ArticlePDF Available

Music-Colour Synaesthesia: A Sensorimotor Account

Authors:

Abstract

This paper presents a sensorimotor account of music-colour synaesthesia, proposing a radically different perspective than is commonly provided. Recent empirical and theoretical work in music cognition moves away from cognitivist accounts, rejects representationalism, and embraces an embodied standpoint. It has been shown that some forms of synaesthesia may be elicited from a concept alone and are often accompanied by shapes and textures. It is from this perspective that a skilful engagement with the environment and relevant sensorimotor contingencies may be identified. Here the role of embodied and enactive perception in general music cognition is extended to music-colour synaesthesia, and an argument is made for how the attributes of bodiliness and grabbiness might be found in a sonic environment, and how music listening might be perceived as an act of doing.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1029864920956295
Musicae Scientiae
1 –20
© The Author(s) 2020
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/1029864920956295
journals.sagepub.com/home/msx
Music-Colour Synaesthesia:
A Sensorimotor Account
Caroline Curwen
University of Sheffield, UK
Abstract
This article presents a sensorimotor account of music-colour synaesthesia, proposing a radically different
perspective than is commonly provided. Recent empirical and theoretical work in music cognition moves
away from cognitivist accounts, rejects representationalism and embraces an embodied standpoint.
It has been shown that some forms of synaesthesia may be elicited from a concept alone and are often
accompanied by shapes and textures. It is from this perspective that a skilful engagement with the
environment and relevant sensorimotor contingencies may be identified. Here the role of embodied and
enactive perception in general music cognition is extended to music-colour synaesthesia, and an argument
is made for how the attributes of bodiliness and grabbiness might be found in a sonic environment, and how
music listening might be perceived as an act of doing.
Keywords
synaesthesia, music, music-colour, sensorimotor, cognition
Coloured hearing, or chromesthesia, is an umbrella term that includes music-colour synaesthe-
sia (Ward, Huckstep, & Tsakanikos, 2006). Synaesthesia has been described as “a union of the
senses” (Cytowic, 2002, p. 325) arising from the stimulation of one sense (an inducer) trigger-
ing a reaction in an unstimulated second sense (a concurrent) (Grossenbacher & Lovelace,
2001). This article examines the congruence between general music cognition and synaesthe-
sia, interpreting music-colour synaesthesia within the broader frameworks of embodied and
extended music cognition, in which action and interaction with the environment are central to
music perception. It argues that music-colour synaesthesia is best understood as a sensorimo-
tor phenomenon, rather than understanding it as a particular neurological condition. This
view resonates with recent research in embodied and enactive music cognition, moves away
from traditional cognitivist accounts, rejects representationalism, and embraces a more situated
standpoint (Krueger, 2009, 2011, 2014; Loaiza, 2016; Maes etal., 2014; Reybrouck, 2014,
2017; Schiavio etal., 2017; Schiavio etal., 2019; van der Schyff etal., 2018).
In order to come to a balanced perspective on music-colour synaesthesia as a sensorimotor
phenomenon, this article provides, first, a brief overview of the phenomenon of synaesthesia,
Corresponding author:
Caroline Curwen, Department of Music, The University of Sheffield, Jessop Building, 34 Leavygreave Road, Sheffield, S3
7RD, United Kingdom.
Email: ccurwen1@sheffield.ac.uk
956295MSX0010.1177/1029864920956295Musicae ScientiaeCurwen
research-article2020
Article
2 Musicae Scientiae 00(0)
focusing on music-colour synaesthesia. Next, developments of research in general music cog-
nition are outlined that describe engagement with music, including music listening, as an act of
doing. The third section discusses how music-colour synaesthesia may indeed be explained from
a sensorimotor perspective. The final section discusses challenges presented by synaesthesia to
sensorimotor theory, and how these may be resolved arguing for a shift in perspective of music-
colour synaesthesia from being regarded as special to being illustrative of how typical, but indi-
vidualised music cognition may develop.
Synaesthesia
Researchers are beginning to challenge the assumption that a single mechanism underlies all
forms of synaesthesia (Auvray & Deroy, 2015), and Simner (2012), for example, rejects a one-
for