Putoto and Renzo Pegoraro
Padova Teaching Hospital and Fondazione Lanza
Italy
1. Introduction
In many European countries where reforms of the welfare system are underway, reference
is often made to the need to ‘rationalise’ the provision of health care. This term is
generally used to refer to the need to organise healthcare effectively by reducing waste,
containing costs, and ensuring that budgets are adhered to. Actions taken to achieve this
are varied: some relate to the provision of services (for example, concentrating the
provision of goods and services, redistributing health care workers); others require
redefinition of the level of service provision (for example, avoiding hospital admission for
conditions that can be treated in the clinic, or in day care); others rely on the application of
the tools provided by evidence based medicine and evidence based healthcare to define the
most effective medical care and interventions (for example, eliminating those procedures
whose effectiveness is not supported by firm scientific evidence). All this is aimed at
making healthcare provision more efficient and effective. Nevertheless, despite the efforts
being made in this direction, it is becoming evident that rationalisation of healthcare
provision is not sufficient in itself. The ageing population, the development of new and
expensive technologies, the emergence of new diseases such as AIDS, Bovine Spongiform
Encephalopathy (BSE), Severe Acute Respiratory Syndrome (SARS), and above all the
rising expectations of healthcare users, are all leading to an unsustainable tension between
demand and healthcare resources available.
Because it is not possible to provide everything to everyone, even by putting unacceptable
pressure on present finances and by threatening provision for future generations, and
since it is arguably socially unacceptable to leave the provision of healthcare to the free
market, it is inevitable that certain choices be made. This implies a process of ‘rationing’,
rather than ‘rationalisation’, that can be defined as ‘the distribution of resources between
programmes and persons in competition’. In the process of rationing, a series of crucial
questions must be posed: What treatments or healthcare services should be provided to
citizens? How should these services be distributed between members of a society amidst
budgetary constraints? Who decides? How? On the basis of which criteria? The problem
of rationing (also referred to as ‘priority setting’, or ‘resource allocation’) in healthcare is
therefore a problem of the moral legitimacy of such choices; this chapter illustrates this.
As challenges of rationing are not expected to change in the foreseeable future, at least not
in principle, we will address future and present rationing challenges in health care
similarly.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
64
2. From implicit to explicit rationing
Traditionally, the many resource allocation decisions in healthcare were made in a non-
explicit manner. Healthcare budgets were allocated to local authorities on a historical
basis and doctors were given the task of deciding priorities for the provision of services.
Today, increasingly, the choices made by politicians and professional healthcare
managers must consider general and specific criteria in planning within budgetary
constraints, and they are subject to scrutiny from a general public that is increasingly
determined to see proper provision of healthcare in return for their taxes. But it is doctors
that are seeing the greatest changes. The old pact that implicitly gave them the task of
distributing healthcare resources according to their professional judgement is gone. In the
medical world there is now an explicit requirement to account for the treatment choices
made, and there are mechanisms for checking disparities in the provision of diagnostic
and therapeutic services. These choices were once seen as strictly a matter of professional
autonomy. A further change that is indicating a move to a more explicit form of rationing
is the change in the once paternalistic doctor-patient relationship. A better educated
population with easy access to healthcare information, that is increasingly aware of the
need to become involved in decisions that concern their own body and health, and their
associated rights to healthcare, is pushing to question doctors’ decision making and to
demand explanations of choices made to include or exclude certain conditions from
healthcare provision. There are many cases of explicit rationing that are emerging in
different European countries: one of the most widely discussed of these was the
case of Child B in the United Kingdom, who was denied experimental therapy for
leukaemia on the basis that it was prohibitively expensive and of unproven efficacy (Ham,
1999).
In general, there is some agreement that rationing should be more open and explicit, thus
increasing accountability and the credibility of decision making. Despite this, a number of
arguments have been posed against this, particularly that it may lead to instability in the
health system and/or may cause harm to patients and the public. Others suggest that
rationing is about decision making and should be considered a political process that is
experimental and incremental.
3. Levels of rationing: macro, meso and micro
Healthcare rationing is a pervasive process that takes place at all levels and assumes various
forms. Choices concern priorities, so that the rationing taking place at different levels of the
public service through a hierarchy from high to low often constrains spending at the lower
level. There are at least five levels at which choices are made:
- the level of funding to be allocated to health services
- the distribution of the budget between geographical area and services
- the allocation of resources to particular forms of treatment
- the choice of which patients should receive access to treatment
- decisions on how much to spend on individual patients
For convenience it is common to refer to three levels. The first (‘macro’) is the national or
regional level, where the healthcare budget is decided. At this stage, decisions are made
regarding increases in contributions, reductions in spending, or financing of particular
programmes. Macro-decisions at a national level represent the key constraint within which
Resource Allocation in Health Care
65
further divisions of funds between regions and local health providers are made according to
formulae that vary from country to country.
The second (‘meso’) is the local level (regional or hospital), where resources are allocated to
different functions and local authorities make decisions about local priorities. Such choices
may involve the priorities attached to, for example, treatment services versus preventative
medicine; particular patient groups, for example those with renal failure versus drug
addicts; or certain hospital services, for example cancer services, versus other services such
as respiratory care.
The third (‘micro’) level is the care level, where healthcare professionals make decisions
about who, how, when, where and how to care for patients. This is a question of
professional prerogative that can be limited by constraints from above, but never
eliminated.
4. Decision makers and problems in reaching consensus: Who decides?
In societies where health services are funded and supplied principally via the state, cost
increases and budgetary constraints impose difficult choices that influence the services that
can be provided, the patients served and the circumstances of healthcare. The notion that
public opinion can influence the decision making process has gained momentum. Taking
note of public opinion obliges doctors, managers and politicians to take account of the
concerns of the population, supports the formulation of objectives according to need, and
favours social cohesion as well as civil identity. Many claim that without the agreement of
the public, choices about rationing should never be effected, as they lack legitimacy. It is
important to remember that public opinion about what services should be provided
frequently differs from the opinions of doctors and healthcare managers. It is also important
to note that in some jurisdictions, healthcare professionals other than doctors/physicians
have a strong say in this matter.
Considering the tendency of healthcare providers to be sometimes unresponsive to the
needs of society and inward looking, this develpoment of public involvment is to be
considered a positive step. In a democratic society it is no longer acceptable to make
decisions in the name of and on behalf of others without those others being informed and
consulted. It is a matter of what we now call ‘citizen rights’. Nevertheless, involving the
public in decision making is a complex process, both in principle and in relation to the
instruments that are used to gather public opinion. It is worth considering these limitations
in order to mitigate their effects (Mossialos & King 1999):
- The public, in general, is not in possession of enough information to make decisions.
Unless certain information is supplied regarding the effectiveness, risks, costs, and
quality of life implications of interventions, along with the options for alternative
treatments, decision makers cannot fully understand the problem
- There is a lack of familiarity with the debate on rationing, which would permit the
public to be capable of assessing the questions presented
- The effect of bias in public opinion caused by emotional responses generated by a
media that prefers sensationalist reporting to accurate presentaion of facts should not
be underestimated, as shown by the Di Bella case in Italy (Benelli 2003).
- It is important to encourage the public to think in terms of public interest as a whole, for
the common good over and above the good of individuals
Bioethics in the 21st Century
66
- Even public representation, when it exists, can present its own problems. The inclusion
or exclusion of certain groups or individuals can influence the range of attitudes and
values expressed. One approach is to involve service users, another is to solicit general
public opinion, or the opinion of institutional representatives. In the US state of Oregon,
for example, groups of disabled persons rejected the first list of proposed funded
treatments; they argued that the quality of life of disabled persons was undervalued by
the Commission addressing their matter.
- It is also necessary to consider the level at which choices are made (Litvaa et al. 2002).
At the system and program levels, informants generally tend to favour consultation,
without taking responsibility for decisions, but with the guarantee that their
contribution would be heard and that decisions taken following consultation would be
explained. At the patient level, it may be that the public should participate only by
setting criteria for deciding between potential beneficiaries of treatment, leaving the
final say to the doctors and the patients involved (and other healthcare professionals
and family involved).
- There are many methods that can be used to solicit public opinion. These include
surveys, in-depth interviews, public meetings, community forums, focus groups and
citizens’ juries. This list is not exhaustive, but reflects a range of options available. Pros
and cons in terms of time, costs, depth and breadth of analysis, discussion and
deliberations should be taken into account.
- Regardless of the method used, the value of public participation in priority setting is
largely dependent on the importance placed, by decision-makers, on the results of
public consultation.
The participation of the public in setting priorities is key for legitimacy. It is an educational
process that has to be encouraged and sustained. Public debate should be based on relevant
information and accurate communication, be open and transparent with all stakeholders,
and should make use of appropriate tools.
5. Methods of rationing
Methods of rationing that can be applied are many. In general they are classified as follows:
- Selection: Using this method, recipients of care are selected on the basis of clinical
benefit they will obtain, or the amount of time required to treat them.
- Denial: This method involves the exclusion of certain patient populations because
they are deemed unworthy, or because their needs are not seen as sufficiently
important.
- Deflection: This involves referring patients to other institutions. It is a form of rationing
when a patient’s needs can be met by other health or social services.
- Deterrence: This involves deterring patients from accessing healthcare by the imposition
of complex logistical/administrative requirements, such as inconvenient opening times,
incomprehensible paperwork, and unhelpful staff. This type of rationing tends to
disadvantage less educated and more vulnerable people.
- Delay: This method includes the use of waiting lists. It is the most recognised form of
implicit rationing in healthcare, and discourages patients from accessing health
services.
- Dilution: In this situation access to services is not denied, but the provision of services is
reduced, such as the frequency of home visits.
Resource Allocation in Health Care
67
- Interruption: This is the premature termination of a service or a treatment based on a
maximum time limit for a given treatment, such as premature discharge from hospital
or case closure.
Overall, these mechanisms of rationing are used by various decision makers, although only
the first (selection) is formally endorsed. Often rationing is not deliberate or conscious, but is
a means for professionals to cope with budgetary or other pressures. An alternative is the
development of guidelines as a medium/long term solution.
6. Technical and distributive approaches to rationing
To make choices or establish priorities, certain criteria are required that reflect the most
prevalent values in society. All countries that have embarked on this have stated the values
on which they have based their choices. There are, in general, diverse principles that can
guide a society’s choices. These can be classified into technical criteria or distributive
criteria. The first refer to the ‘technical’ qualities that services must possess in order to be
included, such as efficiency, efficacy, and appropriateness. The others criteria are
‘distributive’ in nature, in that they help establish an order of priorities in the choice
between different patient groups, such as relative benefit, and the rule of rescue.
7. Technical criteria
These are a prerequisite for any selection of priorities. For example, it is well established and
accepted that healthcare interventions should be effective, efficient and appropriate. Such
considerations can help in making choices, in as much as they help exclude those
interventions that do not meet these criteria, but they are not enough in themselves to
establish how many and which interventions to provide, and to whom.
Effectiveness
The principle of effectiveness affirms that priority must be given only to those
interventions that produce positive medical results. It is a principle that is intuitive and
attractive in itself. The difficulties arise when one has to apply it and face up to the
implications of this principle. According to some studies, the majority of surgical and
medical procedures in use today are not based on scientific evidence of their effectiveness
(85% according to the US Office of Technology Assessment). The scientific method for
evaluating the effectiveness of healthcare treatments is based on the use of clinical
research, and has as its gold standard the randomised controlled trial, the most rigorous
assessment instrument, (hence real life circumstances) although it addressed efficacy
rather than effectiveness. Despite the recent development of evidence based medicine and
evidence based health care approaches and more refined instruments such as meta analysis,
the criterion of effectiveness is not without its limitations. Above all, the collection and
analysis of data about interventions is often expensive and may lead to ambiguous
conclusions. Sometimes clinical research is not conducted with the required rigour, and
frequently a treatment that may not be of general effectiveness may be appropriate in
particular circumstances. To eliminate all procedures not demonstrated to be effective
would therefore be unwise: even those treatments that are not scientifically well
corroborated may sometimes be helpful.
Efficiency
Bioethics in the 21st Century
68
Efficiency is an economic concept. There are at least three types of efficiency that have been
identified: technical, productive, and allocative.
Technical efficiency compares the resources required for a healthcare intervention (input) with
the health benefits obtained (output). The relation must be as high as possible: maximum
output compared with input, or minimal input compared with output. An example of
technical efficiency is that of using 10mg of alendronate rather than 20mg of it in the treatment
of osteoporosis since studies showed that the smaller dose achieved the same clinical results
(assuming use of the smaller dose is less costly than use of the larger dose).
Productive efficiency is related to the possibility of choosing between two or more alternative
treatments in relation to costs and results. Consider, for example, a policy of changing from
maternal age screening to biochemical screening for Down's syndrome. The concept of
productive efficiency refers to the maximisation of health outcome for a given cost, or the
minimisation of cost for a given outcome. If the sum of the costs of the new biochemical
screening program is smaller than or the same as the maternal age programme and
outcomes are equal or better, then the biochemical program is productively efficient in
relation to the maternal age program. In healthcare, productive efficiency enables
assessment of the relative value for money of interventions with directly comparable
outcomes.
Allocative efficiency refers to the destination of resources, which society makes available to
various alternative uses, and defines as optimal the allocation that improves the health
situation of an individual without compromising that of another.
The promise of the principle of efficiency, in its three forms, as a guide for defining
choices, is attractive from an ethical point of view because it promises to deliver a greater
volume of healthcare services at the same cost, and to make choices less painful. But
problems emerge when applying this principle, in deciding the optimal allocation of
scarce resources within a society. Economic theory in general has led to the development
of various methods of evaluating the costs and benefits associated with different
healthcare interventions, in particular analysis of cost/efficacy, cost/utility and
cost/benefit. Criticisms of this approach lie not so much in the evaluation of costs, as in
the notion of benefit and the consequences on health and above all, in distribution. In the
cost/efficacy analysis, the results of a healthcare intervention are measured using
indicators specific to the intervention or the disease treated (for example, reduction in
infection rates, or rates of five year survival) and therefore do not allow a comparison
between different illnesses, but only amongst alternative treatments for the same disorder
(for example, medication compared to a surgical alternative). In cost/utility analysis this
limitation has been overcome, to a certain extent, by the use of complex formulae such as
QALYs (quality-adjusted life years) and DALYs (disability-adjusted life years), which
tend to better reflect not only the cost of an intervention, but the quantity and quality of
years of life productive/independent and functioning gained. This allows a comparison
between different interventions for different illnesses and allows the creation of a ‘league
table’ of interventions, based on these criteria. Evaluating cost/benefit can also include a
monetary evaluation of the health gain, even an evaluation of the economic value of the
extra years gained.
The limitations of these techniques are that from a technical point of view they are
expensive, complex and difficult to carry out, and from an ethical point of view they mask
Resource Allocation in Health Care
69
serious value judgements beneath their seeming neutrality. The fact that scarce resources
may be used to favour certain social groups to the exclusion of others solely on the basis of
economic criteria causes much ethical and social concern.
Appropriateness
According to traditional classifications of treatments, an appropriate treatment is one where
the expected benefits exceed the expected negative effects (risks) associated with the
treatment. One can distinguish between clinical and organisational appropriateness.
Clinical appropriateness – a treatment that is not effective cannot be appropriate, but a
treatment that has been scientifically corroborated may still be inappropriate if carried out
on a patient whose condition does not indicate its use in their particular circumstances.
For some years the question of the appropriate use of interventions has been the subject of
health service research, addressing the variation of the use of services. In the Unites States
it is estimated that certain medical procedures (including coronary angiography,
endoscopy, coronary artery by-pass surgery, and hysterectomy) have a rate of
inappropriate use that ranges from 15-30%.
Organisational appropriateness refers to the type of service provision (inpatient ward, day
unit, clinic) appropriate to the intervention offered in terms of patient safety and the most
economic use of resources. With the introduction of such payment methods as diagnostic
related groups (DRGs), the assessment of organisational appropriateness includes a review
(known as a ‘utilisation review’) of clinical paperwork to evaluate the medical necessity of
the treatment provided, the means of providing that treatment, and its duration. In this way
the intervention and the appropriate timescale for such an intervention can be evaluated,
and inappropriately long care identified.
8. Distributive criteria
Distributive criteria are a set of principles that establish an order of priority in the allocation
of healthcare resources. They do not address the question of what must be guaranteed to
individuals and society at large, but attempt to establish who (which individual, which
social group) can have access to such resources.
Need
In almost all methods of resource rationing there is an underlying principle of equality or
justice, in which resources must be allocated according to need. A key element of justice
requires that individuals with the same needs should receive the same treatment and that
greater need takes priority over lesser need. The principle of equality requires that those
with the greatest needs should have the greatest claim on resources. But how does one
evaluate which need is greater than another? By whose evaluation: the doctor or the patient?
Needs may be evaluated in terms of the consequences or results of interventions. A just
society would have the moral obligation to provide for the needs of each citizen for
treatment, but not for mere desires. Doctor and patient preferences may not coincide when,
for example, decisions about quality versus quantity of life have to be made. Even if the
concept of need is crucial, it remains ill defined and elastic. To what extent a society can
satisfy needs is closely related to the resources available. Science can help in classifying
needs on the basis of their consequences, independently of consideration of costs. The
relation between needs and resources is, however, a political choice.
Merit/demerit
According to the notion of merit, priority must go to those who deserve special
consideration. For example, older people may deserve more attention as they have
Bioethics in the 21st Century
70
worked and paid their taxes for longer than anyone. Or children, because they have not
yet had the chance to realise their human potential. Demerit is when judgments are made
about lifestyle in relation to certain risk factors that may justify the restriction of the
provision of health services. For example, heavy smokers, drug users and alcoholics may
be deemed unworthy of receiving certain healthcare interventions unless they change
their high-risk behaviour. The notion of merit/demerit is controversial if not
unacceptable, as it contradicts the enlightenment tenet of the brotherhood (or more
generally, siblinghood) of humanity.
Risk
The concept of risk is similar to that of need and refers to the deterioration of a situation that
could occur in the absence of an action or intervention. While the concept of need measures
the deficit in well-being of an individual, that of risk evaluates the consequences of a non-
intervention. The service providers possess the necessary information as to the relative
grades of risk.
Benefit
The communitarian sense of the principle of benefit is based on the discussion of collective
good and the use of common resources. It is not the individual characteristics of need or risk
that count have, but the final result for the community as a whole. Priority must be given to
those who can gain the maximum benefit from an intervention (the ‘capacity to benefit’).
The underlying principle is that scarce resources must be used in such a way as to maximise
the benefit not to the individual, but to the collective whole. According to this principle, it is
immoral not to consider the costs associated with intervention, as this would mean ignoring
sacrifices imposed on others.
The rule of rescue
The duty to intervene when a life is in imminent danger cannot be avoided. According to
this principle priority must be given to people in an emergency situation, or whose life is in
danger. In healthcare, as in other sectors, the application of this principle is considered a
fundamental indicator of our degree of civilisation. In fact, more importance is attached to
the act of assisting than to the outcome of the intervention; this creates a practical difficulty,
because it offers no assistance as to when to cease such interventions if the patient does not
die. To apply the rule of rescue in all cases of need would lead to an unsustainably
expensive system.
9. Theories of justice in healthcare
The technical criteria and particularly the distributive criteria that we have so far
considered represent attempts to find some shared rational bases with which to deal with
the problem of resource allocation in the health sphere. Apart from their apparent
neutrality, they require a more or less explicit assumption of values. This in turn requires
the consideration of theories of distributive justice, three in particular: individual liberty,
utilitarianism and egalitarianism. These theories have profoundly different visions of the
world, but are all inspired by two considerations that to a certain extent bind them
together:
- Justice, while relevant to the individual conscience, is not restricted to the discretion of
the individual, but represents the necessities of human coexistence
- Justice Relates to at least one of the following concepts: equality, liberty, responsibility,
equity.
Resource Allocation in Health Care
71
We will now examine different justice positions in more detail, both from a general point of
view and in relation to the healthcare sphere.
The theory of individual liberty
This philosophical approach attaches the utmost importance to individual liberty rights. As
a consequence, the state is required to support individual autonomy, both through rights
that promote the notion and through promotion of a market economy. The market is left the
task of redistributing resources in order to guarantee a level of dignified life for all,
supporting individual expectations. The state becomes a discreet bystander in society where
individual liberties take precedence, affording the fullest possible autonomy. For these
reasons, in a ‘pure’ liberal state, there is no ‘formal imperative’ to support social solidarity.
By definition the state is not obliged to tackle inequalities or to take on the task of supplying
social services such as healthcare or education. In the healthcare sphere the results are as
follows:
- There is no automatic ‘right’ to health for subjects
- The state is not morally obliged to provide any mechanism for the protection of health
- Health care is provided by means of a private contract between patient and healthcare
provider; the patient pays for the service and the doctor/patient relationship reflects this
- The quality and amount of healthcare received is dependent on the ability of the patient
to pay.
Utilitarian theory
The difficulties in the individual liberty theory lead to recourse to utilitarianism (or, more
generally, consequentialism), where individual liberty rights are subordinated to the
requirements to maximise utility, that is the state of ‘maximum happiness and minimal
misery’, or ‘the greatest happiness to the greatest number’. By definition, each action is
judged on the basis of the amount of utility it generates: the objective is the best possible
outcome for the largest amount of people for the minimum cost in terms of loss of utility.
Utilitarianism thus inverts the relationship between individual and society, favouring the
second. The state, in pursuing the goal of social utility, will favour the good of many over
the individual.
The provision of a public healthcare system is in keeping with the theory as a whole, bearing
in mind that the objective is the promotion of utility in terms of best possible health status
for the maximum number of people. From a societal perspective, treating many patients
who suffer from various conditions is viewed as equivalent to saving a few whose lives are
in danger.
The theory of egalitarianism
The egalitarian model includes a multiplicity of positions, sometimes philosophically and
politically far removed from each other. It brings together forms of socialism, social contract
theory, and communitarianism. Egalitarianism attaches maximum importance to the
equality of fundamental rights (to life, liberty, work, culture, and more) and to the
conditions that support and protect these rights. Collective and societal needs take
precedence over individual need in their theory, where upon public bodies have a pre-
eminent role in their duty to protect and support the needy. This is the antithesis of
individual libertarianism, as here a cooperative society is obliged to tackle inequality in all
its forms:
Bioethics in the 21st Century
72
‘Social and economic inequality must satisfy two conditions: firstly, they must be attached to offices
and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity; secondly, such inequalities
are justified only if they benefit the worst off’ (Rawls 1999)
Egalitarian healthcare is based on the ‘right to health’ – protection and promotion of
physical and mental integrity, healthcare and quality of life and of the environment are
seen as positive rights. The state must take on the protection and promotion of these
rights, through provision of universally accessible healthcare on the principle of
solidarity.
10. The conflicts and limits of philosophical approaches
Theories of justice and their implications for the organisation of healthcare and the problems
of rationing lend themselves to a series of considerations that illustrate both the strengths
and weaknesses of such approaches.
Theories of individual liberty have the advantage of guaranteeing maximum individual
freedom, but the price paid is high, particularly for those unable to participate fully in the
marketplace and those whose individual autonomy is weakened (the poor, the elderly, the
disabled, and others). Not only that, but the market imperative, far from promoting the
well-being of many, rewards selfishness and highlights economic inequalities.
Furthermore, freedom without responsibility is incomplete, the material and moral life
ruled by laws of supply and demand, with the only aim being the attainment of
individual freedom.
Utilitarianism has the advantage of subordinating individual advantages to the well being
of the many, the key objective being to maximise collective utility. The theory is not
without its criticisms, however. One of these is that in maximising utility to the collective
whole, there is potential to ignore the needs of the individual. There are also difficulties in
defining utility, given that this is a subjective term (as wanted in quality of life
assessments). The values involved, the burdens of expensive treatment and the clinical
benefit derived for the patient are incommensurable (not capable of being compared with
each other) unless there is a similar treatment alternative to use as comparator. Where
there is no alternative, the application of a utilitarian evaluation often creates more
problems than it resolves.
Egalitarianism seeks maximum social justice and protection of rights, but this theory also
incurs criticisms. First, what is the foundation of this equality? Based on the social
mechanism we want to refer to, social rights may be embedded in a more or less solid
foundation. In the case of the social contract, rights are normally attributed to members of
society or, by the same vein, are drawn from them. Yet social rights could also be attributed,
regardless of a social agreement, as fundamental human entitlements that cannot be
questioned, for example by the majority rule. Secondly, there is a risk that social dynamics
could prevail over the individual, forcing the latter to accept priorities and objectives that
are opposed to his or her own rights.
To conclude this part, when referring to rationing in health care, it can be argued that in
pluralistic societies there are continuous tensions and confrontations about what distributive
justice is about and how it can be guaranteed to citizens. An agreement based on the
philosophical approaches outlined above is likely to be unachievable, thus it is necessary to
explore other solutions to the problem of rationing of health care resources.
Resource Allocation in Health Care
73
11. The ethico-procedural approach
Normative approaches are important as they help identify fundamental values that are at
the core of political decision making, but they are not enough in themselves, as we saw
that different theories lead to different conclusions and there is no consensus on which is
the correct approach to take. Added to that is the fact that they are too abstract to be
applied as such to the reality of the world of healthcare institutions. Empirical approaches
are sometimes helpful, because they help identify what has been done and what could be
done, but not what should be done. In the absence of a broad consensus on the
acceptability of various guiding principles for the allocation of resources, the problem of
‘fair’ distribution becomes a question of ‘procedural justice’. An ethico-procedural
approach requires a decision making process that allows agreement on what is legitimate
and fair in terms of rationing. Rather than concentrating on principles and values that
should underpin decision making, the ethico-procedural approach asks how such
decisions are made. It involves a shifting of perspective from content to process. The
rationale on which the ethico-procedural approach is based is as follows: irrespective of
the financing or provision of health services, legitimate authority is conferred by the
influence of the democratic process on the system. A well known ethico-procedural
approach is ‘accountability for reasonableness’ (Daniel & Sabin 2002). The conditions
essential to the application of this approach are as follows:
1. Publicity condition: decisions regarding both direct and indirect limits to care and their
rationales must be publicly accessible.
2. Relevance condition: the rationales must rest on evidence, reasons, and principles that all
fair minded parties (managers, clinicians, patients, and consumers in general) can agree
are relevant to deciding how to meet the diverse needs of a covered population under
necessary resource constraints.
3. Appeals condition: there is a mechanism for challenge and dispute resolution regarding
limit setting decisions, including the opportunity for revising decisions in light of
further evidence or arguments.
4. Enforcement condition: there is either voluntary or public regulation of the process to
ensure that the first three conditions are met.
The advantages of this approach are many. For instance, there is an educational aspect. All
parties to the decision can appreciate the value of debate and deliberation in achieving a fair
decision under resource constraints. Furthermore, ‘accountability for reasonableness’ occupies
a middle ground between implicit rationing and explicit rationing. In a similar fashion to the
implicit approach, the principles on which the decision is made do not have to be disclosed
in advance; in contrast, as in the explicit approach, there is an appeal to greater transparency
in disclosing the reasons for decisions on rationing resources.
12. International experiences
At the international level, there are three basic strategies for rationing that have emerged.
The first (and until now the only example of its kind) is that employed by Oregon (USA),
which tackled two issues together: which treatments, and how much treatment, should
the state provide to its citizens whilst acting within its budgetary restraints? It is the most
explicit and radical form of rationing to date. A second strategy is that of the Netherlands
and Sweden, which defined a set of principles on which to base a healthcare package of
Bioethics in the 21st Century
74
available treatments for eligible citizens (the Netherlands), or to define priorities in the
supply of healthcare (Sweden). Neither country has managed to produce a list of available
treatments. A third strategy is that adopted by New Zealand and Great Britain, who are
not so much concerned with general principles as with putting into place a continual
process of drawing up guidelines and advice on appropriate treatment, supporting their
view that rationing should take place at the local and individual (micro) level.
Oregon
The US state of Oregon was the first to explicitly and fundamentally address problems of
rationing in healthcare. Following the death from leukaemia of a child who was denied a
transplant, the authorities set up a commission in 1989, the Health Services Commission, to
make recommendations on how the government funded Medicaid program could be
extended to include a section of the population who were not covered, and how to set
priorities within the Medicaid program itself. Having unsuccessfully tried an exclusively
technical approach (cost effectiveness analysis), they turned to a method that paired disease
with treatments and ordered these according to the gravity of the disease. Adjustments were
made to the list, according to what the Commission viewed as ‘reasonable’ and taking into
account the results of a public consultation. The ‘Oregon Plan’ was put into practice in 1994,
financing 565 treatments of the 696 listed. This list has since been amended and changes
were made to the originally identified priorities. The abandonment of the technical
approach, debated furiously by the medical profession and the public alike, has become a
symbol and a learning opportunity for many countries faced with difficult choices in
rationing.
The Netherlands
The Dutch government set up a Government Committee on Choices in Healthcare in 1990,
with the mandate remit of examining the problem of choices in healthcare and identifying
criteria for drawing up a basic package of healthcare treatments that should be offered to all
citizens with the necessary state or private health insurance. In their report, delivered in
1991, the Committee adopted a broad approach, with a method for evaluating the necessity
and availability of treatments, using four criteria/filters:
- Necessity
- Efficacy
- Efficiency
- Individual responsibility
The report also dealt with issues such as technological developments, waiting lists, the
appropriateness of treatment, and public involvement in priority setting. The Committee,
however, did not chose to produce a list of treatments for inclusion in the basic package,
but limited itself to applying the principles to a few controversial cases (in-vitro
fertilisation, homeopathic medicine, dental care for adults, sports injury services, care of
the elderly).
Sweden
The Swedish Parliamentary Priorities Commission was set up in 1992 to ‘discuss the role
of health services in its social context and to outline the fundamental ethical principles
that should guide the necessary prioritisation of resources’. An interim report entitled ‘No
Easy Choices’ was published in 1993 and circulated for comment. The Commission
Resource Allocation in Health Care
75
identified two types of approache to the problem of priority setting: a clinical approach
based on patient need, and a politico-administrative approach where scarce resources
needed to be considered. An interesting feature of the Swedish deliberations was the
development of an ethical platform based on certain principles to guide choices about
priorities:
- The human dignity principle
- The principle of need and solidarity
- The cost/efficiency principle
The final report did not contain a detailed list of services to be included or excluded, but it
did group treatments into five classes of descending priority. This approach is a method for
assisting in establishing priorities and helping those responsible to make decisions.
New Zealand
In 1992 a National Advisory Committee on Core Health Services was set up in New
Zealand to ‘make explicit which services everyone should have access to, in acceptable
terms and without unreasonable waiting times’. The practical difficulties in drawing up a
definitive list led the Committee to identify as essential those services already provided,
because these were deemed to be so as the ‘result of many years of reasonable good sense,
decisions founded on principle’. The Committee to developed guidelines for services of
general application, those with high costs, or those that are delivered in high volume. The
guidelines are shared at conferences, and efforts to involve the public in the debate are
notable.
Great Britain
In Great Britain there has been no national committee set up to address the problem of priority
setting in healthcare. The task is delegated at a local level, and local authorities must determine
an annual plan of services they wish to provide. Some have been more explicit in recent years
about which services they will provide, albeit thus far restricting access to marginal treatments
such as tattoo removal. At a national level there is an agency that evaluates treatments and
develops guidelines – the National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence – and another
that looks at service performance – the Health Care Commission.
Developing countries
Developing countries who have limited resources more than developed countries, are
obliged to make difficult choices in terms of healthcare provision and who to provide it
to. A specific example is the provision of antiretroviral treatment for AIDS sufferers in
Africa. Scarce resources, even when accounting for international help, do not permit
universal access to these drugs: choices have to be made. Governments can make such
choices on the basis of financial, socio-economic or medical criteria. As an alternative, or
in conjunction, they may be allocated on the basis of less formal, unfair criteria such as
individual preferences of decision makers, or political considerations (Rosen 2005).
Developing countries are advised by the World Bank to direct resources to public health
programs on the basis of economic and cost efficiency considerations, using tools such as
the Disability Adjusted Life Years tool (World Bank 1993). In any case, the
same considerations need to be taken into account: who decides? On the basis of which
criteria? On what values are decisions based? How democratic is the decision making
process?
Bioethics in the 21st Century
76
12. Conclusion
International experiences serve to highlight yet again just how difficult the issue of rationing
in healthcare is. Every country we have considered has found its own way to set priorities.
There is no consensus on principles, or on the methodologies used to make choices. General
principles, when they have to be applied in a practical way at a local or individual level,
have to be interpreted in light of circumstances and there is an ever-present ambiguity in
this application. It is not possible to predict all the situations in which the rules will have to
be applied, so a certain level of discretion and interpretation is required. All this confirms
that there are no easy solutions at hand (Holm 1998).
Coulter and Ham (2001) summarized international experience with health care priority
setting, and concluded:
‘there is a need to strengthen institutional processes in which decisions are taken; priority
setting processes must be transparent and accountable; clinical guidelines are increasingly being
used as a priority setting tool, but fair processes are needed for guidelines, just as for priority
setting more generally; the politics of rationing favours muddling through and the evasion of
responsibility, but this is unsustainable in an era of increasing public awareness about policy
making; priority setting policy making is an exercise in policy learning; and “accountability for
reasonableness” is a leading ethical framework for priority setting in institutions’.
Accordingly, a strategy for improving priority setting in health care entails improving
priority setting processes using guidance such as that provided by the “accountability for
reasonableness” approach. Without analysis and debate about public policy, people and
institutions can make arbitrary decisions about access to treatment, and implicit rationing
can foster both inequity and inefficiency.
13. References
Benelli E. (2003). The role of the media in steering public opinion on healthcare issues. Health
Policy, Vol. 63, No. 2, (February, 2003), pp.179-186, ISSN 0168 8510.
Coast, J., Donovan, J., Litva, A., Eyles, J., Morgand, K., Shepherd, M. & Tacchie, J. (2002). ‘If
there were a war tomorrow, we’d find the money’: contrasting perspectives on the
rationing of health care. Social Science & Medicine , Vol.54, No.12, (June 2002), pp.1839–
1851, ISSN 0277 9536.
Coulter A. & Ham C. (eds.) (2001). The Global Challenge of Health Care Rationing. Philadelphia:
Open University Press, Buckingham. ISBN 0 335 20463 5.
Daniels N. & Sabin E. (2002) Setting Limits Fairly. New York: Oxford University Press. eISBN
019514936X, ISBN 9780195149364, New York USA.
Gibson L., Martin D. & Singer P. (2005). Priority setting in hospitals: fairness, inclusiveness,
and the problem of institutional power differences. Social Science & Medicine, Vol.
61, No. 11, (December, 2005), pp. 2355-2362, ISSN 0277-9536.
Ham C. (1999). Tragic choices in health care: lessons from the Child B case. BMJ, Vol.319, No.
7219, (June, 1999), pp.1258-1261, ISSN 0959 8138.
Holm S. (1998). Goodbye to the simple solutions: the second phase of priority setting in
health care. BMJ, Vol. 317, No. 7164, (October, 1998),pp. 1000-1002, ISSN 0959 8138.
Resource Allocation in Health Care
77
Klein R. (1993). Dimensions of rationing: Who should do what?. BMJ, Vol.307, No. 6899,
(July, 1993), pp.309-311, ISSN 0959 8138.
Klein R. (1995). Priorities and rationing: Pragmatism or principles?. BMJ, Vol. 311, No. 7008,
(September, 1995), pp. 761-762, ISSN 0959 8138 .
Klein R., Day, P. & Redmayne, S. (1996). Managing scarcity. In Ham .C (ed.) State of Health
Series. Buckingham: Open University Press.
Litva A., Coast, J., Donovan, J., Eyles J., Shepherd, M., Tacchif J., Abelsong J, Morgane K.
(2002). ‘The public is too subjective’: public involvement at different levels of
health-care decision making. Social Science & Medicine, Vol. 54, no.12, (June, 2002),
pp.1825–1837, ISSN 0277 9536
Mossialos E. & King D. (1999). Citizens and rationing: analysis of a European survey. Health
Policy, Vol. 49, No.1-2, (October, 1999), pp. 75–135, ISSN 0168 8510.
Rawls J. (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, ISBN 0 674 01772 2.
Rosen, S., Sanne, I., Collier, A. &Simon, J.L. (2005). Hard choices: rationing antiretroviral
therapy for HIV/AIDS in Africa”. Lancet, Vol.365, No. 9456, (January, 2005), pp.
354-356, eISSN 1474 547X
Spagnolo A. et al (2004) Etica e giustizia in sanità. Milano: Mc Graw Hill 2004. World Bank
(1993) World Development Report: Investing in Health. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Deber R., Wiktorowicz M., Leatt P., Champagne F. (1994). Technology acquisition in
Canadian hospitals: how is it done, and where is the information coming from?”
Healthcare Management Forum, Vol. 7, No.4, pp. 18–27, ISSN 0840 4704 .
Deber R., Wiktorowicz M., Leatt P., Champagne F. (1995). Technology acquisition in
Canadian hospitals: how are we doing? Healthcare Management Forum, Vol.8, No. 2,
pp. 23–28, ISSN 0840 4704 .
Martin D.K., Shulman K., Santiago-Sorrell P., Singer P.A. (2003). Priority setting and hospital
strategic planning: a qualitative case study. Journal of Health Services Research and
Policy, Vol. 8 No.4, (2003), pp. 197–201 ISSN 1355-8196, .
Madden S., Martin D.K., Downey S., Singer P.A. (2005). Hospital priority setting with an
appeals process: a qualitative case study and evaluation. Health Policy, Vol. 73, No.
1, (July, 2005), pp.10–20, ISSN 0168 8510.
Hope T., Hicks N., Reynolds D.J.M., Crisp R., Griffiths S. (1998). Rationing and the Health
Authority. BMJ, Vol. 317, No.7165, (October, 1998), pp. 1067–9, ISSN 0959 8138.
Mitton C. & Donaldson C. (2002). Setting priorities in Canadian Regional Health
Authorities: a survey of key decision makers. Health Policy, Vol. 60, No. 1, (April,
2002), pp. 39–58, ISSN 0168 8510.
Singer P.A., Martin D.K., Giacomini M., Purdy L. (2000). Priority setting for new
technologies in medicine: a qualitative case study. BMJ , Vol.321, No.7272,
(November, 2000), pp. 1316–8, ISSN 0959 8138
Foy R., So J., Rous E., Scarffe J.H. (1999). Perspectives of commissioners and cancer
specialists in prioritising new cancer drugs: impact of the evidence threshold. BMJ,
Vol. 318, No. 7181, (February, 1999), pp. 456–9, ISSN 0959 8138.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
78
Martin D.K., Pater J.L., Singer P.A. (2001) “Priority setting decisions for new cancer drugs: a
qualitative study”. Lancet, Vol. 358, No. 9294, (November, 2001), pp. 1676–81, ISSN 0140
6736.
5
Ethics and Medically Assisted Procreation:
Reconsidering the Procreative Relationship
Laurent Ravez
Associate Professor at the University of Namur,
Director of the Interdisciplinary Center on Law, Ethics and Health Sciences
Belgium
1. Introduction
Since the birth of Louise Brown, the first ‘test-tube baby’ in the history of humanity, in July
1978, criticisms of MAP have not ceased. These criticisms are generally of two types. The
first relates to the medico-technical dimension of MAP and questions the effectiveness and
the safety of these biotechnologies. The second, which I will discuss here, relates to the
ethical dimension of MAP.
I will initially review the ethical criticisms of MAP, particularly in the Francophone
literature (although this is not significantly different in the Anglophone literature), and
suggest a way of classifying them, before going on to show the limits of such a classification.
These criticisms can be grouped into three categories: the medicalization of procreation, the
upheaval in the structures of filiation, and the status of the embryo. We will see that,
although this criticism is enlightening in certain cases, it is often excessive and, at the same
time, overlooks the effectiveness of procreation technologies in relieving the suffering of
sterile couples, as argued in previous work of mine (Ravez, 2006).
The suffering of the patients is an essential element in the ethical evaluation of MAP, but it
is not sufficient to construct a satisfactory axiological framework. I will show that such a
framework is essential. I will propose three components of such a framework, taking into
account the limits of criticism addressed at MAP, but also the limits of MAP itself.
2. The “medicalization” of procreation
The “medicalization” of procreation, of which some accuse MAP, is demonstrated through
two professional attitudes:
1. Formulation of the desire for a child as a need to be satisfied immediately,
2. Construal of sterility as pathology.
By “formulation of the desire for a child…”, I mean a deep misunderstanding of the
complexity which drives two human beings to join together and from which sometimes a
child emerges as a symbol of this union. For those who denounce this misunderstanding, it
is particularly limiting to imagine that the human desire for a child is only or mostly
biological, while trying to resolve possible mechanical failures that may have lead to this
sterility. To illustrate this, I quote Genevieve Delaisi de Parseval who wrote: “It is in the
mind that children are conceived”(Delaise de Parseval & Verdier, 1985, p.20).
Bioethics in the 21st Century
80
Viewed as a need, the child, when it is desired, must be obtained as fast as possible and
under the best possible conditions. Desire is formulated as a need everyone has the right to
have fulfilled. In this view, sterility constitutes an obstacle to the need to have a child, which
reproductive medicine has the duty to alleviate. Many authors that are critical of MAP argue
that “pathologizing” sterility is likely to eliminate the psychological suffering which is
sometimes the origin of this desire. It may be better to listen initially to what couples with
procreative difficulties are trying to say, before launching into a series of biomedical
procedures. In other words, sterility should be considered as a call to listen to the
relationship rather than or only as a call to medical techniques and procedures.
3. Upheaval in the social structures of filiation
MAP is also regularly accused in the Francophone literature of upsetting the traditional
structures of filiation, thus threatening to destroy the foundation of the human family.
Artificial insemination by sperm donor (AID) makes it possible to dissociate biological
procreation and social filiation (Mehl, 1999). With this dissociation, the social father is no
longer necessarily the biological father of the children carried by his partner. Socially
speaking, this situation is not new. Adoption or adultery may also produce such situations.
But the novelty is found in the involvement of science, specifically biotechnologies, in this
dissociation.
The development of in vitro fertilization (IVF) with donor gametes (ovules and/or
spermatozoa) has reinforced the difference between these two modes; biological procreation
and social filiation. It has been suggested that you can make a child today by rallying
different people to the cause and without anyone of them having sexual relations with
anyone else (Malherbe, 1997). You only need the collaboration of: one genetic father, who
provides the spermatozoa, one genetic mother for the ovules, one surrogate mother providing
her uterus, one adoptive mother who will become the socially recognized mother of the child,
one surrogate father, companion of the surrogate mother, and one adoptive father who will
become the legal father.
Given such dissociation of the elements of procreation, there is fear that the very basis of our
life as a society will be undermined. We have an amalgam of ideas concerning paternity,
situated somewhere between bloodlines, i.e., the parent of a child is the source of the
biological conception, and the will, i.e., the parent of a child is the source of the desire for,
and the choice of, a child. Behind these problems, we find a question present in social
anthropology: does one become a father through conception or filiation? In all human
societies, as regards filiation, there may be a primacy of the social over the biological. The
anthropologist Francoise Héritier states: “To sum up, there has never been a human society
up to the present that is based solely on the biological sense of filiation, or that would give a
purely biological relationship the same weight as the social sense of filiation” ( Héritier,
1996, p.258) . Actually, one could advance the idea that, in the view of social anthropology,
not only has the cleavage between social filiation and biological filiation existed everywhere
and always, but that this cleavage makes it possible to mitigate a situation of sterility, which
is often badly accepted socially.
4. The status of the embryo
As for the status of the embryo, there are many controversies about it. Opinion n°18
(September 16, 2002) of the Consultative Committee of Bioethics of Belgium (CCB)
Ethics and Medically Assisted Procreation: Reconsidering the Procreative Relationship
81
regarding research on human embryos in vitro notes the difficulty of agreeing on the moral
status of the embryo. It highlights five possibilities.
The first possibility is “intentionalist” or “externalist” and is defended by those who state
that the moral status of the embryo depends on the intentions of its (biological) parents.
According to this approach, the human embryo cannot be regarded as a person in its own
right unless it is part of a project of parenthood. Such a project is absent in the case of
supernumerary embryos or embryos created for experimental purposes. The second
possibility is to respect the embryo as a person as soon as the ovule has been fertilized;
this position is described as “internalist” or “creationist”. A third possibility offers moral
status to the embryo starting on the 15th day of development. The fourth possibility
corresponds to the oppinions defended in 1984 and 1986 by the National Consultative
Ethics Committee for Health and Life Sciences (CCNE) in France, according to which the
embryo is a potential person, i.e., it is not an actual person, but it has the potential to
become one and must be respected for this potentiality. The last possibility is known as
“gradualist”, in the sense that the human embryo has variable moral status according to
its degree of development: a 39 week foetus will have to be respected and protected more
than a 10 weeks old embryo.
The question of the moral status of the embryo is of paramount importance, because the
MAP techniques require the sacrifice of many embryos to carry out experiments. If we
regard the embryo as a person from the very first stages of its development, it is clear that
these experiments should cease.
Mehl writes: “In the end, scientists characterize the humanity of an embryo, not on an
essential definition, but rather by what they want to do with it. Paradox: in the past, science
tested the embryo to know what it could do with it. And now, it gives the embryo a status in
function of what it wants to do with it – authorize abortion, do research… So, the status of
the embryo by scientists seems fundamentally opportunistic” (Mehl, 1999, p.90-1). This
accusation of “opportunism” seems to structure the paper: “The Random Embryo”
[L’embryon aléatoire] (Hermitte, 1990). Her criticisms remind us of the moral principle: the
end does not justify the means. Applied to our subject, this principle could mean: whatever
‘benefits’ MAP may bring to couples, it is at the unjustifiable expense of some embryos. On
the other hand, those embryos may not exist from the start without MAP.
5. Suffering denied
Such criticisms help us recognize the weaknesses or even the dangers involved in the new
MAP techniques. Nevertheless, whatever the relative merits of such criticisms, they lack
insight into the suffering of sterile couples and into the effectiveness of new MAP
techniques to relieve this suffering.
Many clinicians note the suffering of sterile couples that want a child. The symptoms of this
distress are reminiscent of those of clinical depression. Muriel Flis-Trèves, a psychiatrist
who worked in the team of Prof Frydman (‘father’ of the first French ‘test-tube baby’), writes
on this subject: “The suffering which accompanies the diagnosis [of sterility] is intense. It is
often followed by a sudden withdrawal from the interests of daily existence, including
work, leisure, and even temporarily from sexual activities”. For men, Luc Roegiers notes
that the principal elements of this depression relate to “self doubt, his sexual prowess, his
capacity to transmit his genome” (Roegiers, 1994, p.169).
Bioethics in the 21st Century
82
Confronted with this suffering, MAP can bring relief to the suffering couple, quite simply by
providing the long awaited child. Positive testimony from couples helped by MAP is much
more difficult to find than complaints when the treatment fails. After the pregnancy has
finally started, couples often forget the particular circumstances which ushered in their
dearest wish. Muriel Flis-Trèves writes: “As soon as she becomes pregnant, the woman who
had recourse to MAP aspires to become a mother like any other. Her pregnancy is now
‘banal’ and she is confronted with the same anxieties, joys and hopes as all other women”
(Flis- Trèves, 1998, p.191). Béatrice Koeppel, a psychologist specializing in sterility has the
same position: “The first or second year after the birth of Amandine, the pregnancies with
IVF [in-vitro fertilization] seemed still extraordinary. This is not at all any longer the case.
On the contrary, the pregnancy is seen as banal. And it is what people appreciate with MAP:
to be like any future mother, to complain about restrictions, to consult books avidly, to be no
different from their peers” (Koeppel, 2000, p. 167-168). Soon after the pregnancy is
underway, even the idea of sterility becomes unbearable to many couples helped by MAP,
which makes discussion of their (former) sterility very difficult.
6. A “blank cheque” for MAP?
If the suffering of the sterile couples constitutes an essential element of the case for MAP,
it is still not reasonable to give the medical staff a “blank cheque”. It is important not to
lose sight of the fact that this kind of treatment is extremely dependant on technical and
scientific advances, in particular on biotechnologies. As Jacques Ellul – French sociologist
who had a great influence on the Francophone philosophy of technology - states, techno
scientific development is mainly guided by what we could call “technical imperatives” or
“the technician’s imperative”, which can be summarized as: “Anything that is possible
technically, should be done” (Ellul, 1954, pg, 122). The technology in itself is not unethical,
but is in fact outside of ethics, that is to say ethically undetermined as to the question of
its development.
Without ethical limits, MAP runs the risk of exacerbating the very problem it is trying to
resolve: the suffering of sterile couples. We have to acknowledge the successes of MAP;
we must also consider its failures and the suffering it may cause. This is suffering that the
authors who criticize MAP denounce, that is to say the suffering of couples for whom
MAP failed to offer the baby desired and for whom distress was increased further with
the procedure. On this point, G. Delaisi de Parseval writes: “[…] medical procedures
regarding infertility […] almost always produce sexual dysfunctions: taking of
temperatures, scheduled or forbidden sexual intercourse, analysis, exams, invasive
treatments that interfere with sexual desire or the achievement of intercourse, anxiety
induced by medicalization, […] sometimes compromise the balanced relationship within
the couple” (Delaisi de Parseval, 1985, p. 61).
On the one hand, we must recognize the effectiveness of MAP in fighting the plague of
sterility. On the other, we must avoid an approach which would justify the use of any and
all bio-technologies as regards human procreation, under the pretext of possible therapeutic
benefits. It is clear, however, that such an effort at clarity can only be effective given an
ethical framework, which is acceptable for both experts and patients, as well as for policy
makers. Today, MAP is integrated in the medical scene and I don’t intend to call into
question its provision, as do numerous authors. But, while accepting the principle of MAP,
Ethics and Medically Assisted Procreation: Reconsidering the Procreative Relationship
83
it is important to optimize its provision, not only on a technical level but also on an ethical
level.
7. Rethinking the procreation relationship and outlining a new axiological
framework
It would seem worthwhile to look further at the following framework:
1. Listen to those suffering from sterility, without necessarily endorsing everything they say;
2. Respect the complexity of the gift of life;
3. Consider technical and scientific advances not as an end in themselves, but as a means
to serve the couple’s desire for a child (keeping resource constraints in mind).
8. Listening to those suffering from sterility, without necessarily endorsing
everything they say
The challenge here is to encourage the parties involved in the area of reproductive medicine to
take the suffering and the stress related to sterility seriously, while leaving open the question
of whether or not this suffering is the cause or the consequences of this sterility. We find an
illustration of this position in the words of M. Bydlowski, one of the experts on the psychology
of infertility in France: “Years of work of consultation on infertility have confronted us with
the suffering of patients. […] Their distress is the consequence of their infertility. However, it
appeared to us that this suffering often exists before the symptomatic demand: the infertility
would then be the testimony of that suffering” (Bydlowski, 2000a, p. 119). If the infertility is
the result of mental distress, any benefit which MAP might cause may not eliminate the
existential malaise; this would need to be heard and explored before or unrelated to launching
a parenting project. Experts should find and use the means to differentiate among the requests
for a child which they receive, to identify what are calls for help from women or couples for
whom MAP is a band-aid for a wounded existence. Imagine a request for help, directed to a
doctor, to have a child, from a patient who in fact desperately seeks psychological healing, a
healing that may not occur even when a child might finally be born.
To illustrate this point, I turn to E. Jéronymidès, a therapist accompanying women with
procreative difficulties. She relates the case of a consultation with a woman looking for
medical assistance for secondary sterility. After two sessions, the patient, who had a very
difficult relationship with her husband, disappeared from care for several years. The therapist
later met her by chance. “Four years later, I bumped into her. She remembered me and seemed
happy to speak to me. She told me that she now had a two month old little boy. She had him
naturally, without MAP. She did not plan it, did not program it in any way. Then she recalled
that she had not contacted the hospital or MAP programme at the time, because her father had
fallen seriously ill. He had ended up being hospitalised and he died of cancer. ‘That’s the
reason’, she told me, ‘that I didn’t return to see you any more. I had a lot of difficulty accepting
the death’, she told me in a very serious tone, ‘I haven’t gotten over it yet and I’m not sure I
ever will. It’s very difficult losing your father. I was really very attached to him’. She said that
she doesn’t breast feed her child because she has a lot of work and that she has to leave her
house everyday. The tone she uses about the birth of the baby is neutral, with a hint of
bitterness. It’s as though the arrival of the child, and his presence with her could not, despite
everything, fill the place of the loss of her father” (Jéronymidès, 2001, p. 54).
Bioethics in the 21st Century
84
In other words, the suffering expressed at the fertility clinic can mask existential difficulties
– discord within the couple, difficulties with their parents, an unhappy childhood
(Bydlowski, 2000, Ravez, 2006) – that MAP, as such, has no way of detecting or resolving,
simply because MAP is a technology designed to treat biological dysfunctions. In that
context, the risk is high that professionals will assist the couple with techniques they
actually don’t want. An interdisciplinary approach at the MAP clinic, using a team of
doctors, nurses, psychologists, social workers and others can reduce this risk.
9. Respecting the complexity of the gift of life
To give life, whether it comes “naturally” or with the assistance of medical science, does not
only involve an efficient mobilization of gametes, a physiological process or a properly
functioning organism. The family context, the psychological aspects and the genealogy are
essential and must not be set aside. These elements are determining factors for a healthy
parental relationship. Bydlowski wrote: “The human child will result from the unique
mixture of the biological programming specific to the species - nucleic acids, molecules, cells
– with the pre-existent parental psyche – the secret desires, dreams, memories, and words”
(Bydlowsi, 2000b, p.24). Life presents a genetic or a biological dimension, but is also given to
the child in the midst of lived complexity, emotional and generational relations created by
their parents. MAP often undermines this complexity, as Brigitte-Fanny Cohen, a famous
French journalist who engaged herself in a MAP procedure, states: “My feeling, at least, is
that for […] agents of MAP, gynaecologists and biologists, I was just a womb and ovaries, at
best, a rate of FSH, a number of follicles or oocytes” (Cohen, 2001, p.67).
In the same manner, MAP can sometimes ignore important stakeholders such as husbands
or other partners and grandparents, due to the desire for a child. Husbands may not be
considered as agents in their own right in the procreative project, and are sometimes treated
as simple carriers of gametes. As the gynaecologist Pierre Fonty wrote provocatively: “These
men have the impression of being reduced to the rank of a sperm machine that produces on
demand, and to no longer being seen as beings animated by the desire for their partner,
having their own desires and sexual instincts” (Fonty, 2003, p. 100).
However, the situation is gradually changing, as certain practitioners of MAP seem to be
more aware lately of the non-biological importance of the father considerations are now
more often invoked. Delaisi de Parseval speaks about the “father who became a father
because of his own father’s regard of him; in short a father who lives through the experience
of paternity that is paradoxically, not very different from that of maternity” (Delaisi de
Parseval, 2003, p.110). Thus clearly “to be a father implies referring to their own role as a
son” (Clerget, 2003, p. 121). Paternity and fatherhood include both inheritance and
transmission.
10. Considering technical and scientific advances not as an end in
themselves, but as a means to serve the couple’s desire for a child (keeping
resource constraints in mind)
Contrary to some critiques of MAP, MAP offers increasingly effective ways for sterile
couples to have the desired child. But public health education is needed in relation to
Ethics and Medically Assisted Procreation: Reconsidering the Procreative Relationship
85
MAP. The methods and techniques of MAP need to be seen as ways of helping couples
have children and not as the cure for distress and angst in modern life. MAP does not
offer happiness, but does create the technical conditions to allow the couple’s happiness
to be expressed through and with the birth of a child. In other words, we can’t expect
MAP to offer love, a sense of balance, or harmony within the couple. Quite the contrary, if
the couple is fragile, the difficulties of MAP are likely to worsen the situation further.
To address this, an on-going dialogue should occur between the couple and the MAP
team.
11. Conclusion
I have argued here that criticisms of MAP ignore the fact that MAP may relieve the suffering
of sterile couples. However, I have argued that this does not constitute a sufficient reason to
give an ethical “blank cheque” to MAP, because MAP is a technology, and as such requires
ethical discernment. Three ethical suggestions were made here: listen to those suffering
from sterility, without necessarily endorsing everything they say; respect the complexity of
the gift of life; and consider technical and scientific advances not as an end, but as a means
to serve the couple’s desire for a child (keeping resource constraints in mind). More ethical
discussion of MAP is required.
12. References
Bydlowski, M. (2000a).La dette de vie. Itinéraire psychanalytique de la maternité. Paris: PUF,
ISBN-10: 2130503535, ISBN-13: 978-2130503538, Paris.
Bydlowski, M. (2000b).Je rêve un enfant. L’expérience intérieure de la maternité. Paris: Odile
Jacob, ISBN-10: 2738123996, ISBN-13: 978-2738123992, Paris.
Clerget, J. (2003). "L'home devenant pere", in Le pere, l'homme et le masculin en perinatalite. ed. P.
Marciano P (Rarnonville Saint-Agne: Eres, 2003), ISBN 2-7492-0126-8.
Cohen, B.H. (2001).Un bébé mais pas à tout prix. Les dessous de la médecine de la reproduction.
Paris: J.-C. Lattès, ISBN-10: 2290326682, ISBN-13: 978-2290326688.
Delaisi de Parseval, G & P. Verdier. (1994). Enfant de personne. Paris: Odile Jacob, France.
Delaisi de Parseval, G. (2003). "Les PMA ou 'Paternites medicalement assistees", in Le pere,
l'homrne et le masculin en perinatalite. ed. P. Marciano P Ramonville Saint-Agne: Eres,
ISBN 9782749201269.
Ellul, J. (1954).La Technique ou L’Enjeu du siècle. Paris: Armand Colin, 1954, Paris: Économica,
1990.
Flis-Trèves, M. (1998). Elles veulent un enfant. Paris: Albin Michel, ISBN 2226105441.
Fonty, B., & Hoguenin, J. (2003). Les pères n’ont rien à faire dans les maternités . Paris: Editions
générales First, ISBN 2-87691-747-5, France.
Héritier, F. (1996). Masculin-Féminin. La pensée de la différence . Paris: Odile Jacob, 1996, ISBN
2-7381-1605-1, Paris.
Hermitte, M.H. (1990). “L’embryon aléatoire”, in Le magasin des enfants, ed. J. Testart (Paris:
François Bourin, 1990), 238-265.
Jéronymidès, E. (2001). Elles aussi deviendront mères. Des femmes qui se sentent stériles. Paris:
Payot et Rivages, ISBN 2228893498 978 2228893497, France.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
86
Koeppel, B. (2000). La vie qui revient. Dans un service de fécondation in vitro. Ed. Calmann-Lévy
(10 mai 2000), ISBN-10: 2702131204, ISBN-13: 978-2702131206, France.
Malherbe,J.F. (1997). Pour une éthique de la medicine. Namur: Artel-Fides, ISBN 287374040X
9782873740405, Montreal, Canada.
Mehl, D. (1999). Naitre? : La controverse bioéthique . Paris: Bayard, 1999, ISBN 2227137738,
ISBN 9782227137738.
Ravez, L. (2006).Les amours auscultées: une nouvelle éthique pour l’assistance médicale à la
procreation. Paris: Les Ed. du Cerf, ISBN 2204079731 ISBN 9782204079730.
Roegiers, L. (2000). Les cigognes en crise (Bruxelles: De Boeck Université, 1994), ISBN 10:
2804119238, ISBN 13: 9782804119232 .4
6
Stem Cells: Ethical and Religious Issues
Farzaneh Zahedi-Anaraki and Bagher Larijani
Endocrinology and Metabolism Research Centre, Medical Ethics and History of Medicine
Research Centre, Tehran University of Medical Sciences
Iran
1. Introduction
Stem cells are capable of generating various tissue cells which can be used for therapeutic
approaches to debilitating and incurable disease. Even though many applications of stem
cells are under investigation, such research has raised high hopes and promises along with
warnings and ethical and religious questions in different societies. Generally, there is little
concern about using non-human or adult stem cells. However, embryonic stem cell research
has been confronted with questions from medical professionals, the public, religious groups,
and national and international organizations. The debate is partly related to "personhood"
and the notion of human dignity. Sources of stem cells, the moral status of human embryo,
the slippery slope toward commercialisation of human life, concerns about safety, germ line
intervention and the challenge of proportionality are some ethical issues.
Stem cell research is a promising but controversial issue on which many religions have
taken strong positions. The point at which human life begins is a pivotal challenge.
Conception, primitive streak development, implantation, ensoulment and birth are specific
stages in which different groups claim dignity begins in the course of human development.
In this chapter, we will review the history and scientific facts of stem cells in brief; then,
ethical considerations will be discussed. Our other aim is to clarify the religious debate on
the issue, particularly monotheistic perspectives. Some related international and national
guidelines will be reviewed in brief.
2. Definitions
In vivo (normal reproduction) or in vitro fertilization (IVF) of ova (female germ cells) and
spermatozoa (male germ cells) forms zygotes which contain the total genetic materials, one
half from the male DNA and one half from the female DNA. In favourable condition, the
zygote divides and forms the blastomere (8 cells), and then the blastocyst (120-150 cells)
around day five. Blastocysts consist of stem cells. At this stage, division of a blastocyst may
produce two or more normal human embryos. During the third week of human
development, the primitive streak, which is the primitive central nervous system, appears. At
this stage, the embryo is a unique entity which is no longer twinnable. Some scientists
consider this point as the moment when human life begins as such (Balint, 2001).
Stem cells in blastocysts are capable of differentiating along each of the germ layers of the
ectoderm (skin, nerves, brain), the mesoderm (bone, muscle), and the endoderm (lungs,
digestive system) (Hyun, 2008). After this stage of human foetus development, stem cells
Bioethics in the 21st Century
88
can be also found in different tissues but their capability is limited. For instance, as Lewis
(2009) stated, while mesenchymal stem cells are able to produce bone, cartilage, and muscle,
bone marrow stem cells can give rise only to white blood cells. The following part sheds
more light on the issue.
3. Stem cells: The facts and promises
Stem cells are undifferentiated cells with the capacity of renewal which can be used for
regeneration of body cells and tissues. Many potential therapeutic benefits are defined for
different types of stem cells. Based on the power of differentiation, stem cells can be
classified as totipotent, pluripotent, multipotent, and unipotent (table 1).
Term Definition Example Sources
Totipotent Able to produce an entire
being Blastomeres
Fertilized egg
drived cells (1-3
days embryo)
Pluripotent
Able to differentiate to germ
layers of ectoderm, mesoderm
and endoderm
Embryonic stem
cell 5-14 days embryo
Multi potent
Able to produce many cell
types and self-renew over the
lifetime of the being and over
many subsequent generations
if transplanted
Hematopoietic
stem cell
Cord blood, fetal
tissues, bone
marrow, Adult
stem cells
Unipotent
Able to differntiate to only
one lineage, and with limited
or no capacity of self-renewal
Neural stem cell Adult stem cells
Induced
pluripotent
(iPS)
Normal adult cells
reprogrammed to an
embryonic state, able to
produce all tissues
---
Derived from a
non-pluripotent
cell
Table 1. Stem cell classification and potential for differentiation.
Embryonic stem cells (ESCs) are able to produce all tissues and germ lines (sperm and eggs)
and to self-renew indefinitely. These pluripotent stem cells were first isolated in 1998.
However, the resources of ESCs are limited, and since human embryos have to be destroyed
for ESC production, many people oppose the use of this kind of stem cell for scientific
research or therapeutic approaches.
ESCs can be produced in the laboratory in two ways: by derivation from the inner cell mass
(ICM) of a blastocyst in a 5-14 days embryo, or by somatic cell nuclear transfer (SCNT).
SCNT or cloning, which was brought into public attention after cloning of the sheep "Dolly"
in 1997 (Wilmut et al., 1997), is also used as a technique to produce stem cells for basic
developmental biology research and cell-based therapies. Through cloning, the DNA of an
unfertilized egg is replaced with the DNA of the patient's cell. Although a Korean scientist
claimed to extract stem cells from human cloning in 2004 (Hwang, 2004, 2005), his work was
recognized as a scientific fraud later on (Kennedy, 2006). Although there are important
Stem Cells: Ethical and Religious Issues
89
concerns about the safety of cloning, as Fischbach and Fischbach state, stem cells produced
by therapeutic cloning have the advantage over those harvested from embryos resulting
from IVF or aborted foetuses in that the cells generated through therapeutic cloning are
genetically similar to the cells of the individual who donated the nucleus (Fischbach &
Fischbach, 2004), therefore they are immunologically matched to the patient, which avoids
problems of rejection (Coors, 2002; Weissman, 2002). Another source of pluripotent cells are
human embryonic germ (hEG) cells which are derived from the gonadal ridges of aborted
fetuses (Gogle et al., 2003; Balint, 2001).
Multipotent stem cells have a research history of more than 40 years and have been
successfully used for treatment of some disorders such as leukaemia for decades (Hyne,
2008). The use of these stem cells is surrounded with less ethical and religious debate since
they can be naturally found as adult stem cells throughout the body; however, their limited
potential of differentiation has restricted their practical uses. Also, mass production of
multipotent (and unipotent) stem cells is time consuming.
Inactive adult stem cells (SCs) exist in many tissues and need to be signalled.
Haematopoietic SCs, which are used for bone marrow transplantation in oncology, are a
good example of the use of this kind of SCs in cell and tissue transplantation. Medical waste,
such as amniotic fluid, placenta, menstrual blood, synovial fluid from knee, teeth,
liposuction aspirate, umbilical cords, is a source of adult stem cells (Lewis, 2009).
Induced pluripotent stem (iPS) cells have been reprogrammed with retroviruses to behave
like embryonic stem cells (Hyne, 2008). The methods that reprogram adult human cells to a
pluripotent state were described firstly by two groups of researchers from Japan and the
United States (Takahashi et al., 2007; Blow, 2008). Considering the mutagenicity of the
viruses and the potential to activate oncogenes, and the debate on their properties and
potential as embryonic stem cells, iPS cells are not used as a practical therapeutic agent yet
(Blow, 2008). Further experiments showed that reprogramming genes can be done in safer
ways without the use of viruses (Lewis, 2009).
The main potential use of stem cells in medicine is for cell and tissue replacement therapies.
There are hopes for lifelong treatment of disorders such as Huntington’s disease,
Parkinson’s disease, type 1 diabetes mellitus, myocardial infarction, spinal cord injuries,
stroke, chronic skin ulcers and burns by transplantation of stem cells. The utilization of stem
cells in the treatment of Alzheimer’s disease, avascular necrosis, neural deafness,
osteoarthritis, liver failure, and some autoimmune disorders including multiple sclerosis
(MS), rheumatoid arthritis, and systemic lupus erythematosus (SLE) is also under research.
Stem cell research may pave the way for designing novel approaches in regenerative
medicine. Since ESCs can proliferate without limit and can differentiate to any cell type,
they offer unprecedented access to tissues from the human body, and they have the
potential to provide an unlimited amount of tissue for transplantation therapies to treat a
wide range of degenerative diseases (National Institute of Health [NIH], 2006). Genetic
research, understanding of normal development, research on the differentiation of human
tissues, and birth defects investigations are other potential uses of stem cells. Stem cells can
be used for drug development and toxicity tests too. They can support research on safety
and efficacy of new drugs.
The therapeutic potential of stem cells has been publicized, and much related public
enthusiasm has been reflected in some stories and movies. There are scientific, ethical, legal,
religious, and social challenges for the use of stem cells for cell and tissue transplantation.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
90
The concerns should be addressed before the widespread use of this science and technology.
We intend to review main ethical issues and religious perspectives in the following sections.
4. Ethical issues
Moral arguments for and against stem cell research and therapy are many, regarding issues
such as the types of cells, the sources and techniques of production, and utilization. There
are few concerns about research on or therapeutic uses of adult stem cells. But embryonic
stem cells have been associated with serious ethical debates. The use of this new science and
technology for human reproduction has triggered ethics and policy disputes around the
world. Human cloning has been a cause of concern for ethicists, lawyers, religious scholars,
sociologists and politicians, among others.
There are different challenges in different societies. The study by Zarzeczny and Caulfield
(2009) confirms the complexity of the issues raised by stem cell research. The results of this
study, which was carried out in Canada, suggest some main themes, including:
theories/views on policy development, issues with focus on science and health, issues
related to the supply of embryos, debates on novel technologies such as cloning, non-
embryonic sources of stem cells, jurisdictional competition, intellectual property issues, the
need for guidelines and standards, research funding issues, and stem cell tourism
(Zarzeczny & Caulfield, 2009).
Related ethical issues may be discussed using different ethical approaches, such as
utilitarianism, deontology, and principlism. Each approach may justify or reject the use of
stem cells in research or therapeutics. For instance, according to the utilitarian approach, the
consequences of stem cell utilization should be assessed using the benefit to harm ratio as a
measure to accept or reject the new technology. In a deontologic (duty-based) approach, the
duty to help those who suffer or to save lives may permit research or therapy with stem
cells. In principle-based ethics, various principles should be discussed collectively to
evaluate the rightness or wrongness of use of stem cells.
People who oppose or support stem cell research can be philosophically divided into
different categories. For instance, some opponents emphasize the dignity of human beings
and that every person is an end and not only a means to some other end. This idea is
consistent with deontology. It means that every person, likely including a foetus, should be
respected and protected (balint, 2001). On the other hand, those who support research on
human stem cells, either in religious or secular bioethics, support the advantages of such
research to save human lives and the duty to relieve suffering in accordance with utilitarian
and duty-based approaches. Some even go so far as to state that such research is a "moral
imperative", considering the potential benefits of ameliorating human suffering (Balint,
2001).
There are important issues, such as respect for human dignity, which may influence these
discussions. Ethical issues will be discussed in the following without reference to the
philosophic basis.
4.1 Human dignity
In the process of stem cell research, stem cells must be extracted from the blastocyst, so the
human embryo is destroyed. Opponents of stem cell research claim that the destruction of
human embryos is morally equivalent to the killing of a human being.
The morality of destroying human embryos for the benefit of others is the main argument in
both secular and religious bioethics. Opinions regarding the ontological status of pre-
Stem Cells: Ethical and Religious Issues
91
implantation embryos vary widely. Some hold the "conceptionalist" view, according to
which the embryo is a "person", considering its potential to develop into a person. Others
believe that the embryo (and even the fetus) is a "non-person", and that it ought not to be
attributed much, if any, moral status (DeWert & Mummery, 2003).
There is another viewpoint of the "relative value" of human embryos, more than cells but
less than persons (Hinman, 2009). This view states that embryos deserve respect but not to
the same extent as a fully developed person. According to this moral argument, the moral
status of a human embryo gradually increases through its development in the uterus, and at
the point of birth it is entitled to enjoy full rights of human beings (United Nations
Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, 2004).
Another moral argument states that the status of embryos differs across milestones in the
process of embryonic development (United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural
Organization, 2004). In this argument, the question is at what point after fertilization of egg
by sperm the cell mass becomes a human being. This seems an ethical impasse which
science may not be able to resolve. For ethical decision making on stem cell research, we
should determine when a new human entity comes into existence. According to the
scientific facts, there are significant points for delineation of human embryos, including: the
moment of fertilization, the point of implantation in the uterus, the initial appearance of the
primitive streak (19 days), the beginning of heartbeat (23 days), the development of brain
waves (48 days), the point at which essential internal and external structures are complete
(56 days), the point at which the fetus begins to move (12-13 weeks) (Hinman, 2009), and the
point when the foetus would be viable outside the uterus (Balint, 2001).
As mentioned above, during the third week of human embryo development, the primitive
streak develops and three germ layers appear. Before this stage, embryos can split and
produce two or more embryos; however, after development of the primitive streak, the
embryo is a unique entity. In view of this fact, many believe that ontological individuality
starts at this point, hence the embryo can be used for research prior to this stage; up to 14
days of development (DeWert & Mummery, 2003).
Religious schools also make various points which will be discussed later. There is no doubt
that an embryo is a living being whether or not it merits human rights. However, an entity
would have the full rights and privileges of human beings when personhood begins.
There are different views on preimplantation embryos. Some bioethicists suggested "the
trajectory argument" to defend the human rights of a human embryo before implantation
(Hinman, 2009). According to this argument, since an early embryo has the potential to be a
human being in the future, it deserves protection. However, others claim that an entity
before implantation is no more than a seed. There is also another viewpoint, according to
which human embryos, even if they are not persons, deserve respect (Hinman, 2009). As
Hinman (2009, slide 20) concludes: "We can see some advocates of both sides of the hESCdebate as
accepting the general principle of respect for innocent human life; their disagreement may not be over
the principle, but over the way in which the principle is to be applied in particular cases."
The fear of "instrumentalization" of human embryos is a barrier to create embryos (DeWert
& Mummery, 2003). However, despite opposition to creation of embryos for research, there
are arguments in support of the use of spare embryos in the process of IVF as sources of
embryonic stem cells because such embryos would be destroyed anyway. Several hundred
thousands of unwanted embryos are discarded annually in IVF clinics. The use of such
embryos before the appearance of the primitive streak is supported by many ethicists.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
92
However, as stem cells that are derived from surplus embryos may cause immune rejection
when transplanted to a patient, some researchers emphasize the production of genetically
identical stem cells by the use of cloning or other techniques in order to avoid immune
rejection in transplantation (United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural
Organization, 2004).
The research carried out in Canada (Zarzeczny & Caulfield, 2009) shows that even though
issues related to the moral status of embryos continue to be a main issue in the literature on
stem cell research, discourses associated with the moral status of embryos may not receive
the same attention in social and other realms. For instance, while the moral status of
embryos has a central role in legal discourse, it plays a relatively minor role in print media
(Zarzeczny & Caulfield, 2009).
4.2 Safety
Many people are excited about the potential benefits of stem cells in clinical practice. There
are many claims about the power of stem cells as an unparalleled cure in medicine. Potential
benefits coupled with great public interest have produced significant pressures on scientists
to continue research. Along with the promises, stem cell science poses a threat to human
safety. As Dresser (2010) states, many claims about the therapeutic power of stem cells lack a
solid evidentiary foundation and many data are not examined in human clinical trials. In
other words, there is much to learn regarding the use of stem cells for the treatment of
diseases. Therefore, prior to any decision about using stem cells, their safety and efficacy
must be determined.
Risks of stem cell treatment, including tumors after stem cell injections (Amariglio et al.,
2009, as cited in Lindvall, et al., 2004, 2006), drew attention to safety issues and importance
of medical and ethical standards before clinical application of this new type of treatment.
Some who agree with stem cell research claim that such research is still in the early stages
and very far from clinical, therapeutic or reproductive uses.
Based on the principle of non-maleficence, harms to the embryo cannot be justified by future
benefits to society. It is also suggested that "… the harm done to the society by allowing the
destruction of embryos is more significant." (Balint, 2001).
4.3 Informed consent
Many scientists believe that people are misinformed about stem cells, their sources, their
potential benefits, and harms. It also seems that medical companies and industries are
optimistic about stem cell future. So, a demand for stem cell research and therapy has been
created in many societies. Some centres for the treatment are in countries with a lesser
ethical oversight, such as China and some Eastern European countries. An increase in stem
cell tourism has received attention in many countries (Zarzeczny, 2010). For these reasons,
disclosure of information to patients and their families is essential. Murdoch et al (2010,
page 21) have emphasized that such disclosure should have at least three elements:
"1. Disclose and discuss the potential for real physical, psychological, and economic harm from the
interventions and travel, including costs of the procedure relative to patient’s means.
2. Disclose and relay independent scientific evidence of risk or benefit for a defined intervention.
3. Disclose any evidence of ethical misconduct or questionable practices. This includes:
- Failure to supply local and national evidence of oversight.
- Engaging in questionable patient recruiting practices.
Stem Cells: Ethical and Religious Issues
93
- Clear misrepresentation, fraud, or patient abuse."
As mentioned before, the extra embryos of IVF clinics which are no longer wanted by the
parents are sources for stem cell research. Obtaining consent for such embryos is
problematic. There are questions of whether consent of biological parents is enough and
how the consent should be obtained and recorded. Also, as Balint (2001) states, there may be
emotional pressure on parents to consent. The parents' feelings and beliefs may also cause
additional anxiety and a sense of guilt about embryo donation for use in research.
Consent of gamete donors in cases of IVF should also be obtained and recorded. Many
ethicists are worried about risks to women who participate in the egg production process. In
the Korean cloning fraud, one ethical problem was related to the egg collection from the
subordinate women staff, which raised the issue of coercion and violation of their rights
(Longstaff et al., 2009, as cited in Saunders & Savulescu, 2008). From a feminist perspective,
the instrumental use of women in the process of the creation of embryos for research is an
important concern, since the creation of human embryos for research purposes requires the
harvesting of eggs from women (United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural
Organization, 2004). In animal cloning, there is a need for hundreds of unfertilized eggs to
produce one cloned embryo. In women, there has to be a period of hormone treatment
followed by invasive surgery to obtain oocytes for research purposes. In addition to the risk
of exploitation of women and commercialization of human eggs (United Nations
Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, 2004), there may be life-threatening risks
such as Ovarian Hyper-stimulation Syndrome (OHSS).
4.4 Slippery slope
A slippery slope argument is used by opponents of stem cell research, who cast doubt on
the morality of the use of stem cells by reasoning that if we accept the creation and
destroying of human embryos in the process of such research, there is no logical cut-off
point by which we can distinguish the point at which destroying a human embryo is
permissible. As Evers (2002) states, it may open the way to a slippery slope of dehumanizing
practices, such as embryo farms, cloned babies, the use of fetuses for spare parts, and the
commodification of human life.
The right to reproductive freedom in individualistic social systems may be used to justify
reproductive approaches with use of stem cells. Some opponents claim that eradication of
an entity like a human zygote is similar to abortion, which thus has a link to stem cell
research (Dresser, 2010). All societies should take a stand on the issue of eradication of
human embryos in the process of stem cell research.
4.5 Resource allocation and commercialization
There are many patients, scientists, politicians and even bioethicists who have paid tribute
to stem cell therapy and its hypes and hopes (Murdoch, et al., 2010), despite debates on
safety and efficacy. Commodification of human embryos is a concern expressed by many
ethicists. There may be loss of equity in access to stem cell benefits, as many people would
not be able to pay the high cost of this new treatment.
Resource allocation and distributive justice are related important issues. Limited resources
of health care systems raise questions about research priorities in many societies. Stem cell
research is expensive, and its outcome may not be useful for many patients or healthy
people. Thus, it could be argued that money can be more effectively spent for more
Bioethics in the 21st Century
94
important health care plans which cover a vast range of diseases and large numbers of the
general population.
However, many argue that banning stem cell research by governments would not stop such
research in the private sector. Private research can raise concerns about commercialization of
stem cell research, which may result in unfair distribution of benefits within society (Balint,
2001). So, some conclude that federal funding and support of research on embryonic stem
cells is the only approach that may guarantee the fair distribution of benefits (Balint, 2001).
Moreover, such policy can provide the way for more strict observance of ethical standards
by researchers.
Private sectors usually tend to allocate their resources to fields with high potential of
financial gain. However, priority of resource allocation in the public budget by governments
depends on some other factors, including: public health needs, scientific value of the
proposal, potential for advances in a particular area, distribution across diverse research
areas, and national training and infrastructure needs (Dresser, 2010). Funding stem cell
research is not considered a research priority in some countries, due to other health care
needs and limitations of health budget. Many underdeveloped or developing countries are
obligated to devote research funds to common disorders with high rates of mortality and
morbidity.
Stem cell tourism and fear of negative health consequences due to lack of enough oversight
are other concerns which have attracted special attention among ethicists and medical
practitioners. Such matters deserve separate discussion elsewhere, particularly as they are
not unique to stem cells.
4.6 Other issues
Many ethical issues associated with the use of stem cells apply to biomedical research
generally. Some issues which were discussed above, such as priorities of research and
allocation of limited resources, disclosure of truth about benefits and harms, and obtaining
consent, are prominent in stem cell research. Paying appropriate attention to research
integrity and related matters such as responsible conduct of research, ownership of data,
and authorship, are particularly emphasized in this field.
Another relevant general ethical issue is that of conflict of interests. There are financial
interests for researchers who work in this field. Honesty and openness of researchers, along
with appropriate independent review of research, are required.
Some issues are more specific and require special attention. For instance, stem cells can be
used for the study of normal development of human embryos and for genetic research.
Therefore, concerns about germ lines interventions attempting eugenics have been raised
(Balint, 2001).
An issue is the principle of subsidiarity, according to which stem cell research can be
ethically permissible only if there are no alternatives (DeWert & Mummery, 2003). Some
options have been discussed as alternatives of human embryonic stem cells, which consist
of: human embryonic germ (hEG) cells, adult stem cells, and xenotransplantation. For
comparison of these alternatives, many elements should be analysed, including: burdens
and/or risks, the chance of success and applicability, and the time-scale in which clinically
useful applications are to be expected (DeWert & Mummery, 2003). Low success rates of the
use of hEG cells and uncertain outcomes, and cross-species infections caused by
xenotransplantation and high rates of immunity rejection are the barriers for the first and
third alternatives.
Stem Cells: Ethical and Religious Issues
95
Adult stem cells experiments have had great success in recent decades. Scientists have been
studying them since the 1960s (United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural
Organization, 2004). Avoidance of immunity system rejection problems is an important
advantage of these cells. However, there are many doubts about their developmental
potential and their proliferation capacity as a substitute for embryonic stem cells (Kuehnle &
Goodell, 2002; Gavaghan, 2001).
As mentioned above, iPS cells are suggested as another alternative for human embryonic
stem cells (Hyne, 2008; Takahashi et al., 2007; Blow, 2008). Many experiments have been
done in recent years to test the efficacy and safety of this novel option (Lewis, 2009).
Aborted foetuses are suggested as sources for obtaining germ line stem cells, though critical
issues are raised (Balint, 2001). Women coercion, their safety, stem cell recipient safety,
informed consent issues, and vulnerability of the foetus are concerns which cause this
suggestion to remain controversial.
According to some advocates, stem cell research can save many lives. But the principle of
proportionality urges ethicists to weigh potential benefits and harms. Pursuance of medical
progress at any cost does not seem ethical.
5. Legislation and guidelines
During recent decades, stem cell research has posed a challenge for politicians and national
and international regulatory agencies. Despite challenges across different societies, stem cell
research continues to be conducted by researchers. The need for oversight and regulation to
prevent unethical conduct and negative outcomes is recognized by many scientists. As a
result, international and national bodies have tried to guide stem cell activities ethically.
General ethical guidelines such as the Belmont report (Department of Health, Education,
and Welfare, 1979), Helsinki declaration (The World Medical Association [WMA], 2008), and
International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects
(Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences [CIOMS], 2002) should be
observed by stem cell researchers. There are also specific stem cell guidelines and standards
internationally and in various countries.
Establishment of international ethical guidelines and legal frameworks for human cloning
was considered at the end of the 20th century. The issue of reproductive cloning was
discussed several times in United Nations agencies after the birth of Dolly in 1997. In 1998,
the United Nations General Assembly endorsed a Declaration in which reproductive
cloning of human beings was banned (United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural
Organization, 2004).
The Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights (The United Nations
Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization [UNESCO], 1997) (Section C-Article 11),
and the report of UNESCO’s International Bioethics Committee (IBC) on “The Use of
Embryonic Stem Cells in Therapeutic Research” (UNESCO, 2001) were compiled to address
these complex issues in different societies. Other international organizations such as the
World Health Organization (WHO) compiled relevant resolutions too.
The International Society for Stem Cell Research (ISSCR) has also tried to address relevant
scientific, cultural, religious, ethical, and legal differences across national borders by
preparation of the "Guidelines for the Conduct of Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research"
(ISSCR, 2006). The mission of the taskforce for compiling the guidelines was stated as: "…to
emphasize the responsibility of scientists to ensure that human stem cell research is carried out
Bioethics in the 21st Century
96
according to rigorous standards of research ethics, and to encourage uniform research practices that
should be followed by all human stem cell scientists globally." Due to the ever-increasing
therapeutic uses of stem cells in clinical practice, the "Guidelines for the Clinical Translation
of Stem Cells", were compiled in 2008 (ISSCR, 2008). The Guidelines address three major
areas of translational stem cell research: (a) cell processing and manufacture; (b) preclinical
studies; and (c) clinical research.
As to the disputes on the time when personhood starts, the guidelines and Acts determine
this. The United Kingdom's Human Fertilization and Embryology Act, for instance,
determines the point of primitive streak development as the point when human life begins
and research must be stopped (Balint, 2001, citation of Human Fertilization and Embryology
Act, 1990).
As Childress (2004) emphasizes, the connection between ethics and public policy remains
important. Two types of public policies have special relevance to human stem cell research,
public policies on use of governmental funds, and public policies on whether, apart from the
use of governmental funds, to permit, regulate, or prohibit activities such as human cloning
(Childress, 2004).
Many societies have attempted to characterize the legal status of the human embryo and
regulate stem cell research. Considerable differences exist between countries in the
regulation of stem cell research. In the United states, the National Bioethics Advisory
Committee (NBAC) decided that creation of embryos purely for research purposes was not
acceptable, while in the United Kingdom, the Human Fertilization and embryology
Authority permits the creation of embryos for research but the embryos must never be
implanted (Balint, 2001). In addition, in the United Kingdom and some other countries
where stem cell research under national regulations is permitted, there are standard
guidelines and recommendations for public and private sectors; there are no such
regulations and supervision in the US (Balint, 2001). The National Institutes of Health (NIH)
provided guidelines on Human stem cell research with the aim of "Removing Barriers to
Responsible Scientific Research Involving Human Stem Cells" (NIH, 2009).
In Canada, Human Pluripotent Stem Cell Research Guidelines released by the Canadian
Institutes of Health Research (Canadian Institutes of Health Research, 2010), and the
Assisted Human Reproductive Act (Health Canada, 2004), are the most important
regulations concerning the use of stem cells in research and reproductive technologies.
In Costa Rica and Germany, eradication of embryos for research purposes is prohibited.
Some countries, such as Belgium and the United Kingdom, allow research on surplus
embryos and created embryos within 14 days after fertilization. In Denmark and Japan,
while research on surplus embryos is permissible, the creation of embryos solely for
research purposes is prohibited (United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural
Organization, 2004). Many European countries have prohibited reproductive cloning, but
there is a wide spectrum of diverse religious and secular beliefs about that (Nippert, 2002).
In the Middle East, Iran, as a pioneer country in stem cell research (Ilkilic and Ertin, 2010;
Saniei and De Vries, 2008) that reported the establishment of a new stem cell line in 2003
(Baharvand et al, 2004), has recently established ethical guidelines for stem cell research and
treatments in the country (Nejad-Sarvari et al, 2011).
Banning public funding for stem cell research in some countries like the US caused some
worry about potential "brain drain", but funding the research costs by non-profit and private
sectors has offered many opportunities for scientists to follow such research in these
countries (Dresser, 2010).
Stem Cells: Ethical and Religious Issues
97
6. Religious perspectives
As mentioned before, determination of the moment at which human life begins is pivotal in
stem cell debates. Ensoulment is defined as the time when the entity becomes a human
being, based on many religions' perspectives, although the moment when the soul arrives is
long disputed.
Judaism considers the extracorporeal embryo in the preimplantation stage as genetic
material, so stem cell research is permissible according to most branches of Judaism
(Hinman, 2009; Childress, 2004; Ohara, 2003; Bioethics Advisory commission, 2000). A
human embryo is not considered as sacred until the fourth month of pregnancy, according
to most Jewish scholars (Pompe et al, 2005). Owing to this fact, research on stem cell and
human embryos is allowed in this period.
In Christianity, while the current dominant belief is that ensoulment occurs at the moment
of conception, the Roman Catholic theologian, Thomas Aquinas, believed that the soul
arrives around the third month of pregnancy (quickening). St. Augustine believed that
personhood begins with ensoulment at forty days of gestation, in accordance with
Aristotle's and Talmudic scholars' views (Balint, 2001). Although this opinion was accepted
by Popes innocent III (1211 AD) and Gregory XIII (1550 AD), increased use of abortion in the
18th century led to a change in the Church's thinking. As a result, Pope Pius IX decreed that
ensoulment occurs at fertilization, and his viewpoint was followed by the Orthodox Church
(Balint, 2001).
Currently, the Catholic Church believes personhood begins at conception (Daar et al., 2004).
Despite strong opposition of Catholics to stem cell research, Protestants have a wider range
of views (Childress, 2004; Ohara, 2003; Bioethics Advisory commission, 2000). Less
conservative Protestant Christians support stem cell research at least before the
development of the primitive streak at 14 days after fertilization (Fadel, 2007).
Most Muslim thinkers accept embryonic stem cell research (Childress, 2004; Ohara, 2003;
Bioethics Advisory commission, 2000), although there are obstacles to the research in some
Islamic countries (Ilkilic & Ertin, 2010). According to Islamic teachings, decisions on stem
cell research and cloning research should be based on advantages and limitations.
Considering inevitable consequences of reproductive cloning, it is prohibited by many
Muslim religious authorities; however, stem cell research and cloning for therapeutic
purposes is sometimes permissible with precautions in pre-ensoulment stages of fetus
development (Larijani & Zahedi, 2004). Most branches of Islam consider ensoulment as the
moment when the entity would have a full value of human beings, though the moral
singularity of humans occurs at implantation.
Holy Quran depicts the different stages of human development in the womb in verses 12-
14 of the chapter (Sura) of Al-Mumenoon (the Believers). Based on these verses and some
other Islamic resources, it is accepted by Muslim scholars that ensoulment takes place at
120 days after conception (Aksoy, 2005; Morrison and Khademhosseini, 2011). It is
noteworthy that in Islam human embryonic life is entitled to respect at any stages even
before the breathing of spirit into the fetus (Fadel, 2007); however, the respect grows as
the weeks pass until ensoulment when the child deserves the full respect of human being.
As Ilkilic and Ertin (2010) state “…the ensoulment gives the embryo an exceptional moral
status, which is decisive for the ethical assessment of any medical intervention affecting
the embryo.” So, experimental activities and therapeutic uses of stem cells are permissible
before ensoulment with necessary precautions when they are justifiable based on Islamic
Bioethics in the 21st Century
98
principles such as the public interest. Looking for scientific advancements and seeking
new treatments for human disorders may also apply to justify the use of human
embryonic stem cells (Fadel, 2007).
The source of stem cells has been considered by Islamic scholars in issuing fatwa (religious
decree) on permissibility of stem cell research. For instance, the scholars in the confereence
of the Muslim World League’s Islamic Jurisprudence Council held in Mecca in 2003 issued
that the use of stem cells for therapy or scientific research is permitted as long as the cells’
sources are permissible. Adults who consent, placenta or umbilical cord blood, excess
fertilized eggs produced during the course of IVF and spontaneously aborted embryos are
some acceptable resources, and intentionally aborted fetuses are forbidden to be used as a
source for stem cells (Fadel, 2007, citation of Muslim Word League, 2003).
7. Conclusion
Human stem cells have introduced many hopes in medicine. There are still many scientific
questions and unknowns surrounding the issue. Stem cell therapeutic options may not have
widespread application in the short term. Significant concerns exist about the ethical, social
and legal consequences of the use of the cells in research and treatment. Bioethicists,
religious leaders, regulatory bodies, and political bodies have discussed these matters and
attempted to address the consequences in appropriate ways. We aimed to review some
relevant challenges in this chapter, in the hope of strengthening the relation between science
and ethics. The various positions that different monotheistic religions have adopted
regarding this novel type of research were also reviewed in this chapter.
Stem cell science is rapidly evolving in the world; however, finding alternatives and
carrying out parallel research are important. While some scientists believe that ethical
concerns are barriers to scientific progress, others are worried about the harms and seek
new alternatives such as iPS cells which can address the issue of human dignity in the field
of stem cell research.
Given the promises of stem cell research, it seems that there is a conflict between the duty to
reduce suffering and the duty to respect human life. It is more sensible to regulate stem cell
research than to ban it. In countries with government-sponsored activities in the field of
stem cell research, ethical observance and control over private and public activities can be
more effectively maintained.
Stem cell markets and tourism should be controlled, regulated and supervised. The general
public should be engaged more actively in this discussion and in finding solutions and
guidelines.
8. References
Aksoy, S. (2005). Making regulations and drawing up legislation in Islamic countries under
conditions of uncertainty, with special reference to embryonic stem cell research.
Journal of Medical Ethics, Vol. 31, No. 7, pp. 399-403, ISSN 0306-6800, eISSN 1473
4257.
Amariglio, N; Hirshberg, A; Scheithauer, BW; Cohen, Y; Loewenthal, R; Trakhtenbrot, L., et
al. (2009). Donor-derived brain tumor following neural stem cell transplantation in
an ataxia telangiectasia patient. PLoS Med, Vol. 6, No. 2, (February 2009), e1000029,
pp. 0221-0231, ISSN 1549-1277, eISSN 1549-1676.
Stem Cells: Ethical and Religious Issues
99
Baharvand, H; Ashtiani, SK; Valojerdi, MR; Shahverdi, A; Taee, A; Sabour, D. (2004).
Establishment and in vitro differentiation of a new embryonic stem cell line from
human blastocyst. Differentiation, Vol. 72, no. 5, (Jun 2004), pp. 224-9, ISSN 0301
4681, eISSN 1432-0436.
Balint JA. (2001). Ethical issues in stem cell research. In: Ethics and Law in stem cell research
Panel, Date of access: February 25, 2011, Available from:
<http://www.albanylawreview.org/archives/65/3/EthicalIssuesinStemCellResea
rch.pdf >
Bioethics Advisory commission. (2000). Summary of presentations on religious perspectives
relating to research involving human stem cells, 1999. In: Ethical issues in human
stem cell research. Vol. 1, Bioethics Advisory commission, Rockville, June 2000, pp.
99-104.
Blow, N. (2008). Stem Cells: A new path to pluripotency. Nature, Vol. 451, No. 7180, (13
February 2008), pp. 858-858, ISSN 00280836, eISSN 1476-4687.
Canadian Institutes of Health Research. (2010). Updated Guidelines for Human Pluripotent
Stem Cell Research, June 30, 2010. Retrieved from
<http://www.cihr-irsc.gc.ca/e/42071.html >
Childress, JF. (2004). Human stem cell research: some controversies in bioethics and public
policy. Blood Cells, Molecules, and Diseases, Vol.32, (January-February 2004), pp. 100-
105, ISSN 1079-9796.
Coors ME. (2002). Therapeutic cloning: from consequences to contradiction. Journal of
Medicine and Philosophy, Vol.27, No.3, 2002. pp. 297-317, ISSN 0360-5310, eISSN
1744-5019.
Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS). (2002). International
Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects. Available
from: < http://www.cioms.ch/publications/layout_guide2002.pdf >
Daar, AS; Court, BE; Singer, PA. (2004). Stem cell research and transplantation: science
leading ethics. Transplant Proceedings, Vol.36, No.8, (Oct 2004), pp. 2504-2506, ISSN
0041-1345.
Department of Health, Education, and Welfare. (1979). The Belmont report. Available from:
< http://ohsr.od.nih.gov/guidelines/belmont.html>
DeWert, G; Mummery, CH. (2003). Human embryonic stem cells: research, ethics and
policy. Human Reproduction, Vol.18, No.4, (April 2003), pp. 672-682, eISSN 1460-
2350 , ISSN 0268-1161.
Dresser, R. (2010). Stem cell research as innovation: Expanding the Ethical and Policy
Conversation. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, Vol. 38, No. 2, pp. 332–341,
(Summer 2010), eISSN 1748 -720X.
Evers K. (2002). European perspectives on therapeutic cloning. The New England Journal of
Medicine, Vol.346, No.20, (May 16, 2002), pp. 1579-82, ISSN 0028-4793, eISSN 1533-
4406.
Fadel, HE. (2007). Prospects and Ethics of Stem Cell Research: An Islamic Perspective.
Journal of the Islamic Medical Association of North America (JIMA), Vol. 39, No. 2, pp.
73-83, ISSN 0899- 8299, eISSN 2160-9829.
Fischbach, GD; Fischbach RL. (2004). Stem cells: science, policy, and ethics. The Journal of
Clinical Investigation, Vol.14, No.10, (Nov 15, 2004), pp. 1364-1370, ISSN 0021-9738,
eISSN 1558-8238.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
100
Gavaghan, H. (2001). The promise of stem cells. Bulletin of the world Health Organization,
Vol.79, No.8, (2001), pp. 800-801, ISSN 0042 9686.
Gogle, CR; Guthrie, SM; Sanders, RC; Allen, WL; Scott, EW; Peterson, BE. (2003). An
overview of stem cell research and regulatory issues. Mayo Clinic Proceedings,
Vol.78, (August 2003), pp. 993-1003, ISSN 0025-6196, eISSN 1942-5546.
Health Canada. (2004). Assisted Human Reproduction Act (AHRA). Retrieved from:
<http://laws-lois.justice.gc.ca/eng/acts/A-13.4/FullText.html >
Hinman LM. (2009). The Ethics of Stem Cell Research. In: Lectures in Applied Ethics, Date of
access: March 27, 2011, Available from:
<http://ethics.sandiego.edu/Presentations/AppliedEthics/StemCellEthics/StemC
ellEthics.pdf>
Hwang, WS; Roh, SI; Lee, BC; Kang, SK; Kwon, DK; Kim, S; et al. (2005). Patient-Specific
Embryonic Stem Cells Derived from Human SCNT Blastocysts. Science, Vol. 308,
No. 5729, pp.1777-83, ISSN 0036-8075, eISSN 1095-9203.
Huwang, WS; Ryu, YJ; Park, JH; Park, ES; Lee, EG; Koo, JM; et al. (2004). Evidence of a
pluripotent human embryonic stem cell line derived from a cloned blastocysts.
Science, Vol. 303, No.5664, 2004, pp. 1669-1674, ISSN 0036 8075, eISSN 1095 9203
Hyun, I. (2008). Stem Cells, In: From Birth to Death and Bench to Clinic: The Hastings Center
Bioethics Briefing Book for Journalists, Policymakers, and Campaigns, Mary Crowley
(ed.), pp. 159-162, The Hastings Center, Retrieved from:
< http://www.thehastingscenter.org/Publications/BriefingBook/>
Ilkilic, I; Ertin, H. (2010). Ethical aspects of human embryonic stem cell research in the
islamic world: positions and reflections. Stem Cell Rev, Vol. 6, No. 2, (June 2010),
pp.151-61, ISSN 1550 -8943.
International Society for Stem Cell Research (ISSCR). (2006). Guidelines for the Conduct of
Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research. ISSCR, Retrieved from
< http://www.isscr.org/guidelines/ISSCRhESCguidelines2006.pdf >
International Society for Stem Cell Research (ISSCR). (2008). Guidelines for the Clinical
Translation of Stem Cells. ISSCR, Retrieved from:
< http://www.isscr.org/clinical_trans/pdfs/ISSCRGLClinicalTrans.pdf >
Kennedy, D. (2006). Editorial Retraction. Science, Vol. 335, No. 5759, pp. 335, ISSN 0036- 8075
eISSN 1095- 9203.
Kuehnle, L; Goodell, MA. (2002). The therapeutic potential of stem cells from adults. BMJ,
Vol.325, (Augest 2002), pp. 372-376, ISSN 1759 2151.
Larijani, B; Zahedi, F. (2004). Islamic perspective on human cloning and stem cell research.
Transplantation Proceedings, Vol.36, No.10, (Dec 2004), pp. 3188- 3189, ISSN 0041
1345.
Lewis, R. (2009). A stem cell primer. Biology Digest, Vol. 35, No. 9, pp. 11-19, (May 2009),
ISSN: 0095-2958.
Longstaff, H; Schuppli, CA; Preto, N; Lafrenière, D; McDonald, M. (2009). Scientists’
Perspectives on the Ethical Issues of Stem Cell Research. Stem Cell Rev and Rep, Vol.
5, No. 2, (June 2009), pp. 89–95, ISSN 1550-8943, eISSN 1558-6804.
Morrison, DWG; Khademhosseini, A. (access 2011). Stem Cell Science in Iran. Published by
the Iranian Studies Group (ISG) at Massachusetts Institute of Technology (MIT).
Available from:
<http://isgmit.org/projects-storage/StemCell/stem_cell_iran.pdf>
Stem Cells: Ethical and Religious Issues
101
Murdoch, CE; Scott, CT. (2010). Stem Cell Tourism and the Power of Hope, The American
Journal of Bioethics, Vol. 10, No. 5, (May 2010), pp.16-23, ISSN 1526-5161, eISSN
1536-0075 .
National Institute of Health [NIH]. (2006). Regenerative medicine 2006, Retrieved from
<http://stemcells.nih.gov/staticresources/info/scireport/PDFs/Regenerative_Me
dicine_2006.pdf >
National Institutes of Health (NIH). (2009). NIH Guidelines for Human Stem Cell Research.
Retrieved from < http://stemcells.nih.gov/policy/2009guidelines.htm >
Nejad-sarvari, N; Emami-razavi, SH; Larijani, B; Zahedi, F. (2011). The proposal of ethical
guidelines in stem cell research and treatments in Iran. Journal of Medical Ethics and
History of Medicine, vol. 4, No. 2, pp. 15-24, eISSN: 2008-0387. Available from: <
http://journals.tums.ac.ir/upload_files/pdf/17809.pdf> (in Farsi)
Nippert, I. (2002). The pros and cons of human therapeutic cloning in the public debate. J
Biotechnol , Vol.98, No.1, (Sep 2002), pp. 53-60, ISSN 0168 -1656.
Ohara, N. (2003). Ethical consideration of experimentation using living human embryo: the
Catholic Church’s position on human embryonic stem cell research and human
cloning. Clin Exp Obstet Gynecol, Vol.30, No.2-3, 2003, pp. 77–81, ISSN 0390-6663.
Pompe, S; Bader, M; Tannert, Christof. (2005). Stem-cell research: the state of the art. EMBO
Reports, Vol. 6, No. 4, (April 2005), pp. 297–300, ISSN 1469 221X.
Saniei M, De Vries R. (2008). Embryonic stem cell research in Iran: status and ethics. Indian J
Med Ethics, Vol. 5, No. 4, Oct-Dec 2008, pp. 181-4, ISSN 0974-8466.
Takahashi, K; Tanabe, K; Ohnuki, M; Narita, M; Ichisaka, T; Tomoda, K; Yamanaka, SH.
(2007). Induction of Pluripotent Stem Cells from Adult Human Fibroblasts by
Defined Factors. Cell, Vol. 131, No. 5, pp. 861-72, ISSN 0092-8674.
The United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO). (1997).
The Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights. Available
from:
<http://www.unesco.org/new/en/social-and-human-sciences/themes/bioethics
/human-genome-and-human-rights/>
The United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO). (2001).
The Use of Embryonic Stem Cells in Therapeutic Research. Available from: <
http://www.eubios.info/UNESCO/ibc2001sc.pdf >
The World Medical Association (WMA). (2008). Declaration of Helsinki. Available from: <
http://www.wma.net/en/30publications/10policies/b3/17c.pdf>
United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization. (2004). Human cloning:
ethical issues. France: UNESCO, SHS-2004. Retrieved from:
< http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0013/001359/135928e.pdf >
Weissman IL. (2002). Stem cells-scientific, medical and political issues. The New England
Journal of Medicine, Vol.346, No.20, 2002, pp. 1576-1579, ISSN 0028-4793, eISSN 1533
- 4406.
Wilmut, I; Schnieke, AE; McWhir, J; Kind, AJ; Campbell, KHS. (1997). Viable offspring
derived from fetal and adult mammalian cells. Nature, Vol. 385, No. 6619, pp. 810-
13, (27 February 1997), ISSN 0028- 0836, eISSN 1476 -4687.
Zarzeczny, A; Caulfield, T. (2009). Emerging Ethical, Legal and Social Issues Associated
with Stem Cell Research & and the Current Role of the Moral Status of the Embryo.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
102
Stem Cell Rev and Rep, Vol. 5, No.2, (June 2009), pp. 96-1ffi, ISSN 155-8943 eISSN
1558-6804.
Zarzeczny, A; Caulfield, T. (2010). Stem Cell Tourism and Doctors 1 Duties to Minors-A
View From Canada, The American Journal of Bioethics, Vol. 10, No.5, (May 2010),
pp.3-15, ISSN 1526-5161, eISSN1536-0075.
7
The “Cultural Differences”
Argument and Its Misconceptions:
The Return of Medical Truth-Telling in China
Jing-Bao Nie
1University of Otago
2(Adjunct/Visiting) Hunan Normal University and Peking University
1New Zealand
2China
1. Introduction
Cultural differences are real and arresting. They are noted, discussed and debated in
bioethics, as in contemporary social and political life in general. But cultural differences can
be very tricky to interpret. Their factual status, moral meanings and political implications
are rarely, if ever, as straightforward as they appear. Cultural differences can be seriously
misconceived, misinterpreted, misrepresented and misused in various ways. Empirically
problematic perceptions, ethically dubious judgments, and practically contentious
resolutions can easily become entangled when considering matters of cultural difference.
Many works on cross-cultural bioethics have often merely served to reinforce deeply rooted
stereotypes and myths regarding both Western and non-Western cultures, especially the
latter. A glaring example of such confusion is the appeal to perceived cultural differences as
an ethical justification for rejecting those norms perceived as originating in the West and
strongly advocated there – such as truth-telling by medical professionals, informed consent,
patients’ rights, women’s rights and human rights in general. It is argued and widely held in
certain circles that such practices and values are irrelevant and inapplicable to non-Western
societies and cultures.
In this paper, I will critically examine “the cultural differences” argument as it has been
formulated against medical truth-telling in the Chinese context. I will demonstrate that,
despite its popularity and apparent plausibility, the argument is seriously flawed both
descriptively and normatively. Elsewhere, through comparisons between China and the
West and supported by extensive primary Chinese materials, I have shown that direct
disclosure is far from culturally alien to China and that, on the contrary, there was once a
long, though forgotten, tradition of medical truth-telling in China (Nie 2011: Chapter 6).
Here, I argue that, even if medical truth-telling were culturally alien to China, as usually
assumed, ethical imperatives exist to reform the contemporary mainstream Chinese practice
of nondisclosure or indirect disclosure through family members. Moreover, I will offer a
Confucian defence of truth-telling as a fundamental ethical principle and a cardinal personal
and social virtue which physicians would do well to take seriously. In the process, I expose
some common intellectual barriers to cross-cultural understanding: dichotomizing different
Bioethics in the 21st Century
104
cultures as “radical others” to one another, promoting the tyranny of existing cultural
practices, and obscuring the real ethical issues at stake. To put the matter positively, I seek
to present the elements of a more adequate cross-cultural bioethics or a “transcultural
bioethics” – an ethics that resists cultural stereotypes, upholds the primacy of morality, and
acknowledges the richness, openness and internal heterogeneity of medical ethics in every
culture, whether in China or elsewhere.
2. The “cultural differences” argument
It is known far and wide that, in sharp contrast to most Western countries where
truthfulness constitutes an essential, even legally required, element of good medical
practice, medical professionals in contemporary China (including Hong Kong and Taiwan)
customarily withhold from patients crucial information about terminal illnesses such as
cancer. Any information given out is usually restricted to family members only, and is often
given in an overtly paternalist manner (e.g., Kleinman 1988: 152, Li and Chou 1997, Pang
1998, 1999, Tse, Chong and Fob 2003, Fan and Li 2004, Tang and Lee 2004, Zhu 2005, Zeng,
Li, Chen and Fang 2007, Tang et al. 2008).
This situation is not restricted to China. Nondisclosure or indirect disclosure through family
members is the mainstream practice in other Asian countries such as Japan and Nepal, as
well as in other parts of the world such as the Middle East and Eastern and Southern Europe
(e.g. Surbone 1992, Mitsuya 1997, Gongal et al. 2006, Mobereek et al 2008). In different
countries or within different ethnic groups within the same country, patients suffering from
cancer and other terminal illnesses receive very different levels of information about their
diagnosis, prognosis, and therapeutic options (e.g. Macklin 1999, Mitchell 1998, Mystakidou
et al. 2004, Tuckett 2004, Hancock et al. 2007, Surbone 2006, 2008). As the title of an editorial
by an Italian physician in the journal Support Care Cancer characterizes it, there is a
“persisting difference in truth telling throughout the world” (Surbone 2004).
According to more recent literature, although “there is a shift in truth-telling attitudes and
practice toward greater disclosure of diagnosis to cancer patients worldwide”, “partial and
nondisclosure is still common in many cultures that are centered on family and community
values” (Surbone 2008, 237). Thus this striking cultural difference—direct disclosure in most
Western countries vs. non-disclosure or indirect disclosure in most non-Western societies—
is still prevalent in the twenty-first century.
It is from acknowledging this cultural divide that the “cultural differences” view, that
opposes medical truth-telling in non-Western societies like China, has taken root. Two
Chinese medical ethicists put the issue succinctly: “In contrast [with the West], Chinese
medical ethics, even today, in theory and in practice, remains committed to hiding the truth
as well as to lying when necessary to achieve the family’s view of the best interests of the
patient” (Fan and Li 2004, 180). Direct truth-telling – the so-called “Western individualistic
mode” – is defined as being culturally alien to China and therefore morally unsound
because it violates so-called “Chinese familial values”.
In Japan, similar arguments have been put forward to reject medical truth-telling and
replace it by a family-centered style of informed consent. A major rationale behind the
distinction holds that the construal of the self in Japanese and Western culture is to be
defined as “interdependent vs. independent” respectively, or, to put it another way, in
terms of the family vs. the individual (Akabayashi and Slingsby 2006).
The “Cultural Differences” Argument and Its
Misconceptions: The Return of Medical Truth-Telling in China
105
The cultural differences argument against medical truth-telling can take a number of
different forms. In the Chinese context, one common argument, in the form of a syllogism,
goes like this:
Major premise: Different cultural norms and practices ought to be respected and maintained;
Minor premise: In contrast to the Western practice of direct disclosure regarding terminal
illness, the cultural norm in China is nondisclosure or indirect disclosure through family
members;
Conclusion: Therefore, medical professionals should refrain from telling Chinese patients the
truth about their terminal illness.
A more sophistical version of the argument goes thus:
First premise: Different cultural norms and practices ought to be respected and maintained;
Second premise: Chinese and Western cultures are fundamentally and radically different from
each other;
Third premise: Truth-telling is the Western cultural norm and is founded on individualistic
Western culture;
Fourth premise: Nondisclosure or indirect disclosure through family members is the Chinese
cultural norm and is founded on family-oriented Chinese culture;
Conclusion: Therefore, nondisclosure or indirect disclosure through family members should
be maintained and the practice of medical truth-telling rejected in China.
Whatever form it takes, the cultural differences argument consists of two core claims—one
descriptive and the other normative. The empirical or descriptive claim generalizes secrecy
and lying to the sick and dying as the representative and authentic cultural norm for
Chinese. The normative claim insists the practice of nondisclosure should be maintained in
order to respect perceived cultural differences. The descriptive claim is more widely held
than the normative one: those who subscribe to the normative claim always found their
position on the descriptive claim. Yet, those who accept the descriptive claim do not
necessarily agree with the normative claim; they are thus free to take an ethical position
against nondisclosure or indirect disclosure.
3. The current debate in China
Defying its contemporary stereotype as a monolithic, changeless nation or (in the famous
metaphor of Napoleon) a “sleeping lion”, China has always been in a state of flux. In the
past three or so decades – a period designated by the Chinese authorities as one of
“reform and openness” – the enormous social and economic transformations undergone
by China have had a profound impact on the history of both China and the world. On the
medical front, the patient-physician relationship, including the handling of medical
information relating to incurable and terminal diseases, has undergone a comparable
“revolution”. In the 1980s when I was a medical student and intern in China, it was
standard practice that patients were never told directly about their terminal illness. We
were instructed to conceal such a diagnosis and even lie to the sick and dying – for
instance, not to write the Chinese character for cancer, ai, on the patient’s card, but the
English abbreviation Ca. This cloak of secrecy surrounding the terminally ill was (and still
is) referred to by a special quasi-medical term – “protective medical treatment” (baohuxing
yiliao).
Since the 1990s and especially the early 2000s, however, the practice of withholding
crucial medical information has been challenged by patients, medical professionals, and
Bioethics in the 21st Century
106
the general public. An historic change is happening in China, a shift from secrecy and
lying toward honest and direct disclosure. In 2008, thirteen hospitals throughout China
and the premier Chinese journal Medicine and Philosophy jointly issued a series of
documents on informed consent (Yixue Yu Zhexu 2008, 1-12). One of them is entitled
“Guiding Principles on Truth-telling to and Consent from Cancer Patients”. While it
promotes only partial disclosure and insists on the necessity of “appropriate
confidentiality” (ibid, 7-8), this document indicates that the Chinese debate on the issue
has subtly shifted from whether patients should be told about their condition to when and
how they should be best informed.
In many ways, the Chinese debate closely resembles the Western debate of the 1960s and
1970s. As a matter of course, advocates of honest and direct disclosure take up the language
of rights – the right of the patient to know and decide. They also call attention to the damage
done by secrecy and concealing the truth from patients, as well as the benefits of honest
communication for both patients and physicians. On the other side of the debate, defenders
of nondisclosure, especially medical professionals and family members, emphasize the duty
to protect patients and, at least, to avoid doing harm. It is assumed that the communication
of complex and negative medical information is bad for patients’ morale, if not beyond their
intelligence. It has often been asserted, not only in the mass media but also in the medical
and academic literature, that telling the truth about terminal illness frightens and depresses
patients, deprives them of hope, and may even shorten their lives. It has been circulated that
young women are more vulnerable than other groups and are more likely to commit suicide
after learning of a negative prognosis.
The Chinese debate differs in one salient area from that conducted in the West several
decades ago: the issue of cultural differences. A common argument invoked to oppose
medical truth-telling in China lies in the appeal to cultural differences, in particular to
Chinese values and cultural context. Indeed, the invoking of the cultural argument raises a
number of questions regarding the current Chinese trend to honest and open disclosure. Is
this new development merely an aping of the contemporary Western norm? Is it a
consequence of Western cultural hegemony or even of bioethical imperialism? More
fundamentally, is this current shift in attitudes merely a change of fashion or is it based on
sound moral foundations? If the cultural differences argument against medical truth-telling
in China is valid, then current efforts to reform the still widespread practice of secrecy and
lying to the sick and dying are heading in the wrong direction.
But the argument against this reform is seriously flawed. In what follows, I reveal and
discuss a number of empirical and normative problems with this argument, however
appealing it may be on the surface.
4. Dicthotomizing east and west
The cultural differences argument is anchored in and perpetuates a deeply rooted and still
prevalent habit of thought: the dichotomizing of the West and the non-West as “radical
others” to one another (for a critical examination of what can be called the “fallacy of
dichotomizing cultures,” see Nie 2011, especially Chapters 1 and 2). In bioethics, this
polarization of East and West is manifested in the popular but specious idea of “Western
individualist bioethics” vs. “Asian communitarian bioethics” (Nie 2007). According to this
way of thinking, the dominant practice or official position of a given culture or social
group is deemed the authentic representative of the culture or social group concerned.
And the differences between and among cultures are perceived to be radical,
The “Cultural Differences” Argument and Its
Misconceptions: The Return of Medical Truth-Telling in China
107
fundamental, and largely incompatible with each other. As a result, the actual richness
and great internal plurality of a given culture and the complexity of cultural differences
within and between different groups are oversimplified and all too often seriously
distorted.
Drawing on and perpetuating this cultural dichotomy, the cultural differences argument
against medical truth-telling in the Chinese context has crudely distorted the historical and
socio-cultural realities of both China and the West. As the first part of my comparative study
of medical truth-telling has uncovered (Nie 2011, Chapter 6), historically speaking, it is
simply incorrect to claim that truth-telling is the representative Western cultural norm while
it is culturally alien to China. Far from being an age-old cultural tradition, in the West
medical truth-telling did not become the accepted standard until the 1970s or even later – it
has a history of a few decades only. And, on the other side, totally contrary to what has been
universally assumed and presented both inside and outside China, the traditional practice
and norm of Chinese culture and medical ethics was for physicians to disclose their
diagnosis and prognosis of terminal illness truthfully and directly to patients. A great deal
of primary historical material, including the biographies of ancient medical sages and
hundreds of celebrated physicians in different dynasties (Chen 1991[1723]), reveals a well-
established Chinese tradition of medical truth-telling that dates back at least twenty-six
centuries. Ironically, the contemporary mainstream Chinese practice of nondisclosure as a
“historical” phenomenon has a great deal to do with an older Western norm of concealing
medical information.
5. Chinese patients want to know the truth
Sociologically, the cultural differences view has assumed that Chinese patients are not only
kept in ignorance of their condition, but even prefer things this way. However, in total
contrast to this assumption, the great majority of Chinese people, like Westerners, want to
know the truth about their medical condition if suffering from serious illness.
In a telephone survey of 2674 Chinese households conducted in Hong Kong in 1995, 95% of
1138 interviewees aged between 18 and 65 indicated that they would prefer knowing their
medical diagnosis, even if the outlook was grave. The same proportion said they would
object if their family only was informed, while they themselves were not told. And 97% of
respondents would want to know their prognosis. The researchers concluded that the
patterns of preference shown by Chinese people in Hong Kong were “very similar to those
reported in studies on Western populations” (Fielding and Hung 1996). Taiwanese cancer
patients also expressed a strong preference for medical professionals to tell them the truth,
even before informing relatives (Tang and Lee 2004).
The same is true of mainland Chinese. In the early 2000s, speaking to a class of about 60
students, mostly postgraduates, in one of the leading ethics programs in China (in Hunan
Normal University located in Changsha, a central southern Chinese city), I asked if they
would like to know the truth if they were diagnosed with a terminal illness. A large majority
responded “yes” (about 50), and only a handful said “no”.
Despite some deficiencies in sample selections and research design, many extensive surveys
conducted throughout mainland China clearly indicate the preference of the great (or even
overwhelming) majority of Chinese patients suffering from terminal illness to be fully
apprised of the medical facts about their condition. A survey of 311 cancer patients in
Guangzhou in southeast China found that 72.99% believed that patients should be fully
Bioethics in the 21st Century
108
informed; 24.12% responded that the decision should depend on the wishes of the patients
themselves; and only 2.89% thought that patients should not be told about their cancer
diagnosis (Huang, Wang, Zhang, Lü and Li 2001). In a survey conducted in Shenyang,
northeast China, involving 198 hospitalized elderly cancer patients and 312 family members,
94% of patients and 82.7% of family members considered it essential for the truth to be told
about their terminal illness, and 97% of patients and 90.4% of family members believed that
the sharing of accurate medical information would improve the outcomes of treatment (Gao,
Zou and Yang 2006). Another survey of 302 cancer patients in Wuhan, central South China,
concluded that, in general, cancer patients are very keen to know the truth about their
illness and that the practice of “protective treatment” had resulted in distrust of medical
professionals and increased concerns about the seriousness of their condition (Zeng, Zhou,
Hong, Xiang, and Fang 2008).
However, the cultural difference view is accurate on one point in China, most medical
professionals and the majority of family members are unwilling to inform patients truthfully
(see the survey results presented below). Interestingly, when they were asked whether or
not they would like to know the truth if they were themselves had been diagnosed with
terminal illness, the great majority said they would want to know. A survey conducted in
2004 among 180 nurses in Shandong in Northeast coastal China showed that, when
imagining themselves as patients, they would prefer to be informed even though, as medical
professionals, they would hesitate to tell the truth to their own patients (Zhu 2005, 73). When
the nurses put themselves in their patients’ shoes, the overwhelming majority of them,
92.6%, preferred to know the diagnosis and prognosis of severe and terminal illness.
However, when asked whether they as nurses should inform their patients about their
adverse medical conditions, 71.6% said that they would withhold the truth. When asked to
imagine themselves as patients’ family members, only 2.5% would speak directly and
immediately, 69.1% would choose to tell the truth after prevaricating for a time, and 28.4%
would not disclose the condition in any circumstances (Ibid). A survey of 634 doctors and
nurses, conducted in Wuhan, again illustrates that medical professionals are reluctant to
speak candidly about cancer; that patients are aware of that they have insufficient
knowledge about their medical condition; and that physicians are inclined to let family
members, rather than patients, make important decisions (Zeng, Li, Chen, and Fang 2007).
As presented in the second section of this chapter, there are signs that the attitudes of
mainland Chinese medical professionals are changing. In 2009, lecturing to a class of 50
medical students at Peking University Health Science Centre, a leading medical school in
China located in Beijing, I asked the class whether they would tell patients about their
diagnosis and prognosis of terminal illness. The great majority answered “yes” by raising
their hands.
Other surveys confirm the disparity between patients’ wishes on the one hand and the
reluctance of family members on the other. In a survey of 175 patients and 238 family
members visiting a hospital clinic in Beijing (He, Wang, Tian, Zhou and Wang 2009), 42% of
patients wanted to be told immediately after a diagnosis of cancer was confirmed, 31.4%
wanted both patients and family members to be told together, and 26.3% preferred that only
family members be informed. However, only 2.1% of family members wanted the diagnosis
to be communicated directly to the patient – although 16.4% wanted both patients and
family members to be told. The contrasts in this survey are stark: whereas nearly three
quarters of patients wanted to be informed, either alone or with family members, more than
The “Cultural Differences” Argument and Its
Misconceptions: The Return of Medical Truth-Telling in China
109
three quarters of family members preferred that doctors inform them alone. In another
survey of 194 family members of recently diagnosed and hospitalized cancer patients, 57.7%
disagreed and 42.3% agreed that patients should be told (Sun, Li, Sun and Chang 2007). A
further survey of 382 patients and 482 relatives in Chengdu, Southwestern China, indicates
that cancer patients were more likely than family members to believe that patients should be
informed (early stage, 90.8% vs 69.9%; terminal stage, 60.5% vs 34.4%) and that most
participants preferred being told immediately after the diagnosis (Jiang, Li and Li et al.
2007).
One ethical question that arises from the disagreement between patients, their families, and
health care providers, disclosed by these studies is – what should be done when patients
want to know about their condition but medical professionals and relatives prefer to
withhold information and even lie to them? In Chinese culture, the Golden Rule taught by
Confucius is widely known and respected: “Do not impose on others what you do not wish
for yourself” (jishuo buyu, wushi yuren). If the general preference of Chinese people for
knowing the truth about terminal illness is interpreted as a wish not be lied to or to remain
in ignorance, then, according to the Golden Rule, it is ethically unacceptable for medical
professionals and relatives to impose on patients what they consider to be in the patients’
best interests, regardless of what patients themselves prefer.
Another ethical question arises over the significant proportion of patients who prefer not to
know about their prognosis. The short answer is that one should not impose the unpalatable
truth upon this group. To ignore the wish not to know is as wrong as dismissing the desire
to know. Perhaps pre-diagnosis informed consent is required to address this.
6. Harms done by secrecy and untruthfulness
As Tolstoy’s The Death of Ivan Ilyich and Solzhenitsyn’s Cancer Ward so vividly illustrate,
patients can often sense the seriousness of their illness even though both medical
professionals and relatives strive to keep the truth from them. My own experience as an
intern at a Chinese county hospital in the 1980s confirms the reality of this instinctive
awareness of their condition by patients. In fact, a major practical difficulty of hiding the
truth in these circumstances is that it is almost impossible to carry out successfully. Humans
communicate with each other not only through language, but also through their social
context, body language, and by many other means. The specialised wards and hospitals that
patients find themselves in, and the gestures of medical professionals, relatives and friends
can easily reveal the truth, despite all efforts to hide it. For the patients concerned, whatever
others may tell them, the secrecy surrounding their treatment reveals a truth of paramount
importance – their illness is serious.
Even if it were feasible to hide the truth from patients, the practice of nondisclosure—the
norm in China today—should be reversed because it is harmful to patients. On the one
hand, the advocates of nondisclosure have offered no compelling evidence of its benefits for
patients or their families. On the other hand, they often downplay or ignore the enormous
harm that the practice of nondisclosure and evasion has caused to patients, families, the
medical profession, and society at large. In addition to dismissing patients’ wish to know,
the practice of nondisclosure increases the feelings of abandonment of those suffering from
terminal illness and undermines the bonds of social trust, in particular those between
patients and medical professionals.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
110
For the cultural differences argument, the ethical rationale for disclosure turns on the
question of individual rights and personal autonomy. The norm of medical truth-telling is
thus arguably not applicable to those societies and cultures where the language of
individual rights and autonomy is largely absent. It is true that, politically, the shift from
nondisclosure to disclosure that occurred in most Western countries around the 1970s had a
great deal to do with the patients’ rights movement. And, in bioethics, disclosure and
informed consent are often theoretically justified out of respect for the patient’s autonomy, a
leading principle in the discipline. However, it is a mistake to regard the ethical rationale for
direct disclosure as wholly based on the notions of individual rights and autonomy. There
are other sound ethical reasons for direct disclosure—for instance, the principle of
beneficence, a fundamental value for almost every healing system and medical ethics
tradition worldwide.
Although often overlooked in cross-cultural discussions of truth-telling and informed
consent, a major factor in the historical shift toward disclosure in the West was the practical
necessity for effective (but not overly aggressive) therapeutic intervention. Jay Katz’s The
Silent World of Doctor and Patient, a classic of bioethics, has highlighted this crucial point. The
practice of truth-telling and informed consent is grounded not only in the principle of
autonomy or self-determination, but also in good therapeutic management in face of the
problem of uncertainty in medicine and the new challenges that have arisen in caring for
seriously ill and dying patients. Nondisclosure and untruthfulness are not ethically
justifiable because “[t]he iatrogenic deprivation of information makes a powerful
contribution to patients’ sense of abandonment.” (Ibid, 212)
Doctors’ ready retreat behind silence—apparent to patients by doctors’ demeanor when
they keep most of their thoughts to themselves, deprive patients of vital information, or pat
patients on the back and assure them that everything will be all right and they need not
worry—makes patients feel disregarded, ignored, patronized, and dismissed. (Ibid, 209-210)
In the words of two other authors, “Tacitly to impose silence, denial, deception, and
isolation upon the dying patient may itself cause suffering and bring about bereavement of
the dying, a state of premortem loneliness, emotional abandonment, and withdrawn
interest” (cited in Katz 2002: 222). The practice of nondisclosure thus serves medical
professionals’ interests more than those of patients. Disclosure and informed consent, on the
other hand, “seek to protect patients from the ravages and pain of abandonment” (Ibid, 208).
In the late nineteenth century, Tolstoy imaginatively rendered the detrimental effects of
lying to the patient with terminal illness:
Ivan Ilyich suffered most of all from the lie, the lie, for some reason, everyone accepted,
that he was not dying but was simply ill, and that if he stayed calm and underwent
treatment he could expect good results. Yet he knew that regardless of what was done,
all he could expect was more agonizing suffering and death. And he was tortured by
this lie, tortured by the fact that they refused to acknowledge what he and everyone else
knew, that they wanted to lie about his horrible condition and to force him to become a
part of that lie. This lie, a lie perpetrated on the eve of his death, a lie that was bound to
degrade the awesome, solemn act of his dying to the level of their social calls, their
draperies, and the sturgeon they ate for dinner, was an excruciating torture for Ivan
Ilyich. And, oddly enough, many times when they were going through their acts with
him he came within a hairbreadth of shouting: “Stop your lying! You and I know that
I’m dying, so at least stop lying!” (Tolstoy 1981, 102-103)
The “Cultural Differences” Argument and Its
Misconceptions: The Return of Medical Truth-Telling in China
111
Acknowledging to patients the seriousness of their medical condition may not be caring or
healing in itself (although one could argue that it is), but it is at least the starting point for
any good caring and healing regime. Medical professionals and other caregivers may lack
the power to truly relieve the suffering of gravely ill and dying patients, but, as Ivan Ilyich
urged, they can “at least stop lying”.
Those who defend the practice of nondisclosure in China may contest that Chinese patients
do not feel the abandonment, loneliness and agony that Ivan Ilyich or Western patients
experienced when deprived of critical medical information. But, unless convincing empirical
evidence is provided for this imagined cultural difference, one must assume that Chinese
patients do not differ radically from their counterparts in the West in this regard.
The major concern in contemporary China, as in the West a few decades ago, is that open
and direct disclosure may harm patients. Yet, in Western countries where medical truth-
telling has now become firmly established it has been shown that concerns over the
presumed psychological and physical harms to patients are in most cases unfounded. And it
need hardly be said that such paternalistic attitudes seriously underestimate the intelligence,
resilience and resolve of patients suffering from terminal illness in dealing with the realities
of death and dying.
Lying has a further serious detrimental effect – the harm done to the patient-physician
relationship. Social trust is the foundation of any good communal life. Lying to patients
undermines their trust in medical professionals, just as lying in public life does lethal
damage to the sustaining and nourishing of social trust. So nondisclosure and
untruthfulness can hardly be justified by either “individualistic” or “communitarian”
values.
7. The question of family
As we have seen, a key element of the cultural difference view that defends the Chinese
practice of nondisclosure stems from a highly legitimate and important concern – the
interests and integrity of the family. However, a number of the assumptions and assertions
involved in defending this concern are empirically problematic and ethically misleading.
Although detailed discussion of the role of the family in relation to bioethics from a
Chinese-Western comparative perspective needs much more space, I wish to at least raise a
few questions on the subject here.
Firstly, based on the popular dichotomy of China and the West as “radical others”, the
cultural differences argument posits a cross-cultural distinction, asserting that the family is
central or even unique in Chinese culture but not so in the West. Those who would make
this assertion are very selective and arbitrary in their choice ofcultural traditions within
China and the West. Several major Chinese schools of thought and socio-political
movements such as Daoism, Moism, the New Culture Movement in the early twentieth
century and Chinese socialism – both in its ideology and in its political-economic system –
have all challenged the primacy of the family. At the same time, the essential role of the
family in Western civilization (e.g., in Judeo-Christian tradition) as well as in Western
bioethics has very often been downplayed and even dismissed. The truth is that, both as an
essential social institution and as a cardinal moral value, the family has always been a vital
element of any society or culture, whether in the East or in the West.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
112
Secondly, the practice of nondisclosure in China has been attributed to the value placed by
Confucianism on the primacy of the family. Yet, as I showed elsewhere (Nie 2011), the well-
established Chinese tradition of open and direct disclosure on medical matters was
endorsed by one of the key Confucian moral ideals, that of cheng (truthfulness, sincerity).
Thirdly and most importantly, the argument about the family assumes that the practice of
nondisclosure or indirect disclosure is more beneficial to the family than that of direct
disclosure. However, there is no empirical evidence to support this. Secrecy and lying can be
very harmful to family relationships as vividly portrayed, once again, in Tolstoy’s Death of
Ivan Illich. On the contrary, a strong case can be made that direct disclosure may better serve
families affected, and family values, in than nondisclosure and deceit.
Drawing on the classic work of Sissela Bok (1989 [1978]), who condemns deception in public
life, including lying to dying patients, as both ethically unjustifiable and practically harmful,
some Western scholars have challenged the “cultural difference” view of truth-telling to the
sick and dying in the Chinese context (e.g. Wear 2007). Still, we are warned to “studiously
avoid presuming to take a firm stand” on lobbying for truth-telling as a general rule in Chinese
society because the available data allegedly do not give a clear picture on two crucial points at
the heart of the realted ethical dilemma: what Chinese patients typically want, and whether
medical truth-telling will undermine the traditional Chinese family (Ibid).
However, as discussed above, we do have reliable data on the preference of the majority of
Chinese to know the truth about terminal illness. As for the relationship between truth-
telling and the family, the practice of direct disclosure in the West over the past several
decades suggests that disclosure in itself does not necessarily harm the family as a social
institution or as a locus of moral value. Truth-telling can empower family members to better
support dying patients, attend to the needs and wellbeing of their loved ones, and diminish
the feelings of abandonment and loneliness experienced by their suffering relative. In such
difficult times when, as a Chinese saying expresses it, the whole family suffers if a single
member is in pain (yiren xiangyu, mandang bule), truth-telling can strengthen, rather than
weaken, the bonds of love and interdependence among family members.
8. The Confucian morality of truthfulness and its ethical implication for
medical practice
The contemporary Chinese practice of non-disclosure or indirect disclosure has been
presented and argued to be justifiable and preferable according to Confucianism (e.g. Fan
and Li 2004). However, this interpretation of Confucianism is historically groundless (see
Nie 2011: Chapter 6) and normatively wrong and misleading. In other words, the
contemporary dominant – though challenged – practice in China cannot be justified by the
ethical principles and ideals of major Chinese moral, political and spiritual traditions such
as Confucianism.
In Confucianism, the highest moral ideals or principles are ren (humanity, humaneness), yi
(righteousness) and li (the correct performance of rites), although scholars disagree about
which has primacy (for a discussion of Confucian professional ethics of medicine, see Nie
2011: Chapters 11 and 12). While chengxin (truthfulness, honesty, trustworthiness or
sincerity), another virtue highly regarded in Confucianism, is often used as a single phrase
in modern Chinese, in classical Chinese cheng and xin are two closely related but different
concepts, especially in Confucian tradition. Confucius himself discussed xin frequently in
The “Cultural Differences” Argument and Its
Misconceptions: The Return of Medical Truth-Telling in China
113
the Analects. While it rarely appears in the Analects, cheng is a key term in Neo-Confucianism
and in other two Confucian classics, The Great Learning and The Doctrine of the Means.
The necessity of acquiring xin is a major theme in the Analects. According to a contemporary
Chinese scholar, the term – meaning honesty, faithfulness and truthfulness – appears at least
24 times in the “Bible of China” (Yang1980, 257). The other fundamental Confucian concepts
of ren, li and yi appear 108, 74, and 24 times in the Analects respectively (Ibid, 221, 311, 291).
Since the early Han Dynasty (c. the 2nd century BCE) when Confucianism was established as
the official ideology of the state, xin has been regarded as the fifth of the Five Cardinal
Virtues (wuchang) of Confucianism. Confucius used the metaphor of the yoke or horse
harness to illustrate the importance of honesty and truthfulness for both individuals and
social life (II, 23):
The Master said, “I do not know how a man without truthfulness is to get on. How can a
large carriage be made to go without the cross-bar for yoking the oxen to, or a small carriage
without the arrangement for yoking the horses?” (Legge 1971 [1893], 153)
Confucius placed a very high value on xin, stating that “No human being can stand without
truthfulness” (XII, 7) and, in The Great Learning (III, 3), “In communication with people, he
[ie, the truthful person] abides in faithfulness.”
While the term cheng (sincerity, authenticity or truthfulness) is rarely mentioned in the
Analects, it is a crucial concept in other Confucian classics and for Confucianism in general.
The term embodies a complex nexus of metaphysical, ethical, psychological, and spiritual
meanings, as the following quote from The Doctrine of the Mean (XX, 18) indicates:
Sincerity [truthfulness] is the way of Heaven. The attainment of sincerity is the way of men.
He who possesses sincerity, is he who, without an effort, hits what is right, and apprehends,
without the exercise of thought; – he is the sage who naturally and easily embodies the right
way. He who attains to sincerity, is he who chooses what is good, and firmly holds it fast.
(Legge 1971[1893], 413; emphasis original)
Philosophically, this passage is comparable to Kant’s discussion of “the good will”. Still,
however sophisticated the ramifications of the term may be, at the most basic level, like xin,
cheng equates to one of the most fundamental moral maxims endorsed by most if not all
human societies and ethical systems: be honest and, at the very least, do not deceive.
It is important to point out that, while the ethical principle of truthfulness is essential for
Confucianism, this value is not absolute. In certain situations, concealing the truth is
certainly an acceptable course, even a praiseworthy one. According to a story in the Analects
(XIII, 18):
The duke of Sheh [Ye], informed Confucius, saying, “Among us here there are those who
may be styled upright [or just] in their conduct. If their father has stolen a sheep, they will
bear witness to the fact.”
Confucius said, “Among us, in our part of the country, those who are upright are different
from this. The father conceals the misconduct of the son, and the son conceals the
misconduct of the father. Uprightness [or justice] is to be found in this.” (Legge 1971 [1893],
270).
In one of the early dialogues of Plato, Euthyphro, Socrates challenged a similar belief that it is
right to indict one’s father for committing manslaughter. Many commentators, ancient,
modern and contemporary, have debated the rationale behind the position taken by
Confucius here. For the purposes of our discussion, the point is that, in striking contrast to
Kant’s deontological ethics, truthfulness is not an absolute value in Confucianism.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
114
What are the implications of the Confucian morality of truthfulness for medical practice
regarding whether medical professionals should tell the patients the dire diagnosis and
prognosis? First and foremost, as a general maxim for medical practice, healthcare
professionals should abide by truthfulness as strictly as they can, following the consensus
established by traditional Chinese medical ethics over the centuries. To deceive patients for
motives of personal gain is always absolutely wrong and morally corrupt. Even when
delivering painful news, as in the diagnosis and prognosis of terminal illness, truthfulness
should not be easily set aside and medical practitioners should practice open and direct
disclosure as a general rule, following the norm of the ancient Chinese medical sages.
Moreover, following the example of the systematic modern Chinese text on the professional
ethics of medicine (Nie 2011: Chapter 6), a careful distinction should be made between lying
(or deception) and concealing the truth. Ethically, there is a subtle but significant difference
between these two; in the words of a Chinese idiom, “an error the breadth of a single hair
can lead someone astray by a thousand miles”.
The principle of truthfulness should be breached only in exceptional circumstances, such as
when complete candour would lead to serious danger for the patient, such as confirmed risk
of suicide due to breaking bad news. For Confucian medical ethics the highest ideal is ren, as
articulated in the ethical definition of healing: “medicine as the art of humanity or
humaneness”. Nevertheless, the burden of proof should fall on those who believe that the
principle of open and direct disclosure should be breached in order to avoid perceived risks
to the patient. I have presented overwhelming evidence in this chapter that the great
majority of Chinese patients want information about their medical condition. And we have
seen that a conspiracy of silence or outright deception by family members and medical
professionals can do great harm to patients. So those cases in which the truth needs to be
concealed are likely to be rare. Cases where patients need to be deceived should be even
rarer.
Yet, while most Chinese patients would prefer to know the truth about their medical
condition, there is still a significant proportion of patients who prefer to be kept in ignorance
about their prognosis. This raises a moral question as well as a medical challenge. As
mentioned in Section 5, the short answer is that one should not impose the unpalatable truth
upon this group; and to ignore a patient’s wish not to know is as wrong as dismissing their
legitimate desire to know. From a cross-cultural perspective, patients who subscribe to the
“ignorance is bliss” mentality can be found not only in China but also in the West. On this
point, it is also worth pointing out that, as far as Confucianism is concerned, the concept of
cheng includes a criticism and even a condemnation of self-deception.
The radical level of disagreement revealed in the hospital survey results cited above
provides evidence of a genuine moral dilemma for contemporary Chinese: that is, as
discussed at the end of Section 5, what should be done when patients want to know the
truth about their condition but medical professionals and relatives prefer to withhold
information and even lie to them? According to the Golden Rule in Confucianism, “Do not
impose on others what you do not wish for yourself,” medical professionals should not
obstruct the wish of patients in order to achieve what they believe to be in the best interest
of patients.
Placing the onus of disclosure on family members in cases of terminal illness, a practice
that is widespread in China and favourably endorsed by the advocates of the cultural
differences argument, raises additional ethical questions. For instance, is this really in the
The “Cultural Differences” Argument and Its
Misconceptions: The Return of Medical Truth-Telling in China
115
patient’s best interests, or for the convenience of medical professionals? Telling patients
the truth about their serious condition is an art; however caring and experienced he or she
may be, no physician will be perfect at this. As the 1847 Code of Ethics of the American
Medical Association recommends, it is not ethically sound for physicians to delegate this
difficult task wholly to family members. Apart from their obvious lack of systematic
training in medicine and counselling, most importantly, lay relatives may lack the
necessary professional and personal distance often critical for imparting sensitive
information in an empathic way. Chinese medical professionals need to change their
practice on this. Shunning a professional duty merely because of its difficulty is
unacceptable, ethically and professionally. If the real motivation for “familist” practice is
simply the convenience of medical professionals, then the practice clearly needs reform.
For Chinese medical practitioners, the basic requirement of the Confucian medical ideal,
“medicine as the art of humanity”, is to fulfil their professional duties, however
challenging they may be.
9. The tyranny of culture vs. the primacy of morality
Respecting perceived cultural differences constitutes a major ethical stumbling block to
implementing the practice of direct and truthful medical disclosure in non-Western
societies (and non-European groups within Western countries). By this logic, the current
mainstream cultural practice is proffered as a sufficient ethical rationale to reject medical
truth-telling. In other words, the “cultural difference” proponents attempt to bypass the
moral difficulties involved by substituting statements about cultural practices for serious
ethical examination. In this age of Western cultural hegemony, it is extremely important
to respect different cultural practices, especially non-Western ones. However, an ethical
dilemma arises when cultural practices conflict with moral imperatives. The cultural
difference argument privileges cultural practices over ethical mandates; it implies, if not
holds, that whatever is culturally authentic is automatically ethically defensible. This
tyranny of culture over ethics can easily lead to moral relativism and even ethical
nihilism. According to the logic of the cultural difference view, slavery in human history;
gender discrimination and many other forms of discrimination, which are found in almost
all human societies; the West’s colonization of the non-Western world; the Third Reich in
Germany; and foot-binding in Chinese history – to list just a few examples – are all
ethically justifiable because all these practices were or still are culturally genuine and even
unique.
More crucially, respecting cultural norms and practices can actually work against the
fundamental values of a given culture and society. For both Confucianism and Daoism, the
two major indigenous Chinese moral and political traditions, it is not existing cultural
practices that should be privileged, but whatever is morally right. For Confucianism and
Daoism, the most fundamental value is precisely the primacy of ethics and morality over
existing social and cultural practices, rather than the other way around. The moral
imperative of the Dao (Tao, literally “the Way”) or the Tianming (the mandate of Heaven) is
superior to the claims of any cultural and social practices, whether Western or Eastern. The
basic task and highest calling of ethics is, first of all, to identify which socio-cultural
practices are morally justifiable and which are not.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
116
10. Conclusion
Taking a universalist ethical position on human rights and patients’ rights, other bioethicists
have forcefully argued the importance of truth-telling and informed consent internationally,
in China as well (Macklin 1999). This may be seen as a kind of outside perspective. In this
paper, my stance is from the inside out.
My aim is not to dispute the existence of widely acknowledged cultural differences in China
and the West regarding medical truth-telling. Rather, the key question for me is how this
prima facie cultural difference—direct disclosure vs. non-disclosure or indirect disclosure—should be
interpreted historically, sociologically and ethically. In particular, I have demonstrated that,
despite its popularity and apparent plausibility, the cultural differences argument against
medical truth-telling in China is seriously flawed at both the descriptive and normative
levels. It has oversimplified and distorted both the historical and socio-cultural realities,
including the role of family, in both China and the West. It has mis-presented and mis-
interpreted the standpoints of such major Chinese traditions as Confucianism on the subject.
Historically, it has ignored the venerable Chinese tradition of direct truth-telling and,
sociologically, it has dismissed the wishes of the great majority of Chinese patients who
want to know the truth about their prospects. Ethically, it has obscured critical moral
problems involved in nondisclosure and deception by medical professionals, and it
promotes the tyranny of existing socio-cultural practices over ethics and acceptable
morality.
Therefore, the contemporary Chinese practice of concealing the truth and even lying to
patients about their terminal illness, no matter how widespread, ought to be critically
examined, vigorously challenged, and systematically reformed. Culturally, the shift toward
honest and direct disclosure now occurring in China is not so much –or at least not just-
following a Western pathway, but constitutes a return to a neglected indigenous tradition (for
a detailed discussion of this forgotten Chinese tradition, see Nie 2011, Chapter 6). More
importantly, even if it were proven to be culturally alien to China as universally assumed, the
norm of truth-telling should be instituted on the basis of the ethical imperatives presented in
this paper.
As for cross-cultural bioethics, if I have appeared to argue that all cultures are
fundamentally the same and that cultural differences do not matter, I would like to say
that this is not my intention. My point is that Chinese and Western cultures are different,
but not in the ways suggested by popular stereotypes, not in the sense of their being
“radical others” to one another. As this study of medical truth-telling in China and other
research projects have illustrated, Chinese-Western cultural differences are far more
complicated, subtle, intriguing – and thus more difficult to grasp and articulate – than
facile overgeneralizations. Rather than being homogenous and static, Chinese culture, like
any other human culture, has always been internally heterogeneous, full of contradictory
elements, changing over time, influenced by and borrowing elements from foreign
cultures, open to new possibilities, and subject to ethical scrutiny and developing moral
ideals. The complexity of cultural differences as indicated in medical truth-telling in
China in comparison with the West calls for a more adequate cross-cultural bioethics or a
“transcultural bioethics”: an ethics that resists cultural stereotypes, cherishes the common
humanity, upholds the primacy of morality, and acknowledges the richness, internal
diversity, dynamism and openness of medical ethics in every culture, whether in China,
The “Cultural Differences” Argument and Its
Misconceptions: The Return of Medical Truth-Telling in China
117
the West or elsewhere (for these general points, see Nie 2005, 2007, 2009, and especially
2011).
11. A Personal note
I would like to end this paper on a personal note. In the late 1980s, the father of a former
medical school classmate and good friend of mine was suffering the final stages of lung
cancer. A psychiatrist himself, without any knowledge of the new practice of disclosure in
the West, my friend informed his father of the diagnosis and prognosis – something his
father’s doctors and nurses never did. In taking this step, my friend set out bravely in
defiance of the dominant social and medical norm of nondisclosure, and unknowingly
travelled a way that ancient Chinese medical sages had walked more than twenty
centuries ago. At the time, I should have questioned him further about his courageous
decision to choose this unorthodox route. But our discussions were kept brief – after all, it
is never easy to talk about the death of a loved one. Now it has become impossible for me
to continue the dialogue. Having just celebrated his 31th birthday, and when working as a
visiting physician in Japan in 1994, my friend was hit by a car while riding a bicycle and
died from his injuries.
This paper is humbly dedicated to Dr Zou Xinxin (1963-1994), a brilliant physician and
friend. If only I could have had the benefit of his endorsement and criticism.
12. Acknowledgements
The expanded version of this chapter will be included in my forthcoming book, Medical
Ethics in China: A Transcultural Interpretation, to be published by Routledge. This work is a
part of a larger research project on medical ethics in China, financially supported by a
University of Otago Research Grant. I am very grateful to Li Hongwen in Beijing for his
research assistance in search of Chinese materials and Dr Paul Sorrell in Dunedin for his
professional editing. Parts of materials have been presented as invited speeches at the 7th
Beijing Forum, at a symposium organized by Giuliana Fuscaldo, Lynn Gillam and Sarah
Russell for the 10th World Congress of Bioethics, and at the second seminar of the New
Zealand Ministry of Health Pacific Health Leadership. I gratefully acknowledge the
organizers and the audiences of these events for their interest in my work and for their
helpful questions and comments.
13. References
Akabayashi A. and B.T. Slingsby. (2006). Informed Consent Revisited: Japan and the U.S.
American Journal of Bioethics, Vol. 6, No. 1(Jan-Feb 2006), pp.9-14, ISSN 1526-5161,
eISSN 1536-0075.
Bok. S. (1978). Lying: Moral Choice in Public and Private Life. New York: Vintage Books. ISBN-
10: 0375705287, ISBN-13: 978-0375705281
Chen, Menglei. (1991). [1723]. Gujin Tushu Jicheng Yibu Quanlu (A Collection of Ancient and
Modern Books, Section on Medicine), Book 12: General Discussions (Volumes 501-
520 in original), Beijing: People’s Health Press. (In Chinese)
Bioethics in the 21st Century
118
Fan, R. and B. Li. (2004). Truth Telling in Medicine: The Confucian View. Journal of Medicine
and Philosophy, Vol. 29, No.2, (April 2004), pp. 179-193, ISSN 0360-5310, eISSN 1744-
5019.
Fielding, R. and J. Hung. (1996). Preference for Information and Involvement in Decisions
during Cancer Care among a Hong Kong Chinese Population. Psycho-, Oncology
Vol. 5, No.4, (December 1996), pp. 321-329, ISSN: 1057-9249, eISSN 1099- 1611.
Gao, B., D. Zou, and L. Yang. (2006). A Study of Methods and Timing with Regard to
Informing Elderly Cancer Patients. Nursing Journal of Chinese People’s Liberation
Army. No. 10. (in Chinese)
Gongal, R. P. Vaidya, R. Jha, O. Raijbhandary & M. Watson. (2006).Informing patients about
cancer in Nepal: what do people prefer. Palliative Medicine, Vol.20, No.4, (June
2006), pp. 471- 476, ISSN 0269-2163, eISSN 1477-030X.
Hancock, K. et al. (2007). Truth-telling in discussing prognosis in advanced life- limiting
illness: a systematic review. Palliative Medicine, Vol. 21, No.6, (September 2007), pp.
507-517, ISSN 0269-2163, eISSN 1477-030X.
He, R., Y. Wang, Y. Tian, C. Zhou, H. Wang. (2009). The Preferences of Chinese Patients and
their Relatives Regarding the Disclosure of Cancer Diagnoses. Chinese Journal of
Clinical Oncology and Rehabilitation. No. 3. (in Chinese)
Hern, H.E. Jr., B.A. Koenig, L.J. Moore, & P.A. Marshall. (1998). The Difference That Culture
Can Make in End-of-Life Decision Making. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics
Vol. 7, No.1,(Winter 1998), pp. 27-40, ISSN 0963-1801, eISSN 1469-2147.
Huang, X., X. Wang, Y. Zhang, B. Lü, and T. Li. (2001). Information Needs of Cancer
Patients: Whether and How to Disclosure the Diagnosis of Cancer. Chinese Journal of
Mental Health No. 4. (in Chinese)
Jiang, Y., C. Liu, J-Y Li, et al. (2007). Different attitudes of Chinese patients and their families
toward truth telling of different stage of cancer. Psycho-Oncology, Vol. 16, No. 10,
(October 2007), pp. 928-936, ISSN: 1057-9249, eISSN 1099-1611.
Jotkowitz, A., S. Click and B. Gezundheit. (2006). Truth-telling in a Culturally Divers World.
Cancer Investigation 24:786-789.
Kagaw-Singer, M. and L.J. Blackhall. (2001). Negotiating Cross-Cultural Issues at the End of
Life: “You Got to Go Where He Lives”. Journal of American Medical Association,Vol.
286, No.23, (December 2001), pp. 2993-3001, ISSN 0098-7484, eISSN 1538-3598.
Katz, J. (2002) (first edition 1984). The Silent World of Doctor and Patient (with a new foreword
by A. M. Capron). Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN
978- 4020-8603-8, eISBN 978-4020-8604-5, Springer.
Kleinman, A. 1988. The Illness Narratives. New York: Basic Books. ISBN 0-465-03202-8, ISBN
0-465-03204-4. United States of America.
Legge, J. (tran) (1971) [1893], The Confucian Analects, The Great Learning and The Doctrine of the
Mean, New York: Dove.
Li, S., and J-L Chou. (1997). Communication with the Cancer Patient in China. Annals of New
York Academy of Sciences, Vol. 809,(February 1997), pp. 243-248 ISSN 0077-8923,
eISSN 1749-6632.
Macklin, R. (1999). Against Relativism: Cultural Diversity and the Search for Ethical Universals in
Medicine. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN 0-19-511632-J, NY.
The “Cultural Differences” Argument and Its
Misconceptions: The Return of Medical Truth-Telling in China
119
Mitchell. J. (1998). Cross-cultural Issues in the Disclosure of Cancer. Cancer Practice 6(3): 153-
160.
Moberireek A.F. et al. (2008). Information disclosure and decision-making: the Middle East
versus the Far East and the West. Journal of Medical Ethics Vol.34, No.4, (April 2008),
pp. 225-229, ISSN 0306-6800, eISSN 1473-4257.
Mystakidou, K., E. Parpa, E. Tsilika, E. Katsouda, and L. Vlahos. (2004). Cancer information
disclosure in different culture context. Support Care Cancer, Vol. 12, No.3, (March
2004), pp. 147-154, ISSN 0941-4355, eISSN 1433-7339.
Nie, JB. (2011) (forthcoming). Medical Ethics in China: A Transcultural Interpretation.
London and New York: Routledge.
Nie, JB. (2009). The Discourses of Practitioners in China. in Robert Baker and Larry
McCullough, eds., The Cambridge World History of Medical Ethics, New York and
London: Cambridge University Press. Chapter 21, pp. 335-344.
Nie, JB. (2007). The Specious Idea of an Asian Bioethics: Beyond Dichotomizing East and
West, in R.E. Ashcroft, A. Dawson, H. Draper and J.R. McMillan, eds. Principles of
Heath Care Ethics, Second Edition, London: John Wiley & Sons. pp. 143-149.
Nie, JB. (2005). Behind the Silence: Chinese Voices on Abortion. Lanham and Oxford: Rowman &
Littlefield.
Pang, M.S. (1998). Information Disclosure: The Moral Experience of Nurses in China.
Nursing Ethics, Vol. 5, No.4, (July 1998), pp.347-361, ISSN 0969-7330, eISSN 1477-
0989.
Pang, M.S. (1999). Protective truthfulness: the Chinese way of safeguarding patients in
informed treatment decisions. Journal of Medical Ethics, Vol.25, No.3, (June 1999), pp.
247-253, ISSN 0306-6800, eISSN 1473-4257.
Surbone, A. (1992). Letter from Italy: Truth Telling to the Patient. JAMA, Vol. 268, No.13,
(October 1992), pp. 1661-2 ISSN 0098-7484, eISSN 1538-3598.
Surbone. A. (2004). Persisting differences in truth telling throughout the world. Support Care
Cancer, Vol.12, No.3, (March 2004), pp.143-146. ISSN 0941-4355, eISSN 1433-7339.
Surbone, A. (2006). Telling the Truth to Patients with Cancer: What is the Truth. Lancet
Oncology, Vol. 7, No. 11 (November 2006), pp. 944-50, ISSN 1470-2045, eISSN 1474-
5488.
Surbone, A. (2008). Cultural Aspects of Communication in Cancer Care. Support Care Cancer,
Vol.16, No.3 (March 2008), pp. 235-240, ISSN 0941-4355, eISSN 1433-7339.
Sun, Y., Z. Li, M. Sun, L. Chang. (2007). A Study of Attitudes of Family Members of Cancer
Patients regarding Truth-Telling and Possible Influencing Factors. Chinese Journal of
Nursing. No. 6. (in Chinese)
Tang, S. T. and S-Y. C. Lee. (2004). Cancer Diagnosis and Prognosis in Taiwan: patient
References versus Experiences. Psycho-Oncology, Vol. 13, No.1, (January 2004), pp.
1-13 ISSN: 1057-9249, eISSN 1099-1611.
Tang, S. T. et al. (2008). Patient awareness of prognosis, patient-family caregiver congruence
on the preferred place of death, and caregiving burden of families contribute to the
equality of life for terminal ill cancer patients in Taiwan. Psycho-Oncology, Vol. 17,
No. 12, (December 2008), pp.1202-1209, eISSN: 1099-1611.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
120
Tolstoy. L. translated by L. Solotaroff. (1986). The Death of Ivan Ilyich. New York: Bantam
Book.
Tse, C.Y., A. Chong, and S.Y. Fok. (2003). Breaking Bad News: A Chinese Perspective.
Palliative Medicine Vol.17, No.4 (June 2003), pp. 339-343, ISSN 0269-2163, eISSN
1477- 030X.
Tuckett. A.G. (2004). Truth-Telling in Clinical Practice and the Arguments For and Against:
A Review of Literature. Nursing Ethics, Vol.11, No.5, (September 2004), pp. 500-513
ISSN 0969-7330, eISSN 1477-0989.
Wear, S. (2007). Truth Telling to the Sick and Dying in a Traditional Chinese Culture. In S.C.
Lee, ed., The Family, Medical Decision-Making, and Biotechnology. pp. 71-82 Dordrecht:
Springer. ISBN 978-1-4019-5220-4, eISBN 978-1-4020-5220-0, The Netherlands.
Yixue Yu Zhexue (Editorial Office of the journal Medicine and Philosophy). (2008). Guiding
Principles on Truth-telling to and Consent from Cancer Patients. Medicine and
Philosophy (Clinical Making Forum Edition) 29 (10): 7-8. (in Chinese)
Zeng, T., Y. Li, Y. Chen, and P. Fang. (2007). An Investigation into the Attitudes of Medical
Professional on Disclosing Cancer Diagnoses. Medicine and Philosophy (Clinical
Decision Making Forum Edition), 28 (11). (in Chinese).
8
Nanotechnology and Ethics:
Assessing the Unforeseeable
Monique Pyrrho
University of Brasília
Brazil
1. Introduction
Nanotechnology is not in consensus. The attempts to answer the question “what is
nanotechnology?” are usually inaccurate, and the responses to it, far from being unanimous.
There has always been controversy, from defining its conception to establishing the limits of
the so-called nanoscience subject, as well as its effects and viability. One of the few points of
consensus among scientists is that manipulation of materials at the atomic level may unfold
new properties.
The emerging nanotechnology brings great excitement due to its technological potential. In
order to analyze its possible ethical implications, the task of starting from the beginning, of
introducing the theme from the concept of the object of study itself, imposes the first and
fundamental obstacle for those who intend to reflect about the ethical approach of
nanoscience and nanotechnology.
This initial challenge comes from the differences found between what each group that uses
the term nanotechnology intends to mean. The objects of study, nanoscience and
nanotechnology do not seem to be consensually organized. In general, researchers and
scientists tend to describe nanotechnology from a perspective of their own activities
(Petersen & Anderson, 2007).
The prefix nano, derived from the Greek “dwarf”, refers to the tiny size of the particles. In
scientific terms, it means a part per billion; therefore, a nanometer (nm) corresponds to a
billionth of a meter (10-9). To illustrate the reduced scale in which nanotechnology works,
the smallest point seen by a human naked eye is about 10,000 nm, while 1 nanometer
corresponds to 10 times the diameter of a hydrogen atom (Medeiros et al., 2006).
Under such perspective, it is possible to understand nanoscience as the field of knowledge
that studies the fundamental principles of molecules and structures (sized between 1 to 10
nanometers in at least one dimension) called nanostructures. Nanotechnology, in turn, is the
application of these nanostructures in functional nanoscale devices.
However, even according to the official definitions by the National Science Foundation
(2000), nanotechnology does not have a clear concept. The NSF defines it as the research and
technology developed from new properties as a result of matter manipulation on a
nanoscale level – between 1 and 100 nm. However, the same properties can be occasionally
found in dimensions below 1 nm and above 100 nm.
Nowadays, the manipulation of objects and devices on that scale is common to almost all
new fields of experimental science. The difficulty in establishing what is and what is not
Bioethics in the 21st Century
122
nanotechnology has important epistemological and ethical consequences (Ferrari, 2010). The
ambiguous nature of such concept results in laboratories claiming that their researches must
be added the prefix “nano”, along with all resources and prestige it brings. The undefined
limits of this new techno-scientific movement influence the debate on its potential and its
consequences.
Nanotechnology is expected to advance almost all current technological industry branches
such as. Literature approaches an expectation of progress in computer science, micro and
nanoelectronics, cosmetic and textile industry, energy production and storage,
telecommunications, chemical and petrochemical industries, agriculture and agribusiness,
automobile industry, aeronautics and, of course, arms industry (Invernizzi, 2008).
As far as healthcare is concerned, nanotechnology shows one of its most promising
announcing revolutionary scientific and technological progress that might deeply affect
the way we deal with health and medicine in the near future. In the new field of
nanomedicine, devices and nanostructured materials are expected to be applied to
monitor, repair, build and control human biological systems (Sahoo et al., 2007). There are
countless possibilities: controlled release of therapeutic agents, production of active
ingredients, medical imaging, lab diagnoses, biomaterial production and implants, and
more (Wagner et al., 2006).
The great promises in nanotechnology are not new. The fact that many laboratories are
investing more and more in research shows more than a resemblance between
nanotechnology and the latest great advances in biotechnology.
Before the promising scientific advances and their impacts come, major social groups have
not waited to express their positions on nanotechnology and society. The media, scientists,
policymakers and sectors of society have promptly set out their stances, with the
justification that scientific changes require urgency in decision-making. A hasty scenario of
extreme positions has been set up. However, the shape of this innovation demands balanced
reflection rather than taking unconditional sides on the use or ban of nanotechnology, or
definitively halting it, or waiting for it to eventually happen. At this initial stage, therefore, it
is opportune to propose a prior discussion that is broader than foreknowledge and
assessment of the unforeseeable beneficial effects or risks.
As the establishment of the topics for discussion already seems to be difficult strategies
other than discussing risks that cannot be fully foreseen and assessed are strongly
suggested. This is how this topic will be brought up and developed here.
The first challenge regards the different appropriations of vocabulary and the diversity of
devices and techniques used in the various fields of research. This leads to the notion that
nanotechnology is not a single entity to which a single value judgment can be attributed.
Actually, one should consider not one, but many nanotechnologies. Thus, it would be
extremely difficult and also inappropriate to propose a comprehensive stance for all the
fields and products involved.
In different scenarios, the term “nanotechnology” can have a different interpretation,
eventually being used for different objectives, leading to different consequences. There are
some who even question the innovative nature of nanotechnology , grouping it with other
fields of biotechnology. This attitude may diminish the hype around this so-called
innovation; however, it also points to the need to analyze the various objectives and
definitions upon which the debate is based (Ferrari, 2010).
Consequently, instead of mainly establishing concepts and discussing the possible risks
related to the use of nanotechnology products, this is a longer and not so explored path.
Nanotechnology and Ethics: Assessing the Unforeseeable
123
First of all, there are some important reference points regarding this scientific phenomenon
to be defined. Also, innovations in relation to previous biotechnological-scientific advances
must be identified, and the degree to which they demand specific debate on their ethics
must be assessed.
2. What is new?
In at least one respect, nanotechnology represents something fairly new among technical-
scientific revolutions: the ethical implications of its possible discoveries have become a cause
for concern even before the discoveries themselves have been made. Indeed, more than the
technological advances themselves, what is most innovative in nanotechnology is the very
discussion of its ethics, which is taking place at the same time as or before the scientific
events on which it focuses. Long before scientists could explore the manipulation and
shaping of compounds at atomic and molecular levels, it was the expectation of the
transformation of our relationship with the world, of delving so deeply into the structure of
matter, which motivated the visionary Feynman (1961) in the first references to the theme.
Possible repercussions precede and obscure the actual facts. Debates regarding the possible
transformation of the world, and of humans into post-humans, take place before the basic
science has been established. Apocalyptic scenarios are depicted even before methods and
procedures for nanotechnology can be clearly established (admittedly, this is not unlike
some genetics).
Therefore, according to Schummer (2007), the technological exploration of nanoscale
properties is not the real innovation. He states that the innovative aspect lies in how
nanotechnology and the way it is depicted reflect the connections between society, science
and technology. This innovation affects pre-established boundaries between living and non-
living things, the natural and the artificial.
It is significant that a debate on ethical implications is taking place before the scientific
advances themselves have actually taken place. An ethical approach, rather than an attempt
to explore science fiction, could perhaps state that nanoscience, its structures and scientific
approaches, represent a characteristic rupture between new paradigms and the classical
scientific model.
Innovations frequently disrupt established moral standpoints, bringing discomfort or a
conflict between customs and the new reality that is imposed, and requiring further
discussion. Moreover, dealing with novelty brings, to some degree, an urge
to explore the paths of the unknown which cannot easily be foreseen (Swierstra & Rip,
2007).
In the case of nanotechnology it is characterized not by the size of the particles it deals with
but by the new and unknown chemical and physical properties that derive from their size
(Ratner & Ratner, 2003). The great attraction of working on a nanoscale lies in new and
unusual physical and chemical properties that are not found in the same materials at micro
and macroscopic dimensions. It is therefore unrealistic to expect to know all the possibilities
for their use and to foresee their consequences. The specific characteristics of the nanometric
dimension diverge from the physicochemical laws that determine the behavior of materials
at “normal” macroscopic scales.
3. The scientific paradigm and its implications
Given that nanoscience is based on the diverse and unpredicted behaviour of materials
manipulated on a nanoscale, the unknown and the unforeseen are central to it. Scientific
Bioethics in the 21st Century
124
knowledge, insufficient in itself to provide moral solutions, is also revealed to be incapable
of providing sufficiently reliable information to enable proper reflection on the health-
related, ecological, ethical and social impacts of nanotechnology.
The literature on nanotechnology and ethics is incipient in comparison with what has been
produced internationally regarding its techno-scientific aspects. However, it is noticeable
that the ethical implications that have been identified, and the solutions that have been
proposed, vary in accordance with the writer’s individual perspective on scientific activity.
There is a tendency for scientists to have an inward-looking perspective that describes
scientific activity on the basis of its methods and technical results, in this case producing
what one might call a scientific image of nanotechnology. The ethical discourse arising from
this image emphasizes ethical implications closely connected to the direct consequences of
the applications of nanotechnology.
With regard to practical questions regarding health and the expected use of nanomedicine,
the ethical issues arising from the applications of nanotechnology are too numerous and
complex to be addressed satisfactorily by scientists alone.
If, in the past, the analysis by scientists of ethical issues surrounding technological advances
proved to be limited, and sometimes biased, a new science that reveals epistemological
ruptures with the fundamental scientific characteristics of reproduction and predictability
would appear to present an even more complex subject for analysis.
Another factor to be taken into consideration is that much of the scientific media defines
nanoscience not on the basis of its conceptual reference points or properties but in raltion to
expectations surrounding its applications. Nanoscience essentially becomes the expectations
that are placed upon it, the things it is deemed to promise. This discourse becomes an
apology for scientific progress, instead clarifying any specific aspect of nanotechnology
(Swierstra & Rip, 2007). Made the object either of huge optimism or huge pessimism,
nanotechnology is depicted either as the future solution to world health problems or the
future cause of a great ecological disaster. From such a perspective a sensible assessment is
impossible.
A new ethical approach is necessary; an approach that uses the language of this new
scientific paradigm. It is especially important to know how to engage in dialogue about a
science based on the unforeseeable and the unknown.
This ethical debate on nanotechnology highlights the oscillation between the
consequentialist and deontological approach, well known in bioethics. The relevance of the
consequentialist approach is clear, due to the central role of risk analysis of nanoparticles in
this debate (Ferrari, 2010). This is completely understandable since this kind of analysis is
necessary in order to guide political and ethical regulation, but it needs to be based on
scientific evidence, which is especially problematic in nanotechnology (Shrader-Frechette K,
2007). The discourses on risks become important, partly because current mechanisms for
regulation and control are insufficient, sometimes even inadequate, to address the uncertain,
unpredictable aspects of this field (Grunwald, 2005).
Those who intend to establish their ethical approach only by studying impacts and detailed
risk analyses based on thorough knowledge of technical possibilities, find themselves
thwarted. Such failure occurs primarily because scientists’ parameters for risks diverge from
the perception of such risks within society (Slovic, 1987). The public perception is that
biotechnological advances bring unknown risks that may take time to become apparent or
may not be fully observable. It is generally opposed to the scientific discourse based on
calculations of risks and benefits. But such calculation is not yet possible (and might never
Nanotechnology and Ethics: Assessing the Unforeseeable
125
be), as the risks and benefits are not yet well known (Savadori et al., 2004). The principle of
precaution is frequently presented as a solution to the difficulty of predicting the direction
of scientific development. It is seen as a guideline for decisions under uncertain conditions.
It is assumed that negative effects are known, but it is impossible to measure risks due to a
lack of data (Ferrari, 2010).
Not only is it impossible to measure the risks presented by nanotechnology but even its
effects are unpredictable. This is because nanotechnology involves a new epistemic scenario,
the inherent basis of which is uncertainty and ignorance (Stirling, 2007). Decision making in
nanotechnology, therefore, is additionally complex because of its epistemic nature, as well
as other factors such as the wide variety of its applications (Rip, 2006). Consequently, the
precautions taken against unknown risks are not successful in practical life and its
interactions with the market. The parameters of the analysis therefore need to be revised.
The subject has to be analyzed on an interdisciplinary basis, taking into consideration the
complexity of the relationships between many levels of reality, and thus encompassing both
scientific and social phenomena (Victoriano, 2006). An increasing number of authors
criticize risk analysis as the only approach in debates on the ethics of nanotechnology. They
suggest that ethical reflections should go beyond risks and benefits to also address the way
science is performed, including its objectives and methods. These would be more complete
approaches, taking into account issues such as intellectual property, public opinion, and
future generations (Ferrari, 2010).
In recent years, especially in Europe, there has been an increasing number of initiatives
calling for a more representative inclusion of public opinion in debates on the control and
management of new technologies. This movement grew stronger in the wake of negative
reactions to foods derived from genetically modified organisms. Such initiatives aim to re-
establish trust in science, establish political innovations, avoid adverse reactions,
democratize the governance of new technologies, and promote more responsible, reliable
scientific practices. However, public engagement can be hampered by many factors: a lack
of awareness of what nanotechnology really entails; the future-oriented and promissory
character of nanotechnology, which gives a special role to science fiction in shaping the
moral imagination of nanoscientists and nanotechnology policy itself; and the very
strangeness of nanotechnology in relation to daily life, introducing a dimension that is not
well be understood or even perceived. In addition, the conceptions or discourses that guide
and define the development of nanotech science, though crucial, vary between the many
branches of nanotechnology and different cultural scenarios. Such disharmony makes it
necessary to analyze those discourses with the aim of making possible genuine public
participation. (Macnaghten, 2010).
An ethical approach, therefore, would mean that nanotechnology is part of a cultural
scenario, simultaneously defining and being defined by it. In this way the issue of the
different perceptions of the sciences, and the discourses and expectations that surround
them, take on great importance, since the way the future is described influences the way it
turns out to be. The ethical approach, therefore, needs to be applied to other levels,
overcoming precaution and the search for consequences in order to understand science as a
thorough phenomenon, in all scientific, cultural, economic and political dimensions (Dupuy
& Grinbaum, 2004). Reductionism is no longer acceptable.
One of the possibilities is to understand nanoscience and nanotechnology, with their
promising results and unforeseen risks, within a broader context, such as a practical
segment of a new scientific paradigm based on its ability to control and manipulate matter
at atomic and molecular scales (Kearnes & Macnaghten, 2006).
Bioethics in the 21st Century
126
Kuhn (1962), in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, described the evolution of modern
science and defined scientific paradigms as the successive models on which scientific
theories were based. Normal science would mean research based on scientific
accomplishments recognized, for a while, as the basis for subsequent practice. Normal
science, therefore, would be based on paradigms, i.e. models that structure and order the
current stock of scientific knowledge, thereby determining the methods and subjects for
study. Paradigms are therefore the basis of normal science, which is generally developed to
state and confirm common theories and concepts among scientists.
In the case of the broad field of nanoscience, the paradigm previously applied was known as
Newtonian Mechanics. It originated from the Cartesian hypothesis, which in some aspects it
advanced and completed, and describes the interactions of macroscopic bodies. The
scientific revolution from which the next paradigm will emerge may be structured from
current normal science. Therefore normal research, following the Cartesian scientific model
for analysis, study and synthesis, has influenced the study of bodies and interactions. The
attempts to apply the current paradigm to miniaturization may have brought about its very
specific crisis.
The attempts to verify a theoretical paradigm, i.e. the ultimate goal of ‘normal science’, have
detected imperfections and incoherence between theory and phenomena (Kuhn, 1962). The
search for the ultimate explanation of the universal law that governs all bodies in their
smallest units is halted due to its great divergence from the macroscopic world. At the
atomic or molecular level, the laws governing interactions are related to the wave nature of
electrons and the frequency and wavelength of their vibrations. Unlike the phenomena
predicted by classic scientific theory, the concern of quantum physics is the observation of
behavior on a nanometric scale (Ratner & Ratner, 2003).
The appropriation of the scientific paradigm extends beyond the changing of the physical
science paradigm. Nanotechnology represents the “convergence of quantum physics,
molecular biology, computing science, chemistry and engineering” (Mehta, 2002), and
therefore differs from Cartesian scientific knowledge. Whereas the latter seeks
specialization, nanotechnology results from a convergence of interdisciplinary concepts,
allowing interactions between methods, applications and theoretical foundations in
different fields of expertise (Garrafa, 2006).
Such a scenario is close to the current complex scientific paradigms in which interactions
transcend conventional divisions between sciences, humanities and biomedicine.
Nanoscience thus diverges from the scientific method in which the production of
knowledge is based on analysis. Such object-oriented analysis, within scientific practice,
has resulted in a disconnection between human sciences and natural sciences (Morin,
1988).
Morin (1988) stated that such a disconnection made it impossible to observe the complex
nature of the world, reducing reality to “mathematized” rules and laws that would appear
to explain the world perfectly by ignoring unforeseen events or facing them as errors.
Reality was seen as the sum of observable phenomena, not taking into consideration the
possible overlaps between science and philosophy or between human and biological
sciences (Morin, 2008).
Starting from a perception of realities in their full complexity, new technology and a new
scientific paradigm have practical implications which go beyond the limits of their original
subjects. This complex thinking is illustrated as a network that seeks to analyze the possible
interactions between many levels of reality and the repercussions of events. Also, this new
Nanotechnology and Ethics: Assessing the Unforeseeable
127
thinking includes an awareness that unforeseen events are characteristic of the phenomena;
they are not just the result of errors, and are not to be disregarded (Morin, 1988).
From the viewpoint of complexity, the rupture between ecology and sociology, in which
scientific analysis has as its object the environment without man and man outside his
environment, is artificial and ethnocentric. An analysis of the possible consequences of
nanotechnology should, therefore, avoid disconnecting these dimensions (Victoriano, 2006).
This is vitally important for a proper analysis of the actual influences and the distribution of
social benefits brought about by the minimization of energy and materials required in the
nanotechnology industry (Schnaiberg, 2006).
New paradigms generally emerge as more suitable responses to questions unanswered by
previous paradigms. They enable scientists to explain a greater number of phenomena or to
increase the accuracy of their existing explanations. For this reason the application of new
technologies may be controversial, because they might seem to offer a theoretical solution to
the world’s problems, and because they unveil a set of unknown phenomena that might be
greeted with disbelief or sometimes even panic (Kuhn, 1962).
Nanotechnology is paradigmatic in this sense. Sometimes it is portrayed as a revolutionary
technology that will change the way we live through its effects on industry, communications
and information technology. It would appear to expand the boundaries of medicine,
promising less invasive, more effective surgery, more specific medications, treatments for
incurable diseases such as cancer, and even the possibility of improvements in cognition and
memory processes (Freitas, 2005).
On the other hand, the current lack of knowledge regarding the potential scope of
nanotechnology provokes extreme reactions that tend to emphasize environmental risks and
profound transformations in our way of life. One example is the debate on the so-called
“grey goo”, a scenario where self-replicating nanoscale devices called nanobots would rule
the world. Out of human control, they would eventually eliminate our species from the
planet (Drexler, 2004).
The advances within nanotechnology have led to debates on the ethical implications of its
applications. The ethical issues discussed have included equity, benefit distribution, access
to scientific advances, environmental impact (the use of new materials, and of new
properties of previously-known materials, might make them insoluble or turn them into
pollutants), implications for privacy and security (invisible surveillance equipment, and
infinite possibilities for the arms industry), modification of the constitution of living entities
(genetically modified organisms), and self-replicating devices (Salvarezza, 2003).
In its methods and in the way it is conceived, managed and practiced, the new scientific
paradigm of nanotechnology represents a rupture with the existing scientific model. The
current academic scientific model, conceived in 18th-century Europe, especially in French
and German universities, has been undergoing profound transformations. Post-academic
science shares the objectives of the previous model – the production of knowledge in
accordance with epistemic norms, scientific laws, and values – and yet differs from it in at
least three aspects: how knowledge is produced (focusing on transdisciplinarity); how
knowledge is assessed (for its economic potentials); and the great emphasis on the
application of that knowledge, or in other words, the fact that knowledge is produced so as
to serve certain technological purposes (Jotterand, 2005).
The common perception of nanotechnology as a revolution is therefore understandable.
Nanotechnology not only entails epistemic rupture, as did the other scientific revolutions
Bioethics in the 21st Century
128
before it, but introduces new laws and structures of knowledge, or new cognitive categories.
Changing the way categories are explained brings changes to the way we experience the
world.
Nanotechnology, however, is more than a scientific revolution; it is probably a techno-
scientific revolution, because it focuses not on the properties of matter but on its
manipulation and transformation.
Therefore, in a way that is quite revolutionary, neither the concept of science nor the concept
of technology can perfectly describe the know-how of nanotechnology. Nordmann (2004)
states that nanoscience is not structured from a topic but set to a goal. It is not aimed at
manifestations of nature, machines, or substances with new properties. Its epistemic
effectiveness is not measured based on its devices and the functions of substances. Actually,
nanoscience is an attempt to explore an inhospitable territory and to colonize a new world,
or an as-yet unexplored area of the world. Epistemic success is now a technical
accomplishment; the ability to act in nanoscale scenarios, to see, to move things, to carve a
word in a molecule. This means that nanoscience is not traditional "science" per se, and that
there is no distinction between its theoretical manifestation and its technical intervention, or
between the understanding of nature and its transformation. From now on, therefore, it
would be more appropriate for the debate to be focused on nanotechnoscience.
This particular scenario of technoscientific revolution does not only establish
nanotechnology’s scientific and technological development, but also influences the
development of moral reflections on the social and ethical implications of nanotechnology.
The technoscientific revolution brought about by nanotechnoscience is a broader post-
academic scientific movement in which science, technology, politics and economics have
convergent social purposes. These relationships allow greater integration between ethical
and philosophical reflections and scientific practice within the post-academic context, due to
its cross-disciplinary nature and to the increasing political and social pressure on the process
of scientific knowledge production (Jotterand, 2005).
Sotolongo (2006) pointed out two important ethical issues that require closer attention, both
relate to the current type of science exemplified in nanoscience. First, due to humans’ great
capacity to intervene in natural phenomena, and unprecedented capacity to interact with
and manipulate matter and energy, our physical and intellectual abilities can be enhanced
through autonomous integrated systems. The closer science comes to controlling
environmental conditions, the closer it gets to potential powers of destruction. The second
issue is the huge extent of the knowledge acquired, which makes it impossible to identify all
the possible uses and practical interactions of the resulting technologies. As far as natural
and social complexity is concerned, not all the practical implications can be known,
predicted or manipulated: on the contrary, there is an inherent uncertainty in the
implications.
Although many adverse results can be expected in relation to nanotechnology, not restricted
to the immediate threat of nanotoxicity to humans, it is a cause for concern that so few
studies of its ethical, environmental, political and social implications have been carried out.
Even though there was reflection on its potential impacts before nanotechnology entered
scientific practice, the fast growth of research in its technical and scientific aspects over
recent years contrasts with the lack of investment and scientific production with regard to
its ethical and social aspects. Indeed, there has been an increasing distance between the
expanding technical-scientific knowledge and the required socio-political and philosophical
reflections (Mnyusiwalla et al., 2003).
Nanotechnology and Ethics: Assessing the Unforeseeable
129
The convergence of effort and investment in the technical fields is clearly related to the
social representation of science: the cultural phenomenon in which interpretive science,
which seeks meanings, loses out to empirical science, which seeks laws and rules (Franklin,
1995).
Faced with the innovation and the amount of challenges posed by the ethical debate on
nanotechnology, there are those who propose nanoethics, a subject that would be devoted
exclusively to the analysis of these challenges. However, immediate questions arise about
whether an area of ethical study devoted exclusively to nanotechnology is really
necessary. Consequently, comparisons between bioethics and nanoethics are frequently
made. Nanotechnology does not demand a genuinely new ethical approach but instead an
approach that is different and renewed in relation repertoire of the previous ones.
Therefore, instead of declaring that these questions have already been asked and that
there is nothing new in nanotechnology, it can be pointed out that if the questions are the
same ones as before, it is because they have not yet been answered. It is worthwhile to
pose those same questions again, for they might help to elucidate the phenomenon
(Khushf, 2007).
The same answers and methods that did not completely illustrate the analyzed phenomenon
are dispensable, therefore, but not the ethical concern itself. As previously suggested, the
development of nanotechnology casts doubt on whether risk assessments and other
analyses that are commonly used will nowadays suffice when it comes to evaluating
nanotechnology. Although traditional ethical approaches can be appropriate for some
subjects, nanotechnoscience has social and ethical implications of such magnitude that it
necessitates the development of alternative approaches that can provide conditions for the
development of nanotechnology (Meaney, 2006).
Therefore, whether proceeding from the perspective of nanoethics or from that of other
disciplines, the discussion regarding the ethical implications of nanotechnology reveals that
the questions do not arise only from within the social sciences: the scientists start to question
their own practices.
Despite manifesting this initial interest in reflecting upon their practices, the discourses of
natural science and social sciences are not the same. This is due especially to two factors.
First, following the events of World War II, scientists acquired a greater sensitivity to their
technological impacts. This sensibility focuses mainly on the impact of devices,
concentrating concerns on environmental and health issues. Another factor that sets their
discourses apart is the different readership for natural science articles when compared with
the social sciences and humanities.
4. Some ethical approaches: A typology
The purpose of setting the scenario in which nanotechnology has been established is to
show how the concepts of nanotechnology and the corresponding moral considerations of
the different actors, including scientists, are heterogeneous. The proposed approach,
therefore, starts from this initial effort to identify the concepts, their origins and their effects
(Kaiser, 2006).
Aiming to avoid the dualism that is so prevalent nowadays, Kaiser (2006) suggested that the
strategy for avoiding utopia or dystopia in the debate was to adopt an observational stance,
rather than viewing ethics from a participative perspective. According to him, it would not
be necessary to define nanotechnology, given its uncertain and unpredictable nature, in
Bioethics in the 21st Century
130
order to conduct a debate on it. The strategy suggested would be to stand back from the
topic and observe the scenario within which the actors construct their perspectives on and
concepts of nanotechnology, in order, to guide the ethical analysis.
Grunwald (2005), for instance, argues that the innovative character of nanotechnology is
being overestimated and that the ethical analysis should focus on the various
representations that underlie the discussion. It is not the nanoscale and its processes that
have ethical and social consequences. Ethical reflection should embrace science as part of
human relationships, with their images, significances and expectations.
Accordingly, to understand technologies in order to develop an appropriate ethical
approach, it is necessary to have explored in detail the universe of visions, images, ideas and
representations of nature, and of the human being embedded in the discussion (Ferrari,
2010). This perspective relates to the argument of the philosopher Karl Popper, who states
that every scientific theory is based on a set of values and world views. Roughly speaking,
those world views make up what he calls a Metaphysical Research Program. They are not
susceptible to direct empirical testing and are not falsifiable, and do not properly constitute
scientific knowledge, but they determine which problems, investigation methods and
solutions are considered scientifically (Popper, 2009).
Dupuy (2006) states that in nanotechnology, as in other convergence technologies, the
Metaphysical Research Program is characterized by a lack of distinction between knowing
and doing. Such similarity, which seems to reach its peak in nanotechnology, is illustrated
precisely by the instruments that make it technically possible.
In 1981, the Scanning Tunneling Microscope was developed. Through a very thin tip and a
voltage bias, it allowed atomic dimensions and dispositions to be analyzed, and it was later
discovered that this same instrument, with a small modification, was capable of
manipulating and repositioning atoms very accurately (Cao, 2006).
Dupuy (2006) argues that the Metaphysical Research Program goes beyond this very
explanatory metaphor of the microscope. Nanotechnology would make possible the
engineering of evolution, enabling man to be the designer in the production of life.
According to Dupuy, a project of such magnitude could not be analyzed using pre-
established ethical doctrines. A new ethical challenge requires a meticulous exercise of
unveiling the conceptions, ideas and images on which the scientific theory is based, so as to
then proceed to a critical analysis or a normative judgment of the technological progress.
In reply to the question "what is science?" different answers are given, but all of them are
always set in a certain context. The different forms of interpreting this question give birth to
at least two different images of science.
Dealing with different representations of science, Olivé (2006) stated that both the “scientific
image” and the “philosophical image” of science are derived from the question “What is
science?”. While the “scientific image” is usually the way in which scientists describe their
own activities, the “philosophical image” seeks to characterize scientific production within
the contexts provided.
The “scientific image” is to describes scientific facts and elucidates the rules governing
patterns, without concern for the social criticism of its own process of knowledge
construction (Franklin, 1995). The “philosophical image” studies the history, sociology and
philosophy of science and relates scientific activities to social practices and institutions, to
the conditions for the development of science, and to the mutual repercussions of society
and science (Olivé, 2006).
Nanotechnology and Ethics: Assessing the Unforeseeable
131
It is not specifically the dimension of the nanoparticles, therefore, that is important for
studies and consequent debates on the interactions between technology and society. The
analysis depends on the views of nanotechnology held by the different actors. What matters
is the transformation after human interference, and not the nanometric dimension in itself,
given that such a dimension is found in nature regardless of the intervention by human
devices. It is emphasized, however, that no intrinsic moral value is derived from human
intervention. Whether or not one carbon compound is nanostructured does not make it
ethically superior to another. It is in the relations between men, in society, and as part of the
natural environment, that the products and their uses will be revealed as more or less
adequate.
Some of the ethical implications therefore seem to be clearly demonstrated, such as in the
example of a compound that is toxic or pollutes. Other ethical challenges become clear only
within complex social interactions, such as the repercussions for the global economy and the
social inequality resulting from the introduction and appropriation of nanotechnologies by
the market.
Assuming that the ethical approach towards nanotechnology starts from the paradigmatic
unpredictability of this technical-scientific phenomenon, a schematic consideration of the
possible questions is put forward here. The dilemmas resulting from the interaction between
a new scientific paradigm and the complex overall social dynamics, together with the image
of nanoscience on which the ethical perspective is based, produce a classification scheme for
the implications of nanotechnology that has two categories: autogenous (internal) and
heterogeneous (external) (Pyrrho, 2008).
4.1 Autogenous ethical implications
Nanotechnologies are characteristically improvement technologies, which is to say that like
many convergence technologies, they refine and improve tools and materials that will be
used in other fields. They not only change the existing components and devices but also
develop new ones. This is the aspect most closely related to scientifically observable
consequences, which sometimes have considerable implications. Although nanoparticles
are not present-day inventions, the capacity to structure them systematically for the
industrial exploitation of their properties is certainly new. Products developed this way for
sporting, nutritive, automotive, cosmetic, information technological and many other
purposes are now available on the market. This production on an industrial scale is critical
because it may cause significant damage to the environment, to workers, and to the large
populations that are eager for technological goods.
The partial lack of knowledge about the properties of the materials goes together with the
way in which the national and international regulatory bodies lag behind: the regulations
take the chemical composition of the components into account but not their conformation.
For example, it is possible for a new nanostructured component to arrive on the
pharmaceutical market without undergoing new toxicity tests, even though the reactions
within the organism may be completely different.
Such developments are usually accompanied by biased arguments characterized by an
assumption that the application of nanotechnology is inevitable, a fascination regarding
its implementation, and a reduction of the ethical debate to the analysis of toxicological
and environmental risks. The perspective of those making such arguments is that the
benefits from research are usually derived more or less automatically, that any negative
effects can be attributed to mistakes on the part of others, and that it is impossible to
Bioethics in the 21st Century
132
predict how technology will be used once it has been developed (Ferrari, 2010). This
perspective clearly attributes moral neutrality to science. Risks and negative effects are
external to the scientific activity, so it cannot be responsible for them. This view also
produces a common perspective in bioethical discourse – the search for technical solutions
for moral problems.
According to Schummer (2004), three different understandings of the “social and ethical
implications of nanotechnology” stand out among scientists. Computer sciences researchers
associate these implications with radical changes in society, in which everything is possible
with software programming. Natural science researchers seem to hold a more modest but
still visionary position about industrial revolutions and other deep changes, as in
biomedical practices that related to nanotechnology. For toxicologists and
environmentalists, meanwhile, the ethical and social implications represent risks for health
and for the environment.
Despite the common ignorance regarding nanotechnology and its risks, the scientific
image seems to result in a positive perspective on the impacts of nanotechnology. In
another study, based on interviews with researchers, many of the interviewees
emphasized the difficulty in analyzing the risks due to the lack of research and
knowledge regarding important aspects of the nanomaterials. They pointed out
difficulties in foreseeing the behavior of the particles in certain environments, the little
investment in risk analyses, and uncertainty regarding current methods of risk analysis
for the nanoparticles. They described nanoscience as currently going through a latency
period between the introduction of the technologies and the evaluation of the adverse
effects. They still took the view, however, that nanotechnology is positive for society
(Petersen & Anderson, 2007).
The autogenous ethical implications were not highlighted because of an understanding that
they are intrinsic to nanotechnology. Such a view could erroneously put value on the
applications of this technology. The implications are considered autogenous as they are
associated with a causal effect. These are implications that are conceptualized within the
technical perspective. They generally result from the application of such approaches,
without complex analysis of interference from other factors. They are the repercussions that
are most frequently mentioned in debates since they are close to the predominant ethical
model of science, which is usually limited to assessing the impact of products and devices
on the environment and on health. However, at the point where such use seems to present
risks that are more measurable and analyzable, it has to be ensured that the same
technology that enables it is capable of supplying instruments that are sufficiently accurate
to assess any failures and to propose solutions (Pyrrho, 2008).
4.2 Heterogenous ethical implications
The term heterogeneous refers to the fact that studies on nanotechnological devices and
their implications are conceived through different “images” of science. While the devices
result from the “scientific image”, the social understanding of their use relates to a “meta-
scientific” perspective on nanotechnology.
The possible repercussions from the use of nanotechnology that are dealt with here arise
from interfaces of various cultural, social, economic, environmental and political
dimensions. They are heterogeneous because they result from complex interactions and not
from evaluations performed by science itself. They require an ethical assessment that
Nanotechnology and Ethics: Assessing the Unforeseeable
133
diverges from the search for cause-effect relationships and consequent linear risk analyses
(Pyrrho, 2008).
Expectations of technical solutions for social problems, such as the prospect that some of the
main applications of nanotechnology could make it easier to achieve the United Nations
Development Targets through energy production and increased agricultural productivity
(Salamanca-Buentello et al., 2005), have raised environmental, political, economic and public
health questions that, due to their mutual implications, trigger a discussion that does not
deal in simple solutions.
There is quite a widespread understanding that nanotechnology represents a technological
revolution that poses new challenges for traditional understandings about science and
knowledge acquisition, its intrinsically unpredictable character serving to question the role
of science in searching for truth. The new facets that science has been acquiring are dictated
strongly by the avidity of the market for technology. This process through which science is
transformed into techno-science is followed by reconfigurations of economic power, and
consequently also of political power. This politicization of science, and of nanotechnology
specifically, which represents the convergence of science, technology, politics and economy
for social and government purposes, offers the possibility of a better integration of ethical
and philosophical reflections with scientific and technological development (Jotterand,
2006).
This type of analysis emphasizes nanotechnology as a social-technical system and the
cultural values infused in the technologies. The social scientists and ethical consultants who
devote themselves to the study of nanotechnology can therefore influence nanotechnology,
together with other actors. As a consequence, when understanding nanotechnology as an
emerging technology, it is important to address the systems/networks of people and things.
While the technology is being developed, the distribution of power and authority is being
built, meanings are being contested and consolidated, and social practices involving rights
and responsibilities are being established. These social arrangements are a subject that
should be examined in the light of ethics, using ethical concepts, language, principles, norms
and theories (Johnson, 2007).
In the philosophical image of nanotechnology there is a predominant criticism of the so-
called nanohype and of the dualist and reductionist discussion to which it has led. The
dystopian and utopian visions frequently provoke extreme reactions: the former frequently
produce widespread rejection while the latter often lead to eventual disappointment at the
gap between expectations and reality, as in the case of genetically modified organisms.
There is a strong suggestion that social engagement take place in an effective way and not
only as a form of avoiding public non-acceptance.
Although some heterogeneous ethical implications such as social control, intellectual
property, the knowledge economy and social (in)justice have not attracted media or public
attention in the way that cinematographic cyborgs and promised panaceas have done, the
implications that are often forgotten are the ones that portray the most tangible and
important dimensions for an analysis of ethics in nanotechnology.
While recognizing the possibility of problems in classification, the categories proposed here
can highlight possibilities for evaluating risks resulting from nanotechnology and the
complex interdependencies that are socially related. The categories point towards social
dynamics as the locus where diverse ethical reflections and public debates are increasingly
necessary.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
134
5. Conclusion
The challenging character of nanotechnology is illustrated by its cross-disciplinary nature
and the impossibility of ascertaining all of its applications and implications. Even the
theoretical foundations of nanoscience are based on these innovative features. The
unfeasibility of attaining this overall knowledge of nanotechnology, and the unpredictability
inherent in the properties it explores, are responsible not only for the emergence of new
ethical challenges but also for the need for a diverse approach.
It is clear that there can be a distinction between traditional ethics, which seeks answers to
questions already posed, and a conception that attempts ethical reflections regarding the
possible moral implications of the application of this new technology. This difference,
together with an understanding of the complexity of reality, indicates that there is a need for
an innovative kind of analysis. Therefore, to debate and eventually come up with moral
answers regarding nanotechnology, it is necessary to have a perspective with a sufficiently
dynamic basis that is not limited to a strictly codified ethics.
The approach needed to analyze an emerging technology is one that considers not only the
complexity of reality as a whole but also specific moral questions of a given socio-cultural
context. Consequently, the ethical values required are no longer those that are based
epistemologically on principles that lack both a sufficiently stratified theoretical basis and
applicability in complex contexts. They must not be based on accumulated segmented
scientific knowledge but on knowledge (of the facts) that considers complexity. From this it
is may be possible to generate normative implications that are applicable to a moral
dialogue that is guided by tolerance to differences and may also point toward decisions in
different socioeconomic and cultural situations.
Far from attributing intrinsic moral values, the intention in proposing a distinction
between autogenous and heterogeneous implications for the construction of an ethical
approach towards nanotechnology, taking into account the fallibility to which all
classifications are subject, is to distinguish these perspectives from the interactions that
this approach addresses.
The processes of research, production and application of nanotechnology are approached as
autogenous themes. Ethical reflections that involve risk analysis, which is not always
possible, demand a double ability: technical improvement, with the development of
adequate devices for such evaluations, and also the search for new ethical considerations
that are sustained even if knowledge is not imminently attained.
The heterogeneous questions, which deal with the complex interactions of society,
technology, environment, politics and economics, within the still incipient discussion on the
ethics of nanotechnology, are the ones that have received least attention, even though a
sober and attentive reading shows that they are extremely relevant and plausible.
In the light of the hype driving the race between laboratories to label their research with the
prefix “nano”, and between countries to lead the way in producing state-of-the-art
nanotechnology, political agents oscillate between disregarding ethical matters and calling
for a definitive moratorium on research. Given this scenario, ethical reflection on the subject
of nanotechnology has to be free from overreaction and immediacy. The approach taken
toward the emerging technologies, as in the case of nanotechnology, should sober, critical
and dialectical. A diversity of perspectives and interests should be considered when
Nanotechnology and Ethics: Assessing the Unforeseeable
135
searching for answers to the ethical challenges imposed by nanotechnology in the complex
modern context.
6. Acknowledgment
This work would not have been possible without the services of the University of Brasilia
Central Library.
Thanks also to Dr. Gabriele Cornelli for his unselfish and unfailing support.
7. References
Cao, G. (2006). Nanostructures & Nanomaterials: Synthesis, Properties & Applications, Imperial
College Press, ISBN 978-981-4322-50-8, London, United Kingdom
Drexler, E.K. (2004). Nanotechnology: From Feynman to Funding. Bulletin of Science,
Technology & Society, Vol. 24, No. 1, (February 2004), pp. 21-27, ISSN 0270-4676.
Dupuy, J-P. & Grinbaum, A. (2004). Living with Uncertainty: Toward the Ongoing
Normative Assessment of Nanotechnology. Techné, Vol. 8, No. 2, (December –
March 2004), pp. 4–25, ISSN 1091-9264.
Dupuy, J-P. (2006). Les Défis Éthiques des Nanotechnologies. Science & Devenir de l'Homme :
Les Cahiers du MURS, No. 47, (January-March 2006), pp. 53-67, ISSN 1950-4527.
Ferrari, A. (2010). Developments in the Debate on Nanoethics: Traditional Approaches and
the Need for New Kinds of Analysis. Nanoethics, Vol. 4, No. 1, (April 2010), pp. 27-
52, ISSN 1871-4757.
Feynman, R.P. (1961). There’s Plenty of Room at the Bottom. In: Miniaturization, Gilbert,
H.D., pp. 282-296, Reinhold Publishing Corporation, ISBN 978-027-8919-12-9, New
York, United States of America.
Franklin, S. (1995). Science as Culture, Culture of Science. Annual Review of Anthropology,
Vol. 24, (October 1995), pp. 163-84, ISSN 0084-6570.
Freitas, R.A. (2005). What is Nanomedicine? Nanomedicine, Nanotechnology, Biology and
Medicine, Vol. 1, No. 1, (March 2005), pp. 2-9, ISSN 1549-9634.
Garrafa, V. (2006). Multi-inter-transdisciplinaridade, complexidade e totalidade concreta em
Bioética. In: Bases Conceituais da Bioética: Enfoque Latino-Americano, Garrafa, V.;
Kottow, M. & Saada, A., pp. 73-85, Gaia, ISBN 85-7555-077-2, São Paulo, Brazil.
Grunwald, A. (2005). Nanotechnology — a New Field of Ethical Enquiry? Science and
Engineering Ethics, Vol. 11, No. 2, (April 2005), pp. 187–201, ISSN 1353-3452.
Invernizzi, N. (2008). Visions of brazilian scientists on nanosciences and nanotechnologies.
Nanoethics, Vol. 2, No. 2, (August 2008), pp. 133-148, ISSN 1871-4757.
Johnson, D.G. (2007). Ethics and Technology ‘in the Making’: an Essay on the Challenge of
Nanoethics. NanoEthics, Vol. 1, No. 1, (March 2007), pp. 21-30, ISSN 1871-4757.
Jotterand, F. (2005). Nanotechnology, Bioethics and the Techno-Scientific Revolution: Philosophical
and Ethical Assessment of Nanotechnology and Its Applications in Medicine [PhD
Thesis], Rice University, Houston, United States of America.
Jotterand, F. (2006). The Politicization of Science and Technology: Its Implications for
Nanotechnology. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, Vol. 34, No. 4, (December –
March 2006), pp. 658-666, ISSN 1748-720x.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
136
Kaiser, M. (2006). Drawing the Boundaries of Nanoscience: Rationalizing the Concerns?
Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, Vol. 34, No. 4, (December – March 2006), pp. 667-
674, ISSN 1748-720x.
Kearnes, M. & Macnaghten, P. (2006). ``Re-imagining Nanotechnology''. Science as Culture,
Vol. 15, No. 4, (December 2006), pp. 279- 290, ISSN 1470-1189.
Khushf, G. (2007). Open Questions in the Ethics of Convergence. Journal of Medicine and
Philosophy, Vol. 32, No. 3, (June 2007), pp. 299 – 310, ISSN 1744-5019.
Kuhn, T.S. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, University of Chicago Press, ISBN
978-022-645-808-3, Chicago, United States of America.
Macnaghten, P. (2010). Researching Technoscientific Concerns in the Making: Narrative
Structures, Public Responses, and Emerging Nanotechnologies. Environment and
Planning A, Vol. 42, No. 1, (January 2010), pp. 23- 37, ISSN 1472-3409.
Meaney, M.E. (2006). Lessons from the Sustainability Movement – Toward an Integrative
Decision-Making. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, Vol. 34, No. 4, (December –
March 2006), pp. 682-688, ISSN 1748-720x.
Medeiros, E.S.; Paterno, L.G. & Mattoso, L.H.C. (2006). Nanotecnologia. In: Nanotecnologia:
Introdução, Preparação e Caracterização de Nanomateriais e Exemplos de Aplicação,
Durán, N.; Mattoso, L.H.C. & Morais, P.C., pp.14-29, Artliber, ISBN 978-858-8098-
336, São Paulo, Brazil.
Mehta, M. (2002). Nanoscience and Nanotechnology: Assessing the Nature of Innovation in
these Fields. Bulletin of science, technology & Society, Vol. 22, No. 4, (August 2002),
pp. pp. 269-273, ISSN 0270-4676.
Mnyusiwalla, A.; Daar, A.S. & Singer, P.A. (2003). ‘Mind the Gap’: Science and Ethics in
Nanotechnology. Nanotechnology, Vol. 14, No. 3, (March 2003), pp. R9-R13, ISSN
1361-6528.
Morin, E. (1988). Le Défi de la Complexi. Revue Chimères, No. 5-6, pp. 79-94, ISSN 0986-
6035.
Morin, E. (2008). Blind Intelligence. In: On Complexity, Morin, E., pp. 1-5, Hampton Press,
ISBN 978-157-2738-010, New Jersey, United States of America.
National Science Foundation (NSF). (2000). Nanotechnology Definition, In: National Science
Foundation, March 30, 2010, Avaiable from:
<http://www.nsf.gov/crssprgm/nano/reports/omb_nifty50.jsp>
Nordmann, A. (2004). Molecular Disjunctions: Staking Claims at the Nanoscale. In:
Discovering the Nanoscale, Baird, D.; Nordmann, A. & Schummer, J. (Eds.), pp. 51-55,
IOS Press, ISBN 978-158-6034-672, Amsterdam, Netherlands.
Olivé, L. (2006). El Bien, el Mal y la Razón: Facetas de la Ciencia y de la Tecnologia, Paidós, ISBN
978-968-8534-533, Mexico City, Mexico.
Petersen, A. & Anderson, A. (2007). A Question of Balance or Blind Faith? Scientists and
Science Policymakers Representations of the Benefits and Risks of anotechnologies.
NanoEthics, Vol. 1, No. 3, (December 2007), pp. 243-256, ISSN 1871-4757.
Popper, K. (2009). Darwinism as a Metaphysical Research Programme. In: Philosophy After
Darwin: Classic and Contemporary Readings, Ruse, M., pp. 167-174, Princeton
University Press, ISBN 978-0691135540, Princeton, United States of America.
Nanotechnology and Ethics: Assessing the Unforeseeable
137
Pyrrho, M. (2008). Nanociência e Bioética: Novas Abordagens Éticas para Novos
Paradigmas Científicos. Revista Brasileira de Bioética, Vol. 4, No. 3-4, (October –
December 2008), pp. 222-235, ISSN 1808-6020.
Ratner, M. & Ratner, D. (2003). Nanotechnology: a Gentle Introduction to the Next Big Idea,
Prentice Hall, ISBN 978-013-1014-008, New Jersey, United States of America.
Rip, A. (2006). Folk Theories of Nanotechnologists. Science as Culture, Vol. 15, No. 4,
(December 2006), pp. 349- 365, ISSN 1470-1189.
Sahoo, S.K.; Parveen, S. & Panda, J.J. (2007). The Present and the Future of Nanotechnology
in Human Health Care. Nanomedicine, Nanotechnology, Biology and Medicine, Vol. 3,
No. 1, (March 2007), pp. 20-31, ISSN 1549-9634.
Salamanca-Buentello, F.; Persad, D.L.; Court, E.B.; Martin, D.K.; Daar, A.S. & Singer, P.A.
(2005). Nanotechnology and the Developing World. Plos Medicine, Vol. 2, No. 5,
(May 2005), pp. 383-386, ISSN 1549-1676.
Salvarezza, R.C. (2003). Why is Nanotechnology Important for Developing Countries?
Proceedings of the Third Session of the World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific
Knowledge and Technology, Rio de Janeiro, Brazil, December 2003, pp. 134-36,
Avaible from: < http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0013/001343/134391e.pdf>
Savadori, L.; Savio, S.; Nicotra, E.; Rumiati, R.; Finucane, M. & Slovic, P. (2004). Expert and
Public Perception of Risk from Biotechnology. Risk Analysis, Vol. 24, No. 5, (October
2004), pp. 1289-1299, ISSN 1573-9147.
Schnaiberg, A. (2006). Contradições nos Futuros Impactos Socioambientais Oriundos da
Nanotecnologia. In: Nanotecnologia, Sociedade e Meio-ambiente, Martins, P.R.(org.),
pp. 79-86, Xamã, ISBN 85-7587-056-4 , São Paulo, Brazil.
Schummer, J (2004). “Societal and Ethical Implications of Nanotechnology”: Meanings,
Interest Groups, and Social Dynamics. Techné, Vol. 8, No. 2, (December – March
2004), pp. 56-87, ISSN 1091-9264.
Schummer, J. (2007). Identifying Ethical Issues of Nanotechnologies. In: Nanotechnologies,
Ethics and Politics, Ten Have, H.A.M.J. (ed.), pp. 79–98, UNESCO Publishing, ISBN
978-923-1040-511, Paris, France.
Shrader-Frechette, K. (2007). Nanotoxicology and Ethical Conditions for Informed Consent.
Nanoethics, Vol. 1, No. 1, (March 2007), pp. 47-56, ISSN 1871-4757
Slovic, P. (1987). Perception of Risk. Science, Vol. 236, No. 4799, (April 1987), pp. 280-286,
ISSN 1095-9203.
Sotolongo, P.L. (2006). O Tema da Complexidade no Contexto da Bioética. In: Bases
Conceituais da Bioética: Enfoque Latino-Americano, Garrafa, V.; Kottow, M. & Saada,
A., pp. 93-113, Gaia, ISBN 85-7555-077-2, São Paulo, Brazil.
Stirling, A. (2007) Risk, Precaution and Science: Towards a More Constructive Policy. EMBO
Reports, Vol. 8, No. 4, (April 2007), pp. 309–315, ISSN 1469-3178.
Swierstra, T. & Rip, A. (2007). Nano-Ethics as NEST-Ethics: Patterns of Moral
Argumentation About New and Emerging Science and Technology. NanoEthics,
Vol. 1, No. 1, (March 2007), pp. 3-20, ISSN 1871-4757.
Victoriano, J.M.R. (2006). Intersecções entre Sociologia e Ecologia: a Pesquisa como
Fenômeno Social Total a partir da Perspectiva Crítica de Jesús Ibáñez. In:
Bioethics in the 21st Century
138
Nanotecnologia, Sociedade e Meio-ambiente, Martins, P.R.(org.), pp. 87-109, Xamã,
ISBN 85-7587-056-4 , São Paulo, Brazil.
Wagner, V.; Dullaart, A.; Bock, A-K. & Zweck, A. (2006). The Emerging Nanomedicine
Landscape. Nature Biotechnology, Vol. 24, No. 10 (October 2006), pp.1211-1217, ISSN
1546-1696.
9
Speculative Ethics:
Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac?
Gareth Jones, Maja Whitaker and Michael King
Bioethics Centre and Department of Anatomy, University of Otago
New Zealand
1. Introduction
The excitement generated by major scientific advances almost inevitably leads to intense
speculation concerning the uses to which these advances will be put. Since some of these
will be accompanied by ethical challenges, it is appropriate for bioethicists to delve into
their potential ethical implications. If the ethical dimensions of such advances can be
outlined and analyzed in advance, this would appear to be a welcome contribution to any
public debate that may ensue. However, the speculations range from those that could
eventuate within the near future and would represent an incremental change to present
practices, to those that are vastly less likely to come to pass and predict paradigmatic shifts
of momentous proportions. The challenge for bioethicists is to determine whether they
should devote their attention to such extreme speculative possibilities, or to more
circumscribed speculations, or indeed whether it is better to focus on existing issues, rather
than those that are merely possible.
An illustration of more circumscribed speculation is provided by no less a scientific
authority than Francis Collins in his 1999 Shattuck Lecture, in which he speculated on the
medical and societal consequences of the Human Genome Project in 2010, just 11 years into
the future. He described this as a hypothetical clinical encounter in which a 23-year-old
undergoes a battery of genetic tests. This was because by 2010 Collins speculated that the
field of pharmacogenetics would have blossomed to such an extent that a prophylactic drug
regimen based on personal genetic data could be prescribed to reduce cholesterol level and
the risk of coronary artery disease (Collins, 1999). As we look back at 2010 we can see that
these goals have not as yet been realized at the level hypothesized by Collins. The question
then is whether bioethical enquiry into the prospects opened up by genomic medicine has
been weakened by this excessive optimism.
Interestingly, at much the same time, Holtzman and Marteau (2000) contended that the new
genetics would not revolutionize the way in which common diseases are identified or
prevented. In wanting people to see beyond the genetic hype, they pointed to the
importance of existing issues, such as social structures, lifestyle and environment, for much
of disease. They also questioned how much interest would be shown in being tested
genetically and even more in making appropriate lifestyle choices. These too are
considerations calling for the attention of bioethicists.
It is evident then that even relatively focused speculation has its problems. What about far
more exploratory and aggressive speculation? Garreau (2005) considers that we are at a
Bioethics in the 21st Century
140
turning point in history since our technologies are now capable of altering our minds,
memories, metabolisms, personalities and progeny, and similar conjectures motivate Bailey’s
(2005) “liberation biology”. Such vistas have led serious scholars to devote considerable effort
towards counteracting what they see as a dangerous drift towards human self-modification,
genetic perfectibility and eugenic aspirations (Habermas, 2003). The end-result of these
biomedical technologies, it is claimed, is the emergence of programmed people, epitomized by
lack of moral responsibility since they are no longer the authors of their own selves. These
concerns emanate directly from taking seriously highly speculative futuristic visions of
medical accomplishments and often conflating these with current reality.
The question we are addressing here is whether bioethicists should spend time and effort on
speculative possibilities like these. In this chapter we describe and analyze some areas of
applied ethics (particularly bioethics) in which speculation is at its most adventurous, such
as nanotechnology, genetic technology, regenerative medicine, and cryonics. Possibly the
most speculative of these is cryonics, which draws on the rest as potential means for
fulfilling its vision. Because of these qualities, cryonics will be explored in greater depth as a
case study in speculative ethics.
The technologies underlying these areas require ethical attention and analysis; they deliver
new abilities into the hands of those who seek to use them, and ethical reflection helps to
determine the nature and extent of use that can be defended as being responsible. There
may be instances where this leads to a call for a prohibition on the use of a particular
technology, as has been the case of genetic engineering. Further, a new technology can have
unintended consequences that ethical scrutiny can help to reveal and evaluate.
In evaluating new and emerging technologies one of the major problems is arriving at an
understanding of what the technologies are, and of how they might be developed in the
future. This, as we have seen, is a path beset by uncertainties, yet understanding them as
much as possible is integral to informing moral evaluation of them. This is because
judgments that rely on false beliefs about new technologies can have pernicious
consequences for the use of the technologies, and for the credibility of applied ethics. As
speculation becomes more radical, and our uncertainty about the prediction increases, the
epistemic status of applied ethics becomes less secure, and its value more questionable. To
explore these issues, we address arguments for and against the role of speculation in ethical
analysis of technology, and suggest some boundaries on ethical engagement with
speculative matters. First, we will survey some areas of science and technology, focusing on
the role that speculation has played in their development.
2. Genomic medicine
Genetics has to some degree always played a role in modern health care, but it was thought
that the decoding of the human genome in 2003 would provide unprecedented
understanding of the functions and interactions of the entire genome, producing a
revolution in health care under the rubric of genomic medicine (Guttmacher and Collins,
2002). It was hoped that a clearer picture of the human genome would particularly
transform the treatment of multifactorial disorders such as breast and colorectal cancers,
and Alzheimer’s and Parkinson’s diseases, where inherited risk has long been implicated
but little understood. Genomics was expected to uncover the mechanisms of complex
diseases, including asthma, hypertension, and diabetes. Vignettes were frequently
proposed, featuring a patient visiting a doctor, who would order genetic testing that
Speculative Ethics: Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac? 141
revealed certain genetic predispositions, allowing the doctor to craft a personalized
approach to care, ensuring optimized prevention, diagnosis and treatment. There can be
little doubt that these confident claims for genomic medicine were put forward in good
faith. However, it was faith in an overly reductive and deterministic view of genetics, and in
the ability of biomedical scientists and their clinical colleagues to translate the believed
promise of genetic science into clinical reality. The gulf between genomics and personalized
medicine turned out to be far greater than envisaged, resulting in an overstated optimism
(Guttmacher & Collins, 2002; van Ommen et al., 1999) that, as mentioned, resulted in what
now appear to have been quite unrealistic timescales (Collins, 1999).
It has emerged that even though markers of human variation (single nucleotide
polymorphisms) can be associated with disease predisposition in large population samples,
they contribute little to the apparent heritable risk and have poor predictive power at the
individual level (Kraft & Hunter, 2009). Sequencing an individual’s genome can produce a
large amount of information, but the data is difficult to interpret, and so genomic medicine
still has little effect on the health care of individuals (Collins, 2010; Hall et al., 2010).
The push to decode the genome carried with it an impetus to explore the ethical, legal and
social implications of the new genetic knowledge, with the Human Genome Project
dedicating five per cent of its budget to this cause. The program focused on clinical
integration of genetic technology, public and professional education, and the fair use of
genetic information, particularly in employment and health insurance (Collins, 1999). The
aspiration to anticipate these implications before they transpire has been beneficial in
allowing the formulation of appropriate guidelines and legislation, even though the
timescales expected have proved awry (Ginsburg & Willard, 2009).
In terms of speculative ethics, therefore, genomic medicine stands as a beacon of hope.
There has been speculation, some of which has been astray. Nevertheless, it has been limited
in scope and concerted efforts have been made, and continue to be made, to tie in the
scientific advances with considered ethical input and direction. The resulting liaison
between the science and the ethics has been to the benefit of both.
3. Nanotechnology
The term “nanotechnology” was coined in 1974 by Norio Taniguchi (Taniguchi, 1974) and
popularized in 1986 by Eric Drexler (who may have been unaware of its earlier usage) in his
book “Engines of Creation: The Coming Era of Nanotechnology” (Drexler, 1986).
“Nanotechnology” refers to the manipulation of matter at the atomic level. At this scale
particles have different mechanical, electrical, thermal, optical and magnetic properties,
possibly allowing the development of a whole range of materials and devices with new
applications in fields as diverse as medicine and energy production. It has
been postulated that nanomachines will one day be responsible for food production, biological
repair, sewage processing, commodity fabrication, and house cleaning (Milburn, 2002).
Early discussions of molecular manufacturing were preoccupied with self-replicating
nanomachines, and the prospect of the world being converted into a grey goo by these
nanobots, a scenario sketched by Drexler in his seminal work (Drexler, 1986). Thus, a
speculative doomsday scenario has characterized the field of nanotechnology from its earliest
beginnings. Unfortunately, this has continued to dominate popular perception of
nanotechnology (Sheetz et al., 2005), so much so that Drexler wishes he had never coined the
term (Giles, 2004). He writes, “Fears associated with that old scenario are interfering with
Bioethics in the 21st Century
142
current research. . . . Researchers resent it and I want to clean up the mess.” (Giles, 2004).
Drexler now acknowledges that nanoscale manufacturing does not require self-replicating
devices, and so this conjectural danger can be avoided through prohibition (Phoenix and
Drexler, 2004). The most fruitful area of research to date has been the production of nanoscale
particles, such as carbon nanotubes, for the manufacture of characteristic materials for use in
electrical circuits, textiles, and cosmetics (Coyle et al., 2007; Mu & Sprando, 2010).
However, the fears provoked by the “grey goo” scenario have persisted, and apparently
have been manipulated by some environmental groups to engender support for their
present concerns regarding technology profiteering (Giles, 2004). By contrast, in informed
circles the nanotechnology debate has settled down into less spectacular, but more
substantive issues, such as the possible toxicity of nanomaterials (Xia et al., 2009), their
effects on biological systems (Navarro et al., 2008) and the global economic effects of a
possible nanotechnology revolution.
The relevance of this area for the present essay is the role of applied ethics in such ongoing
debate. To what extent does bioethical commentary continue to grapple with speculative
and alarmist scenarios? It is likely that the “grey goo” possibilities occupied attention that
could otherwise have been directed towards the issues that ethicists are now focusing on, to
far greater benefit. However, the dramatic and catastrophic threat described by Drexler’s
scenario seems to demand addressing. These typify the problems posed by speculative
matters in applied ethics, which we will explore later.
4. Regenerative medicine
The term “regenerative medicine” first appeared in the literature in 1992 as a hypothetical
future technology that could revolutionize clinical treatment (Kaiser, 1992). The idea gained
momentum when embryonic stem cells were isolated in 1998 (Thomson et al., 1998), and the
possible clinical significance of their growth potential and pluripotency was appreciated. In
theory, damaged tissues and organs could be regenerated by insertion of stem cells,
stimulation of endogenous stem cells, or transplantation of tissues or organs grown in vitro
from the patient’s own stem cells (Mironov et al., 2004). The underlying hope is that these
techniques will radically advance the treatment of diseases as wide-ranging as Alzheimer’s
and Parkinson’s diseases, diabetes and spinal cord injury.
As is often the case at the cutting edge of scientific development, exciting prospects raise
unwarranted hopes bereft of a feasible scientific basis, and this has been particularly so in
the field of regenerative medicine (Kirkpatrick et al., 2006). The prospects within
regenerative medicine have captured the imagination of commentators from a variety of
backgrounds, who too often have moved with undue haste from considering the use of stem
cells to treat disease and disability to the potential to redesign human nature (Bostrom, 2005;
Glannon, 2008; Ip, 2009b). Regenerative medicine is depicted by some as being “rich with
Promethean promises”(Ip, 2009a, p. 3). It is here that we enter the realm of transhumanism
and posthumanism, where ethicists have considered the implications of these in terms of the
exacerbation of social inequalities, intergenerational fairness, environmental ethics, and the
problems posed by endless life spans, with subsequent divergence of enhanced and
unenhanced human species (Agar, 2007).
Far away from these highly speculative vistas, in today’s laboratories the field of
regenerative medicine faces complex difficulties that are hampering the clinical application
of stem cells at the most basic level. For example, scientists are yet to ascertain how to
reliably direct cell differentiation to the desired lineage and modify cells without raising the
Speculative Ethics: Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac? 143
risk of tumor formation (Kirkpatrick et al., 2006). While this is a rapidly moving area of
research, solutions to these basic problems will likely come gradually and hype should be
tempered with caution (Daley, 2010).
Regenerative medicine raises bioethical challenges at different levels. Discussion that
uncritically conflates regenerative medicine and its likely prospects with grandiose claims
about remaking what it means to be human (e.g. Ip, 2009b) is profoundly misleading.
Distaste over the latter claims may unfairly taint regenerative medicine, with the end-result
of discouraging what could turn out to be extremely helpful medical interventions. While
this may not be the intention of such commentators, it will only be avoided by clearly
distinguishing the speculative hype from the serious science. Regenerative medicine in the
clinic is not being driven by a program that views the human body as infinitely plastic, or
that denies human finitude and mortality, and yet this is the concern of some who have
been taken in by speculative hype (e.g. Song, 2009). Speculative bioethics of this ilk will
simply perpetuate fundamental misconceptions.
Also of concern is the preoccupation of ethical debate on stem cells with the moral status of
embryos. It is true that embryos are destroyed in the process of deriving embryonic stem cells.
This is therefore a legitimate topic for debate and should not be avoided. However, this is not
the sole area of bioethical debate on the potential of stem cells, especially as they relate to
regenerative medicine. Lysaght and Campbell have cogently argued that bioethicists must also
give due attention to the largely neglected issues of informed consent processes, the
exploitation of women, the commodification of human tissue, science communication and the
ownership of immortal cell lines (Lysaght & Campbell, 2011). All these are core ethical
considerations for regenerative medicine as it seeks to enter the clinic. The fact that devoting
attention to the issue of the embryo’s moral status has left other important issues unattended
shows the scarcity of moral consideration as a resource, and raises the question of how this
consideration should be distributed. Speculative scenarios, with little if any relation to current
clinical practice, such as the remaking of human nature through regenerative medicine,
threaten to displace attention further from pressing current and emerging issues.
5. Cryonics
In simple terms cryonics is the practice of storing at very low temperatures the bodies or
heads of legally deceased people (or animals), termed cryonic suspension. The purported
value of cryonic suspension is that, from the stored body/head, the dead individual may be
able to be resuscitated, allowing physical life after an indefinite period of death.
If there is a landmark publication for cryonics, it is Robert Ettinger’s book “The Prospect of
Immortality” (Ettinger, 1965). This is an attempt at a systematic evaluation of, and positive
program for, the cryonics project. At the time of its publication no human bodies had been
stored using cryonics, although the principle of freezing and reviving whole animals had been
successfully demonstrated by Audrey Smith in the 1950s (Parry, 2004). Smith had succeeded in
reviving some hamsters after freezing at -5 ºC for 50-70 minutes, a minority of which survived
for times approaching the normal hamster lifespan. However, Smith also established that this
limited success disappeared if animals were frozen for longer than 70 minutes.
Presumably seeing the cup as half-full, Ettinger attempted to outline a viable approach to
cryonics. Not a cryobiologist (he was a retired college maths and physics teacher at the
time), Ettinger provided a semi-scientific evaluation of the problems facing the success of
the cryonics enterprise, and an optimistic view of its eventual success. In a section entitled
Bioethics in the 21st Century
144
“After a Moment of Sleep” (Ettinger, 1965, pp. 5-6) he describes a tired old man who will
think of his death as merely a moment of dreamless sleep, like anaesthesia. This man will
“awaken” unaware of the potentially vast period of time elapsed, and find himself in either
a rejuvenated state, or about to undergo a process of “renovation”. This can provide, if
desired, the “physique of Charles Atlas”. His “weary and faded wife” may also choose a
physique to “rival Miss Universe” if she wishes. And, more importantly, “they will be
gradually improved in mentality and personality”. He imagines a future world which
resembles “the present, king-sized and chocolate covered”, in which “the resuscitees, will be
not merely revived and cured, but enlarged and improved, made fit to work, play, and
perhaps fight, on a grand scale and in a grand style.” (Ettinger, 1965, p. 6)
With fanciful claims such as these in a foundational document of cryogenics, it is not
surprising that the movement has been subject to ridicule. However, Ettinger acknowledges
that “to remove the prospect of immortality from the realm of thin, hazy speculation or
daydreams and secure it in the domain of emotional conviction and work-a-day policy…
objections must be met, [and] a host of troublesome questions answered.” (Ettinger, 1965,
pp. 6-7) This is what his book aimed to do.
Many of the objections and troublesome questions may be of ethical importance. For
instance, is cryonics impossible, perhaps even in principle? If so, are companies offering
cryonic services being misleading at best or fraudulent at worst? What is the legal and moral
status of the bodies in cryonic storage? If the claims of cryonicists are borne out in the
future, what lives would the patients awake to, and could they reasonably be said to have
consented to this given what they knew before they died? Should cryonics be judged more
as a medical or mortuary procedure?
In order to evaluate cryonics ethically, it is necessary to know what the process might
involve. In the light of this how likely is it that any of these currently impossible stages of
the process will eventuate in the foreseeable future?
Cryonics may be divided into four stages: patient preparation and freezing, storage,
renovation and resuscitation, and life. The first stage is the preparation and freezing of the
cryonics patient. Here, the body of a patient is prepared for freezing, and rapidly cooled to a
temperature below -120ºC. Various procedures are undertaken by cryonicists with the aim
of minimizing post-mortem damage to the body (see Best, 2008). This damage is in part
what would occur to any body after breathing and blood circulation cease (broadly termed
ischemic injury (Kerrigan & Stotland, 1993)), and in part injury that can result from the
cooling process (mainly ice crystal formation (Best, 2008)).
Once the body is appropriately prepared, cooling to temperatures below -120ºC occurs. The
goal for cryonicists at this stage is to achieve vitreous cooling with the aim of avoiding the
cellular damage caused by conventional freezing through ice crystal formation (Best, 2008).
Cooling a large biological system like a human body to a contiguous vitreous state is not
achievable at present – something cryonicists appear to freely admit (Fahy et al., 1990; Fahy,
2004). The main focus of cryonics is the resuscitation of the person who died (i.e. their
identity or conscious self), not merely their body. Consequently, cryonics has tended to
focus on achieving vitrification primarily in the part of the body they believe necessary for
this to occur, viz., the brain (Best, 2008), hoping that its smaller size will give greater chance
of success. Many cryonics facilities offer storage for so-called “neuro-suspension or neuro-
preservation” (Parry, 2004, p. 394) patients, namely, the preserved heads (with enclosed
brain) of those who have died.
The second stage is the storage of the cooled cryonics patient at low temperatures until
scientific advances make successful resuscitation possible. The main issue here seems to be
Speculative Ethics: Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac? 145
storing the patient at a sufficiently low temperature that vitrification is maintained, yet high
enough to minimize cracking and fracturing of the glassy, vitreous tissue which can occur at
very low temperatures (Parry, 2004). A second issue in the storage phase is the maintenance of
the patient in the cooled state continuously for an undefined period of time. This is dependent
on the cryonic facilities being operational for that time, and also the storage being funded by
the patient for the undefined duration – difficult matters to ensure with certainty.
The third stage is the renovation and resuscitation of the patient. Here speculation is at its
most extreme. While there are considerable problems associated with the previous stages,
these pale in comparison to the problems faced in thawing, repairing, reviving and perhaps
enhancing the cryonics patient. However, cryonics has an in-built defence against these
problems – the seemingly limitless potential for science and medicine to advance and
overcome obstacles, if it is provided with sufficient time. The strength of cryonics is that the
stored cryonics patients have plenty of time to spare.
Thus, while cryonicists give the impression of taking seriously the challenge of reducing
obstacles to successful revival, there is always the possibility of appealing to speculative
possibilities within future science as the solution. This means that scientific limitations do
not have to be addressed too directly. Nevertheless, the potential problems are legion. These
include: repair of whatever dysfunction or injury caused the death of the patient, and
damage occurring between this time and freezing; repair of any damage caused by the first
and second stages of cryonic intervention, such as toxic effects of the cryoprotectants, ice
damage or fracturing of vitrified tissue; thawing the body, avoiding or treating de-
vitrification (cellular collapse) and any other damage caused; removal of cryoprotectants
and reperfusion of the body with blood, while avoiding reperfusion-induced injury; any
problems associated with reviving the conscious person from their deceased state, to a
healthy and possibly enhanced state.
Cryonicists argue that these seem like huge problems from the point of view of current
science and technology. A strong theme underlying their confidence in the power of future
science and technology is often a highly reductive view of biology and medicine. According
to this, all of the problems mentioned above are simply a matter of atoms being in the
wrong configuration within a biological system; move the atoms into the correct
configuration and energy state, and the patient is resuscitated. The clearest statement of this
is provided by Merkle (1992, pp. 6-7): “… the purpose of medicine is to change
arrangements of atoms that are ‘unhealthy’ to arrangements of atoms that are ‘healthy’.”
From this reductive view, future developments in medicine will involve gaining better
control over our ability to manipulate atoms – medicine (especially that involved in
cryonics) will be a matter of nanotechnology (Merkle, 1992). The cryonics community’s
endorsement of nanotechnology is probably not welcome news to those scientists studying
the behaviour of matter on a very small scale. In fact nanoscientists have often sought to
distance themselves from this type of science fiction speculation (Milburn, 2002) in much the
same way as cryobiologists have sought to distance themselves from cryonics.
The speculation increases even further when considering the life awaiting a resuscitated
cryonics patient. An idealistic vision is exemplified by Ettinger’s claim that “You and I, as
resuscitees, may awaken still old, but before long we will gambol with the spring lambs –
not to mention the young chicks, our wives.” (Ettinger, 1965, p. 63). Less optimistic, but
equally speculative, possibilities could include life in an impaired mental or physical state as
a result of imperfect techniques – a life with unforeseen suffering, perhaps that one might
judge not worth living. Another might be that continuity of consciousness is lost, causing
Bioethics in the 21st Century
146
the revived person to effectively be a new individual without any memory of their previous
pre-resuscitation life (that such loss may occur is even admitted by a cryonicist (Best, 2008)).
5.1 What is an appropriate ethical analysis of cyronics?
Each of the stages of cryonics as it is currently practised and envisioned by cryonicists is a
potential focus of ethical scrutiny. Cryonics is regarded by its adherents as an indefinitely
prolonged medical procedure. Considering it from this point of view, it should be analyzed
as such, opening up a vast array of medical ethical considerations. For example, is the
consent given by the cryonics patient adequate considering the unknown nature of much of
what the full procedure may entail? Should patients be able to undergo cryonic preservation
before legal death, when cryonicists claim it would be more likely to be effective? A
practical legal issue is the property status of the revived person and their body. As current
law stands in most jurisdictions in which cryonicists operate, property rights over the
deceased person’s body are ceded to the cryonics company (it is treated as a bequeathed
cadaver) – is this reversible if the cadaver comes back to life? What is the moral and legal
status of the frozen body, and what implications does this have for the standard of care
provided by the cryonics facility? Is the prolonging of individual lives (potentially
indefinitely, according to cryonicists’ vision of future medicine) morally wrong, justifiable,
or perhaps even required? And if the latter, should public funding be provided for the
practice and for research to further its development and use?
Alternatively, cryonics could be viewed as an intricate and expensive mortuary procedure.
From this point of view a largely different analysis emerges, characterized by different
issues. For example, since cryonics is not marketed as an alternative to embalming and
burial or cremation, are people who enter the contract being defrauded? What should be
made of the (on this account) mistaken beliefs of those practising and undertaking the
procedure? Should the wishes of cryonics patients be respected posthumously, especially
when these are wishes that can (or, at best, may) never be realized? Is cryonics a repugnant
use of a dead body, and, if so, does this have any normative implications?
Depending on one’s judgment of the future success of cryonics, two quite different, and
ultimately incompatible, avenues of ethical consideration will be pursued. It should be
noted that, for those stored cryonically and for cryonicists, the decision of whether cryonics
should be treated more or less speculatively by bioethicists is nothing less than a matter of
life or death. Cryonics patients are at risk by their being incorrectly treated as cadavers – for
example undermining research into their reanimation, and giving insufficient support for
their care while in storage. The quality of their future lives is also at risk through insufficient
preparation for eventual reanimation. Should bioethicists consider these questions even
though they may be skeptical about the science? If the claims and objectives of cryonics are
taken seriously, to focus on the wrong question could be decried as being complicit in
killing (or perhaps letting die), or at best harming, these patients (Nordmann, 2007).
How should ethicists decide between these two possibilities? One option is to consider both,
however this means that a great deal of time is devoted to considering highly speculative
possibilities, which may never eventuate. Perhaps the likelihood of one or the other being
correct should be estimated, and the lower probability, speculative scenario eschewed in
favour of the other. This grounds ethical analysis in reasonable scientific understanding and
expectation, and confines ethics to those moral issues that are currently present—in this
case, the current reality of individuals having their cadavers frozen and stored indefinitely
postmortem—rather than those that may never exist at all.
Speculative Ethics: Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac? 147
6. The problems of speculation in ethics
It is worth remembering what may be at stake, both in the case of cryonics, but also for
speculative matters more broadly. If considerable attention is devoted to speculative
possibilities like cryonics, what is at stake is the neglect of more current moral issues from
which practical and ethical attention has, to some degree, been diverted (Nordmann, 2007).
Whatever response one might make will have to take note of competing priorities: to devote
attention to the ethical demands made by suffering due to famine, environmental disasters,
or war, the needs of the infertile, the chronically sick or the terminally ill, against the
demands of those who have freely decided to undergo cryonics in the hope of a better life at
some indefinite time in an indefinite future.
One problem of speculative ethics is epistemological – the more speculative and removed from
present experience possibilities become, the more uncertain our knowledge becomes. It will
have little in common with current technology. For example, Drexler’s speculative ideas about
self-replicating nanomachines bore little resemblance to nanotechnology at the time he
published Machines of Creation. Moreover, it bears little resemblance to current
nanotechnology, which has advanced significantly in the manufacturing of nanoscale products
using techniques such as self-assembly, rather than the more fanciful nano-machines of
Drexler’s speculation. While Drexler’s general idea of the way in which nanotechnology will
develop is not necessarily false (only time can determine this), there is little relationship
between these speculative visions and existing technologies. This may do intense disservice to
existing technologies and the way in which they are perceived (Jones, 2006).
However, like all empirical predictions about the way a technology will emerge or develop,
speculations, such as those of Drexler, may indeed be false. In this way, speculative claims
informing ethical reasoning suffer from the same weakness that afflicts the empirical version
of slippery slope arguments. Empirical slippery slope arguments rest on an empirical
prediction, arguing that (acceptable) policy or situation A will, as a result of social or
psychological tendencies, result in the emergence of (unacceptable) policy or situation B.
Like any forward-looking empirical claim, it is open to challenges on its assumptions about
social or psychological tendencies or whatever mechanism is being used to justify the claim.
An overarching problem is that it is usually only in retrospect that we can know with any
certainty whether our speculations or prognostications were accurate. Also of relevance to
this discussion is our inability to predict future scientific developments with reliable
accuracy. One only has to think of once assured dicta that, with hindsight, proved
unwarranted obstacles to further research. There was the alleged inability of the central
nervous system to regenerate to any discernible extent after birth, or to replace any of its
neurons (Ramon y Cajal, 1928). Alongside this can be placed the alleged impossibility of
cloning in mammals (McGrath & Solter, 1984). We have already discussed the opposite
phenomenon, which is the occurrence of obstacles that either were not predicted, or were
underestimated. Clearly, when dealing with predictions, ethicists, as much as other
philosophers, scientists, and policy makers, need to be wary.
A second problem is that these epistemological problems have moral consequences. As
ethics becomes more speculative, its relation to the technology that it is discussing grows
increasingly tenuous. This raises problems we have already touched on. First, it diverts
ethical attention away from current concerns pertaining to the technology, concerns often in
need of ethical attention. Second, the speculative moral judgments about a technology can
influence current perceptions of it. Hence, an emerging technology can be smothered or
hampered, either by the weight of enthusiastic speculative expectations (such as has
Bioethics in the 21st Century
148
arguably been the case for genomic medicine (Evans et al., 2011)), or by the weight of moral
and social condemnation as a result of the harmful implications of the speculative aspects of
the technology (such as the grey goo scenario for nanotechnology). Both can have unjustly
negative consequences for the technology under discussion.
Applied ethics must be applicable to some ethical issue or problem. Unfortunately,
speculative ethics relates to speculative. Consider the ethical discussion on genetic testing
in assisted reproductive technologies (ARTs) regarding whether embryos with particular
genetic combinations should or should not be implanted in a woman for further
development. While a much of this work has addressed pressing issues such as the moral
status of these types of procedures and the implications this may have for social
regulation of reproductive choices, a troublingly large portion of this work anticipates or
presupposes a future in which the desired genetic composition of a child can be
determined or when all human reproduction is handled by technological means such as
these (Sharma, 2007; Steinbock, 2008). Excessive concentration on the latter at the expense
of the former is paying more attention to speculative scenarios far removed from current
scientific reality than to current applied ethical considerations. Speculative ethics does not
conform to paradigmatic work in applied ethics, in that it addresses imaginary (and
perhaps never to be realized) moral problems, not extant, or often even very likely,
practical problems.
This raises the question of whether ethicists should be free to consider whatever they like, or
as we are arguing, should their attention be directed towards particular issues and projects?
Moral reflection is not an infinite resource and this leads to the question of how it should
best be distributed. One plausible way of distributing a scarce resource is to do so in a way
that maximizes benefit. The prima facie case described here is that, unlike paradigmatic
applied ethics, the benefits of speculative ethics are not clear, since it does not directly
address extant moral problems (Nordmann, 2007; Nordmann & Rip, 2009).
We argue that, since those engaging in speculative ethics are doing so at the expense of
addressing real (i.e. not imaginary) moral issues, there is a distributive justice problem here.
This allows ongoing moral problems to persist, whether these be problems related to
famine, harmful exploitation of the vulnerable, or health inequalities. These wrongs and the
suffering they cause are immense and are currently occurring. The obligation to use moral
reflection to address these problems ought to be a concern for every moral philosopher,
motivating them to seek as just a distribution of their discipline’s work as possible. If these
problems and many like them are taken seriously, they lead to a commitment to work on
problems like these rather than on highly speculative ones.
Thus, speculative ethics may squander the benefit that can be derived from the application
of moral reasoning to current problems. However, speculative ethics may go further than
this, reducing the potential of some current and emerging technologies to realize their
benefits for society, and in this way diminishing the means available for addressing current
problems. Examples already alluded to include nanotechnology and the self-replicating
nanobots and “grey goo” scenarios, and regenerative medicine with speculative concerns
about radical life extension and a posthuman future.
A related manner in which speculative ethics can negatively affect current and emerging
technology is the flipside of the first. This technology can be overwhelmed by a weight of
expectation that it is unable to match. This has arguably been the case for genomic
technologies, with their expectation of ushering in a new era of personalized medicine with its
tailored pharmacological and behavioural prevention and treatment of disease (Collins, 1999).
Speculative Ethics: Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac? 149
This raises an interesting issue since in this case the problems have been created more by
scientists than by ethicists. Much of the hype has come from scientists within the field,
perhaps “talking up” the potential impact of their work in an attempt to gain research
grants in an extremely competitive funding market, and also reflecting excitement at the
promise certain emerging technologies might hold (Evans et al., 2011). As outlined earlier,
the director of the National Human Genome Research Institute in 1999 anticipated the
hugely beneficial effect that genomics would have on medicine by 2010 (Collins, 1999).
Collins does caution that his vision has obstacles to its realization, but the ones he identifies
are not scientific, but rather ethical and practical. According to Collins (1999) ethical and
regulatory hurdles must urgently be addressed to ensure that genetic information is not
misused, and health professionals, such as medical genetic specialists, must be educated to
ensure that they are up to the task of understanding and treating patients using genomic
medicine.
The moral imperative that Collins asserts is an example of what Nordmann has referred to
as “foreshortening of the conditional”, a general problem that he claims underlies much
speculative ethics (Nordmann, 2007; Nordmann and Rip, 2009). He characterizes such
speculative moral claims as having the conditional form: if conditions C obtain, then
speculative scenario A will occur, and this will create or exacerbate ethical issues I1, I2, and
so forth. The foreshortening of this conditional statement occurs when the “if” becomes
subsumed by the “then”, which he claims creates a mandate for action with respect to the
scenario and the ethical issues that arise:
‘If-and-then’ statements begin by suggesting possible technological developments and
then indicate consequences that seem to demand immediate attention. What looks like a
merely possible, and definitely speculative future in the first half of the sentence (the
‘if’), turns into something inevitable in the second half (the ‘then’). As the hypothetical
gets displaced by a supposed actual, the imagined future overwhelms the present
(Nordmann & Rip, 2009, p. 273).
Thus:
The true and perfectly legitimate conditional “if we ever were in the position to conquer
the natural ageing process and become immortal, then we would face the question
whether withholding immortality is tantamount to murder” becomes foreshortened to
“if you call into question that biomedical research can bring about immortality within
some relevant period of time, you are complicit with murder” – no matter how remote
the possibility that such research might succeed, we are morally obliged to support it
(Nordmann, 2007, p. 33).
Collins’ speculative vision of personalized genomic medicine in 2010 was false. As a result
of highly optimistic predictions such as this and others (Epstein, 2004), many of the
promises of genomic medicine remain unfulfilled (Evans et al., 2011) despite considerable
progress being made. It is now being asked whether time and money spent on genomic
medicine has been wasted, or would have been better spent elsewhere, such as on
population-based public health strategies to reduce smoking, obesity and risky alcohol use
(Hall et al., 2010; Holtzman & Marteau, 2000). Nordmann (2009) argues that dramatic
promises such as these are often made with regard to emerging technologies, and they
support the “conditional foreshortening” arguments that he maintains provide much of the
impetus for speculative ethics.
Evans et al. (2011) argue that conjectures, like that of Collins, about future developments
within science and technology can be – perhaps counter-intuitively – an impediment to
Bioethics in the 21st Century
150
their development. This is because they can underestimate the number and extent of
hurdles that must be overcome in the course of development, and overestimate the
benefits of their particular approach as a means to address problems. The combination of
these factors means that other potentially promising approaches can be overlooked,
leading to a crippling misallocation of resources, which can endanger the sustainability of
the field (Evans et al., 2011). In addition, scientific and technological promises made are
frequently not delivered on, which undermines the legitimacy of science in general, and
the field from which the speculation arises in particular (Nordmann & Rip, 2009). This
helps to explain the distance that many scientists seek from hyperbolic interpretations of
their work (such as those working within nanotechnology and cryogenic science). A
realistic appraisal of current and future developments in science, and the promises made
about science and technological development, is needed in order for it to receive the level
of trust and support that it deserves, but also, and perhaps more importantly, to allow for
the allocation of research resources to those areas of most (genuine) promise and moral
relevance.
Applying this approach to cryonics draws attention to the number and enormity of the
scientific hurdles that must be overcome in order for reanimation of stored bodies to be
possible, assuming that this is possible, even in principle. However, as mentioned above, the
peculiar nature of cryonics affords its devotees a response to objections of this kind, namely,
that the bodies can be maintained in storage until such time as science has developed
techniques for repairing and reviving them. Thus the fact that time-consuming scientific
hurdles must be overcome is not in itself seen as a problem with respect to the revival of the
stored bodies. However, the longer it takes for these hurdles to be overcome, the more likely
it is that other factors will arise to thwart or displace cryogenic aims, such as the possibility
that medical advances will extend human life to the extent that cryonics becomes irrelevant.
However, this assumes that revival of cryonically stored bodies is possible, and that
continuity of strong personal psychological identity is maintained in the revived body –
both extremely dubious assumptions.
While cryonics is an extreme illustration of speculation, both scientific and ethical, it
typifies the problems of speculative ethics. The example of Collins shows that even
relatively modest speculation can be problematic. These problems amount to a strong case
for the rejection of speculative ethics in favour of grounding ethics in realistic and
rigorous appraisals of science and technology, and a focus on current and imminent
concerns.
7. Exploring Roache’s defence of speculation
Our evaluation of speculative ethics would be incomplete without looking seriously at a
counter analysis in its favour. Roache’s (2008) article aims to defend speculative ethics against
the objections we have so far leveled at it, so it is important we explore it here. Roache begins
by pointing out the important role of thought experiments in philosophy, which are highly
imaginative and serve to test and analyze our intuitions, while noting that these are imaginative
analytic tools, rather than speculations about possible future events. Also, she argues that a vast
amount of ethical thinking involves anticipating, evaluating, and choosing among possible
future events – often very mundane ones – many of which will not come to pass.
Roache’s main argument can be summed up like this. (1) Some speculative future
possibilities may be great potential harms or goods. (2) We ought to determine which
speculative future possibilities are harmful or beneficial, so that the former can be avoided
Speculative Ethics: Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac? 151
and the latter pursued; ethical analysis is required to make these value judgments.
Therefore, (3) we ought to give ethical consideration to future possibilities.
This allows ethics to be in the business not merely of considering and solving current and
emerging problems, but also of shaping the direction of social and scientific development
away from future harms or towards future goods. To do otherwise would be to let science
and society develop without any moral guidance, allowing ethicists only the job of
solving problems once they have arisen or are imminent. She argues that many of our
most important projects are the result of moral evaluation of a problem and speculation
about potential future solutions to it. She cites as examples the development of the ARTs
that allow the selective implantation of embryos, as a response to the moral problem of
genetic disorders, and carbon capture technology as a response to the problem of global
warming. In one respect, these examples do not serve her position well. They are both
examples of current, not speculative, moral problems, for which technological responses
are developed. Devoting the scarce resource of moral attention to these is therefore
acceptable to the anti-speculation position. However, the development of solutions to
these moral problems may require speculation about the nature of possible solutions, and
the evaluation of these to determine which ones ought to be pursued. Roache argues that,
without this moral engagement with speculative possibilities, scientific resources may be
squandered by pursuing solutions that are morally problematic, or not maximally
beneficial.
A difficulty with Roache’s main argument arises with the quantifiers. Premise one can be
accepted. However, even if we accept that some speculative and unlikely possibilities are
worthy of ethical consideration, we must still determine which possibilities these are. This
requires that all possible future possibilities must be imagined and ethically evaluated, no
matter how unlikely. Thus the correct conclusion to the above argument is that we ought to
give ethical consideration to all future possibilities. Given the consideration that ethicists are
a scarce resource, it makes sense that their time should be spent wisely. Among the
infinitely many speculative possibilities, and the vast number of actualities to which
ethicists could direct their attention, it is plausible to argue that it would be best for them to
attend to those that are most significant morally and most likely to eventuate. She disagrees,
arguing that even moves to restrict scope to only those possibilities that are not known to be
highly unlikely are misguided. She cites two counter examples, and she uses these as
evidence that we take seriously highly unlikely possibilities when they promise great harm
or benefit. First is the possibility that the Large Hadron Collider will create a black hole that
will destroy the earth, which was the basis for a lawsuit to halt its activity (Boyle, 2008);
second is the fact that heroic efforts are often expended to provide benefit (such as
attempting to save a life) even when this is the least likely outcome.
The example of the Large Hadron Collider lawsuit is question-begging. While it does show
that the plaintiffs took seriously the threat that they believed the Large Hadron Collider
could pose to the future of the world, it does not show that anyone else did, or, more
importantly, that anyone would be right to. The argument mounted by the plaintiffs is
arguably an example of what Stich (1978) calls a “Doomsday Argument”. This is an
argument based on the principle that prohibition is required of any activity that holds a non-
zero chance of causing an unthinkably immense catastrophe. Such a principle would
prohibit a vast amount of innocuous work (in the sciences and elsewhere). For example,
there may be a non-zero possibility that a chemical synthesized in a laboratory may initiate a
chain-reaction that obliterates the ozone layer, destroying all life on earth. However,
Bioethics in the 21st Century
152
prohibiting all chemical synthesis based on this possibility would be ridiculous. Van der
Burg notes that these “Doomsday Arguments” are a philosophically uninteresting variant of
slippery slope arguments, in which the objected-to outcome “is so highly speculative that
the cogency of the argument—insofar as it exists—depends more upon the horror than upon
the likelihood [of it occurring]” (van der Burg, 1991, p. 43).
More challenging is Roache’s example of heroic attempts to save a life, such as a child
trapped in a cave. A search and rescue team is available; however, it is highly unlikely that
they will find the child alive. We may, she contends, react with horror to the suggestion that,
in light of the small probability of success, it is not worth the cost (in terms of time,
resources, risk of injury) deploying the search and rescue team. She argues that the value of
the child’s life is such that we deem it worth these heroic efforts, despite their highly
unlikely chance of success.
Clearly we do undertake these, but, as with the previous example, this does not show that
we are always right to do so, nor does it show why we might be right to. It is worth
noting that, if the rescue is undertaken, it may not be justified by the value of the
speculative outcome, but by the consequences of the undertaking regardless of outcome. For
example, in this case, the institution of child-rearing may be negatively affected by
parents believing that the state will abandon their children in times of great need, hence
the rescue must proceed. At an abstract level, the resources expended in such an
endeavour may produce greater benefit if spent elsewhere, say improving public health in
third-world countries, or providing vaccinations. However, Roache’s example is a
practical one, and the rescue team cannot be deployed to third-world countries to work on
sanitation systems there. In other words, this example is disanalogous in terms of
deciding which speculative possibilities are worth taking seriously in applied ethics and
pursuing as a society. Nevertheless, we might adjust the scenario to minimize this
problem, by having other children lost in other caves within the rescuer’s area.
Differences in the nature of the caves and the children make the chances of success
finding some more likely than others. There are enough rescuers to undertake some of the
rescues immediately, while others must wait. In this situation it is reasonable to undertake
those rescues with the greatest chance of success, or at least not to undertake those known
to be highly unlikely while others wait.
In light of these considerations, Roache’s example fails to show that we are wrong to
eschew options known to be highly unlikely in favour of other more likely options. But
the example does show that highly improbable, but highly valuable possibilities, may still
make moral demands on us. However, these are demands that must be weighed among
the many demands of other social, scientific and technological options. Roache
acknowledges that some projects will be unacceptably speculative and, given resource
constraints, more worthwhile options should be pursued in their stead. One could,
therefore, think that she endorses the kind of weighting that favours options addressing
current or imminent concerns over those that are distant and speculative (other things
being equal).
Nevertheless, she argues against this focus on “socially beneficial” outcomes, the
judgment of which she says is highly fallible, and influenced by factors such as fads,
prejudice, bias, and misconception. We would, therefore, have reason to view such a focus
as being shortsighted and misguided. To illustrate this point she uses the example of
bacterial antibiotic resistance, which she rightly states could render all antibiotics
ineffective against bacterial infection. She argues that this is not a current problem, since
Speculative Ethics: Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac? 153
there are still drugs that can treat the relevant diseases. She is right that there are drugs or
drug combinations that can be effective in treating antibiotic resistant diseases. She is also
correct in asserting that the emergence of bacterial strains that are resistant to all
antibiotics and their combinations is not a current problem, and therefore could be
excluded from a moral focus that privileges current over future problems. However, she
is wrong to infer that antibiotic resistance per se is not a current problem, and this
undermines her example.
A brief examination of Staphlococcus aureus is sufficient to reveal this. Penicillin resistant S.
aureus was a significant comorbidity during the influenza pandemic of 1957 and 1958
(Kunin, 1993; Schoenbaum, 2001), and, more recently, Methicillin-resistant S. aureus
(MRSA) was reported to increase mortality during the 2003-2004 and 2006-2007 influenza
seasons by 33 per cent. Meta-analysis of 31 articles published from 1980-2000 revealed that
patients with MRSA infection have significantly greater odds of mortality compared to
otherwise similar patients with Methicillin-susceptible S. aureus (Cosgrove et al., 2003),
despite the fact that at the time, MRSA was uniformly susceptible to treatment with
Vancomycin (which is no longer the case (Hiramatsu, 2001)). S. Aureus is one of many
such bacteria that exhibit rapid development of antibiotic resistance and pose a current
problem to successful treatment. Collectively, these findings show that her example fails
as an example of a merely future problem. The future development of alternatives to
antibiotics is an approach that would be effective for this current problem as well as
solving the future problem of total antibiotic resistance in pathogenic bacteria. Her
example shows that—contrary to her own argument— an emphasis on current or
imminent problems can yield solutions that are not shortsighted, but beneficial now and
in the probable future.
However, the point Roache is making is that there are serious future problems that we are
right to anticipate and devote our efforts towards solving. Although there would be
benefits to a cheap alternative to antibiotics now, even if this were not the case, we would
be right to devote resources to considering the moral implications of total antibiotic
resistance, and making efforts to develop alternatives to antibiotic use. Roache is correct
in stating that a position committing one only to considering current and imminent
problems may fail to prepare for or avoid some harmful future scenarios. It may also fail
to identify beneficial or harmful future scenarios. Despite their improbability, they may
still be significant enough to be worth our current attention. However, given the highly
contingent nature of many speculative possibilities, a prima facie preference towards
consideration of current and imminent problems seems reasonable. Roache’s arguments
against this restriction of scope are only partially successful; she does not challenge the
value of current moral problems and she acknowledges that many speculative
possibilities are so unlikely that attending to them would be a waste of time (Roache,
2008). We are then left in the middle ground of admitting a legitimate place for
speculative possibilities in moral thinking, but requiring that these be weighed against
actual or imminent issues.
How we weigh up the many current and potential future issues that could be attended to
is a difficult question. We suggest that relevant factors include a realistic and scientifically
rigorous assessment of the harms and benefits that each issue contains, and the likelihood
that future aspects might be realized. Roache makes the suggestion that “Reflecting on
where our most important values lie, and how we might work to maximise them, is surely
an important step towards ensuring that ethical concern, and other valuable resources, are
Bioethics in the 21st Century
154
not squandered” (Roache, 2008, p. 326). This is a good suggestion, which is compatible
with the middle-ground arrived at here. It should be noted that multiple values would
also have to be balanced against each other, thus prioritizing is inevitable.
Applying this to cryonics, we may decide, upon careful reflection, that one of our most
important values entails sustaining individual lives through the pursuit of life-extending
technologies such as this. In that case, full-blown cryonics is a live ethical issue, and we
should seriously consider taking steps to realize its potential. However, the highly
speculative nature of cryonics means that we can only have limited confidence that it is a
good means of pursuing that which we value. Moreover, a value that entails life-
prolonging technologies such as this would likely entail the promotion of life-prolonging
possibilities elsewhere. Maximization of this value would arguably require a much
greater focus on more reliable or likely means for prolonging life, such as public health
measures in third-world countries. Revisiting our modification of Roache’s analogy of
rescuing the trapped child may be useful here. In cryonics, there may be a possibility that
the frozen cryonics patients can be ‘rescued’ by future medicine. However, this is a rescue
effort of highly unlikely success, whereas there are other efforts in which success is vastly
more likely. To pursue the unlikely alternative at the expense of those that are so vastly
more likely would amount to irresponsible allocation of resources.
8. Conclusion
The degree to which ethics as a discipline should engage with highly speculative
possibilities is a significant matter at a time when science fact and fiction are becoming
increasingly difficult to disentangle (Jones, 2006). Cryonics has been used as a paradigmatic
example, the extreme nature of which highlights the issues involved for bioethicists. We
have argued that considerable caution is required when approaching all speculative
situations; the more extreme the situation the more cautious the response should be. Even if
it is conceded that speculation can be a useful tool for ethical reasoning, and that the pursuit
of speculative possibilities may in principle be justifiable, it is far from clear that the highly
speculative, like cryonics, offers sufficient likelihood of benefit to warrant consideration, let
alone prioritization ahead of more likely and beneficial future possibilities. Tempting as it
may be for bioethicists to be swept away by the apparently exciting and enticing
possibilities rampant in the literature, moves in the direction of speculative ethics ought to
be made with extreme caution.
9. References
Agar, N. (2007). Whereto Transhumanism? The Literature Reaches a Critical Mass. Hastings
Center Report, Vol. 37, No. 3, (May-June 2007), pp. 12-7, eISSN 1552 -146X, ISSN
0093 0334.
Bailey, R. (2005). Liberation Biology: The Scientific and Moral Case for the Biotech Revolution,
Prometheus Books, Amherst, ISBN-10: 159-1022274, ISBN-13: 978-1591022275,
NY.
Best, B. P. (2008). Scientific Justification of Cryonics Practice. Rejuvenation Research, Vol. 11,
No. 2, pp. 493-503.
Speculative Ethics: Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac? 155
Bostrom, N. (2005). A History of Transhumanist Thought. Journal of Evolution and Technology,
Vol. 14, No. 1, (April 2005), pp. 1-25, ISSN 1541- 0099.
Boyle, A. (2008), 'Doomsday Fears Spark Lawsuit over Collider'. In: MSNBC, April 4 2011,
Retrieved from: <http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/23844529/ns/technology_
and_science-science/>.
Collins, F. (1999). Medical and Societal Consequences of the Human Genome Project. New
England Journal of Medicine, Vol. 341, No. 1, (July 1999), pp. 28-37 ISSN 0028-4793,
eISSN 1533-4406.
Collins, F. (2010). Has the Revolution Arrived? Nature, Vol. 464, No. 7289, (April, 2010), pp.
674- 675, eISSN 1476 - 4687.
Cosgrove, S. E., et al. (2003). Comparison of Mortality Associated with Methicillin-
Resistant and Methicillin-Susceptible Staphylococcus Aureus Bacteremia: A
Meta-Analysis. Clinical Infectious Diseases, Vol. 36, pp. 53-59, eISSN 1537-6591,
ISSN 1058-4838.
Coyle, S., et al. (2007). Smart Nanotextiles: A Review of Materials and Applications. MRS
Bulletin, Vol. 32, No. 5, (May 2007), pp. 434-42.
Daley, G. Q. (2010). Stem Cells: Roadmap to the Clinic. The Journal of Clinical Investigation,
Vol. 120, No. 1, (January, 2010), pp. 8-10, ISSN 0021-9738, eISSN1558-8238.
Drexler, K. E. (1986). Engines of Creation, Anchor / DoubleDay, ISBN 0-385-19972-4, New
York
Epstein, C. J. (2004). Genetic Testing: Hope or Hype? Genetics in Medicine, Vol. 6, No. 4, pp.
165-72
Ettinger, R. (1965). The Prospect of Immortality, Sidgwick and Johnson, Retrieved from
<http://www.cryonics.org/book1.html>
Evans, J. P., Meslin, E. M., Marteau, T. M., & Caulfield, T. (2011). Deflating the
Genomic Bubble. Science, Vol. 331, No. 6019, (February, 2011), pp. 861-2, eISSN
1095 -9203.
Fahy, G. (2004). Cryopreservation of Organs by Vitrification: Perspectives and
Recent Advances. Cryobiology, Vol. 48, No. 2, (April 2004), pp. 157-78, ISSN 0011-
2240.
Fahy, G., Saur, J., & Williams, R. J. (1990). Physical Problems with the Vitrification of Large
Biological Systems. Cryobiology, Vol. 27, (October 1990), pp. 492-510, ISSN 0011-
2240.
Garreau, J. (2005), 'Let Humanity Prevail', The Age, August 11.
Giles, J. (2004). Nanotech Takes Small Step Towards Burying 'Grey Goo'. Nature, Vol. 429,
No. 6992, (June 2004), pp. 591, eISSN 1476-4687.
Ginsburg, G. S. & Willard, H. F. (2009). Genomic and Personalized Medicine: Foundations
and Applications. Translational Research: The Journal of Laboratory and Clinical
Medicine, Vol. 154, No. 6, (December 2009), pp. 277-87, ISSN 1931-5244, ISSN 0022-
2143.
Glannon, W. (2008). Decelerating and Arresting Human Aging, In: Medical Enhancement and
Posthumanity, B. Gordijn and R. Chadwick, pp. 175-89, Springer, ISBN 978-1-4020-
8851-3, Dordrecht; London.
Bioethics in the 21st Century
156
Guttmacher, A. E. & Collins, F. S. (2002). Genomic Medicine--a Primer. The New England
Journal of Medicine, Vol. 347, No. 19, (November 2002), pp. 1512-20, ISSN 0028-4793,
eISSN 1533-4406.
Habermas, J. (2003). The Future of Human Nature, Polity Press, ISBN 0-7456-2986-5,
Cambridge.
Hall, W. D., Mathews, R., & Morley, K. I. (2010). Being More Realistic About the Public
Health Impact of Genomic Medicine. PLoS Medicine, Vol. 7, No. 10,(October 2010),
p. e1000347, ISSN 1549-1277, eISSN 1549-1676.
Hiramatsu, K. (2001). Vancomycin-Resistant Staphylococcus Aureus: A New Model of
Antibiotic Resistance. The Lancet Infectious Diseases, Vol. 1, No.3, (October 2001), pp.
147-55, ISSN 1473-3099.
Holtzman, N. A. & Marteau, T. M. (2000). Will Genetics Revolutionize Medicine? New
England Journal of Medicine, Vol. 343, No. 2, (July, 2000), pp. 141-44, ISSN 0028-4793,
eISSN 1533-4406.
Ip, K.-T. (2009a). Introduction: Regenerative Medicine at the Heart of the Culture Wars, In:
The Bioethics of Regenerative Medicine, K.-T. Ip, pp. 3-10, Springer, ISBN 978-1-4020-
8966-4, Netherlands.
Ip, K.-T. (Ed.). (2009b). The Bioethics of Regenerative Medicine, Springer, ISBN 978-1-4020-
8966-4, Netherlands.
Jones, D. G. (2006). Enhancement: Are Ethicists Excessively Influenced by Baseless
Speculations? Medical Humanities, Vol. 32, No. 2, (September 2006), pp. 77-81.
Kaiser, L. R. (1992). The Future of Multihospital Systems. Topics in Health Care Financing, Vol.
18, No. 4, pp. 32-45.
Kerrigan, C. L. & Stotland, M. A. (1993). Ischemia Reperfusion Injury: A Review.
Microsurgery, Vol. 14, No. 3, (October 1993), pp. 165-75, eISSN 1098-2752.
Kirkpatrick, C. J., et al. (2006). Visions for Regenerative Medicine: Interface between
Scientific Fact and Science Fiction. Artificial Organs, Vol. 30, No. 10, (October, 2006),
pp. 822-7, ISSN 1525-1594.
Kraft, P. & Hunter, D. J. (2009). Genetic Risk Prediction - Are We There Yet? The New
England Journal of Medicine, Vol. 360, No. 17, (April 2009), pp. 1701-3, ISSN 0028-
4793, eISSN 1533-4406.
Kunin, C. M. (1993). Resistance to Antimicrobial Drugs - a Worldwide Calamity. Annals of
Internal Medicine, Vol. 118, No.7, (April 1993), pp. 557-61, ISSN 0003-4819.
Lysaght, T. & Campbell, A. V. (2011). The Ethics of Regenerative Medicine: Broadening the
Scope Beyond the Moral Status of Embryos, Third GABEX International Meeting,
Tokyo, February 2001.
McGrath, J., & Solter, D. (1984). Inability of Mouse Blastomere Nuclei Transferred to
Enucleated Zygotes to Support Development in Vitro. Science, Vol. 226, No. 4680,
(December 1984), pp. 1317-9, ISNN 0036-8075.
Merkle, R. C. (1992). The Technical Feasibility of Cryonics. Medical Hypotheses, Vol. 39, pp.
6-16
Milburn, C. (2002). Nanotechnology in the Age of Posthuman Engineering: Science Fiction
as Science. Configurations, Vol. 10, No.2 (Spring 2002),pp. 261-95, eISSN 1080-6520,
ISSN 1063-1801.
Speculative Ethics: Valid Enterprise or Tragic Cul-De-Sac? 157
Mironov, V., Visconti, R. P., & Markwald, R. R. (2004). What Is Regenerative Medicine?
Emergence of Applied Stem Cell and Developmental Biology. Expert Opinion on
Biological Therapy, Vol. 4, No. 6, (June 2004), pp. 773-81, ISSN 1471-2598, eISSN
1744-7682.
Mu, L. & Sprando, R. L. (2010). Application of Nanotechnology in Cosmetics.
Pharmaceutical Research, Vol.27, No.8,(August 2010), pp. 1-4, ISSN 0724-8741,
eISSN 1573-904X.
Navarro, E., et al. (2008). Environmental Behavior and Ecotoxicity of Engineered
Nanoparticles to Algae, Plants, and Fungi. Ecotoxicology, Vol. 17, No. 5, (July 2008),
pp. 372-86, ISSN 0963-9292, eISSN 1573-3017.
Nordmann, A. (2007). If and Then: A Critique of Speculative Nanoethics. NanoEthics, Vol. 1,
pp. 31-46
Nordmann, A. & Rip, A. (2009). Mind the Gap Revisited. Nature Nanotechnology, Vol. 4, No.
5, pp. 273-74
Parry, B. (2004). Technologies of Immortality: The Brain on Ice. Studies in the History and
Philosophy of Biology & Biomedical Science, Vol. 35, No. 2, (June 2004), pp. 391-413,
ISSN 1369-8486.
Phoenix, C. & Drexler, E. (2004). Safe Exponential Manufacturing. Nanotechnology, Vol. 15,
No. 8, (august, 2004),pp. 869-72, ISSN 0957-4484, eISSN 1361- 6528.
Ramon y Cajal, S. (1928). Degeneration and Regeneration of the Nervous System, Hafner,
New York.
Roache, R. (2008). Ethics, Speculation, and Values. NanoEthics, Vol. 2, pp. 317–27
Schoenbaum, S. C. (2001). The Impact of Pandemic Influenza, with Special Reference to
1918. International Congress Series, Vol. 1219, (October, 2001), pp. 43-51.
Sharma, D. (2007). Technogenesis Redesigns Phylogenesis: Or, When Liberation Biology
Meets Our Posthuman Future. Biotechnology Law Report, Vol. 26, No. 6, (December,
2007), pp. 575-82, eISSN 0730-031X.
Sheetz, T., Vidal, J., Pearson, T. D., & Lozano, K. (2005). Nanotechnology: Awareness and
Societal Concerns. Technology in Society, Vol. 27, No. 3, (August, 2005), pp. 329-45,
eISSN 0160-791X.
Song, R. (2009). Genetic Manipulation and the Resurrection Body, In: The Bioethics of
Regenerative Medicine, K.-T. Ip, pp. 27-45, Springer, 978-1-4020-8966-4,
Netherlands
Steinbock, B. (2008). Designer Babies: Choosing Our Children's Genes. The Lancet, Vol. 372,
No.9646, (October, 2008), pp. 1294-95, eISSN 1474-547X.
Stich, S. P. (1978). The Recombinant DNA Debate. Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 7, pp.
187-205
Taniguchi, N. (1974). On the Basic Concept of 'Nano-Technology', Proceedings of the
International Conference on Production Engineering, Part II, Tokyo, JSPE 2, pp.18-
23, 1974.
Thomson, J. A., et al. (1998). Embryonic Stem Cell Lines Derived from Human Blastocysts.
Science, Vol. 282, No. 5391, (November, 1998), pp. 1145-7, ISSN 0036-8075
van der Burg, W. (1991). The Slippery Slope Argument. Ethics, Vol. 102, No. 1, pp. 42-65
Bioethics in the 21st Century
158
van Ommen, G. J., Bakker, E., & den Dunnen, J. T. (1999). The Human Genome Project and
the Future of Diagnostics, Treatment, and Prevention. Lancet, Vol. 354, Suppl. 1,
(July, 1999), pp. S5-10, ISSN 0140-6736.
Xia, T., Li, N., & Nel, A. E. (2009). Potential Health Impact of Nanoparticles. Annual Review of
Public Health, Vol. 30, (April 2009), pp. 137-50, eISSN 1545-2093.
... Since there were 16 questions, the range of score was from 16 to 48. Thus, the Attitude score calculated was categorized into 3 levels: Do not approve (16)(17)(18)(19)(20)(21)(22)(23)(24)(25)(26), Unsure (27)(28)(29)(30)(31)(32)(33)(34)(35)(36)(37) and approve (38-48). To find out the correlation between knowledge and attitude Pearson's correlation was applied and for statistical significance, p-value <0.05 were considered. ...
Article
Full-text available
Background: Health care providers as a trusted source of information for most patients should be able to provide counseling services to patients on the new concept of stem cells utilization, benefits and its practice implications.Objective: this study aims to assess the knowledge and attitude of health care providers in Qassim region regarding stem cells.Methods: Self-administered tools were utilized among 250 health care providers were chosen from five major hospitals in Qassim, including doctors, nurses, and other health care providers such as pharmacists, dietaries and administrative staff.Results: The participants were female,<30 years in age, had practiced for <10 years and nurses. About 56% of respondents had a moderate knowledge regarding stem cells, and only 31.2 % had good knowledge. About three quarters 191 (76.4%) of the participants exhibited positive attitude towards stem cells use. A Pearson’s correlation between knowledge and attitude scores was statistically significant. Conclusion: Data from the present study revealed the moderate levels of knowledge and positive attitude toward stem cells and its application among health care providers in Qassim. Therefore, this study suggests that educational programs on stem cells should be implemented to improve stem cells knowledge and encourage a more positive attitude.
... For instance, if we believe that human personhood begins at conception, the destruction of embryos for research cannot be justified. In case of ensoulment, however, destruction of embryos can be justified before the milestone to provide a treatment for patients (27). As mentioned, religious context have an influential effect on the issue of personhood. ...
Article
Full-text available
The clinical potentials of stem cells in cell-based therapies have raised great hopes in diabetes mellitus as well. However, there are complex ethical, legal, and socio-cultural issues surrounding the subject. In this paper, we intend to review in brief the main ethical issues for endocrinologists and other clinicians who are interested and work in the field of cell therapy and research.
... Since there were 16 questions, the range of score was from 16 to 48. Thus, the Attitude score calculated was categorized into 3 levels: Do not approve (16)(17)(18)(19)(20)(21)(22)(23)(24)(25)(26), Unsure (27)(28)(29)(30)(31)(32)(33)(34)(35)(36)(37) and approve (38-48). To find out the correlation between knowledge and attitude Pearson's correlation was applied and for statistical significance, p-value <0.05 were considered. ...
Article
A smoothing transformation, Legendre and Chebyshev collocation method are presented to solve numerically the Voltterra-Fredholm Integral Equations with Logarithmic Kernel. We transform the Volterra Fredholm integral equations to a system of Fredholm integral equations of the second kind, using a smoothing transformation to cancel the singularities in the kernel, a system Fredholm integral equation with smooth kernel is obtained and will be solved using Legendre and Chebyshev polynomials. This lead to a system of algebraic equations with Legendre or Chebychev coefficients. Thus, by solving the matrix equation, Legendre and Chebychev coefficients are obtained. Some numerical examples are included to demonstrate the validity and applicability of the proposed technique.
Article
Full-text available
Islam gives legal precedence to purity of lineage and known parenthood of all children. In Islam treatment to infertility using IVF is permitted within validity of marriage contract with no genes mixing. The paper shows that the Qur’ān, the word of Allah, and science, the deeds of Allah are not in major conflicts in defining the start of human life. The Holy Qur’ān provides an elegant description of origin, developmental stages of intra-uterine life. The Hadith explains two positions one that believes human embryo get ensouled at conception and the other after 40 days of conception. The paper aims to find that Islam confers moral respect to human embryo, but it also clarifies the absence of full human rights to a developing foetus. In Islam, human embryonic use is probably permissible for therapeutic and reproductive purpose keeping intact the principles of Shari’ah.
Article
Full-text available
The purpose of this paper is to debate whether or not the embryonic stem cell research should be permitted, or even encouraged. I will argue that we have a moral duty to encourage the advance of scientific knowledge (by learning how the embryo stem cell works) and to allow developments in medicine (by using therapies resulted from embryo stem cell research), yet understanding the risks that such research and knowledge brings. Therefore, I will discuss a few medical and procedural aspects regarding embryonal stem cells, I will briefly present several perspectives upon embryo moral status and also upon the most important slippery slope dangers concerning embryonic stem cell research. All of these aspects will be approached focusing not only on potential benefits, but mainly on the correct understanding and appropriate calculation of the risks involved.
Conference Paper
Full-text available
Abstrak Perkembangan sains dan teknologi kini telah mencetuskan inovasi dan penemuan baharu dalam pelbagai bidang. Khususnya dalam penghasilan produk makanan, terdapat trend pemprosesan yang bersifat mesra alam selain daripada permintaan tinggi serta keperluan pasaran terhadap produk terlibat. Antara produk berkenaan adalah penghasilan daging kultur atau daging makmal. Daging ini tidak lagi dihasilkan secara alami melalui penternakan di ladang-ladang, sebaliknya ia dihasilkan di makmal dan kilang. Bahkan ia boleh mendatangkan manfaat yang banyak kepada pengguna. Selain bersifat mesra alam, proses penghasilannya juga ekonomik serta boleh dipelbagaikan gizinya. Biasanya dalam proses pengkulturan daging, terdapat beberapa teknik yang digunakan seperti scaffold structure, organ printing dan tissue culture. Justeru dalam kajian ini, pengkaji hanya akan menfokuskan terhadap penggunaan stem sel berasaskan teknik scaffold structure sahaja. Pengkaji akan meneliti teknik yang digunapakai serta sumber stem sel yang diambil dalam pengkulturan daging. Berasaskan data-data yang dikumpulkan, pengkaji akan menganalisis pandangan ulama terhadap teknik dan produk akhir yang dihasilkan. Ini kerana proses pengkulturan daging berhubungkait dengan pengubahan ciptaan Allah SWT serta sumber stem sel akan memberi implikasi terhadap hukum memakan daging kultur tersebut. Justeru, satu panduan hukum Islam akan dihasilkan berdasarkan penelitian terhadap pengkulturan daging. Kata kunci: pengkulturan daging, daging kultur, hukum Islam, halal dan haram, sains dan teknologi 3 rd Postgraduate Conference on Science and Technology Studies 2014 (22 nd – 23 rd December 2014) Organized by
Article
Full-text available
Patient-centred system of care is essential in managing many disorders such as diabetes mellitus. The cultural and religious context can influence the involvement of patients and their families in such a care. We intend to discuss patient-centred care in diabetology in view of Islam. For more clarification, we will take into consideration a few illustrative lines of argument in detail about situation in Iran. In conclusion, dynamic spirit of Islamic jurisprudence is reflected in its adaptability to change in medical practice. In recent decades, Iranian religious scholars have provided scientists in new fields of science and research with appropriate directions and guidelines. Decree issued by Iranian religious leaders permitting research on stem cells for therapeutic purposes in many disorders including diabetes mellitus is one example. Understanding of the nature of Islam is importance for communication with patients in Islamic countries.
Article
Full-text available
Patients, families, and health care providers have a right to expect that ethics consultants can deal competently with the complex issues that they are asked to address. The Society for Health and Human Values–Society for Bioethics Consultation Task Force on Standards for Bioethics Consultation explored core competencies and related issues in ethics consultation. This position paper summarizes the content of the resulting Task Force Report, which included nine general conclusions: 1) U.S. societal context makes “ethics facilitation” an appropriate approach to ethics consultation; 2) ethics facilitation requires certain core competencies; 3) core competencies can be acquired in various ways; 4) individual consultants, teams, or committees should have the core competencies for ethics consultation; 5) consult services should have policies that address access, patient notification, documentation, and case review; 6) abuse of power and conflicts of interest must be avoided; 7) ethics consultation must have institutional support; 8) evaluation of process, outcomes, and competencies is needed; and 9) certification of individuals and accreditation of programs are rejected. *For members of the Society for Health and Human Values–Society for Bioethics Consultation Task Force on Standards for Bioethics Consultation, see Appendix 1.
Article
Full-text available
Gender-related factors and the social and economic conditions that impact the lives and health of women injection drug users (IDUs) in Chicago are described. Although study participants are highly imaginative and resourceful in terms of income-generating self-sufficiency, they engage in a variety of behaviors that put them at risk of contracting infectious diseases such as HIV and hepatitis B and C viruses. We point out that labor inequalities experienced by women IDUs, together with the gender ideologies that support those inequalities, provide reduced opportunities to practice harm reduction and other health care options.
Article
Stem cells (SCs) are pluripotent cells that retain the ability to develop into all cell types. This characteristic makes them appealing for use in research with view of therapeutic use, especially in "regenerative medicine." Stem cell sources include the following: 1. Embryonic stem cells (ESCs): These are derived from the inner cell mass of developing embryos. 2. Adult stem cells (ASCs): The best known source of ASCs is the hematopoietic cells of the bone marrow. These have been used clinically with good results in the treatment of leukemias. Very few ASCs may be present in other organs, e.g. the brain. 3. Cord blood: Cord blood is another source of "adult" hematopoietic stem cells. 4. Therapeutic cloning: Therapeutic cloning utilizes nuclear transfer techniques to produce pluripotent SCs with the genome of the nucleus of origin. These cells can be induced to differentiate into replacement cells for transplantation into the individual from whom the original cell was obtained, thus eliminating the requirement of immune suppression. In this paper I will discuss the potential and realized gains of stem cell therapies as well as the potential problems associated with their use. I then will discuss the ethical dilemma that this research entails as it deals with the human embryo. I will discuss the moral status of the embryo and the varying views of ethicists in this regard and then I will discuss the opinion of religious communities and, specifically, the Islamic perspective. Islamically, stem cell research is probably permissible, except for the creation of embryos for the specific purpose of using them only in research. Therapeutic cloning will be Islamically acceptable when the intent is to create tissue/organ from the individual who needs it, the procedure is feasible, and the result is expected to be good. Finally, I will discuss the present status of stem cell research in the United States and the politics that impact it. http://dx.doi.org/10.5915/39-2-5425
Article
Sociologists of science and others have long been interested in how advances in science come about, and their potential social and economic impacts. Developments in nanoscience and nanotechnology will provide social scientists with a unique opportunity to explore how scientific activities form de novo. Additionally, scientists will have the opportunity to examine the factors that drive science and technology in certain directions by considering how different models of innovation may explain how the topography of the knowledge-based economy is being shaped by radically new approaches to science.
Article
This study addresses current social and ethical concerns as well as the public's perception of research and development in nanotechnology. Significant efforts have to be made to increase public awareness of this new field in order to avoid unexpected and/or unwarranted backlash. Results from a survey on nanotechnology awareness are presented, showing that only 17% of the respondents were able to identify what nanotechnology is, with 76% of the respondents being men.
Article
Regenerative medicine is rich with Promethean promises. The use of human embryonic stem cells in research is justified by its advocates in terms of promises to cure a wide range of diseases and disabilities, from Alzheimer’s and Parkinsonism to the results of heart attacks and spinal cord injuries. More broadly, there is the Promethean allure of being able to redesign human biological nature in terms of the goals and concerns of humans. Needless to say, these allures and promises have provoked a wide range of not just moral but metaphysical reflections that reveal and reflect deep fault lines in our cultures.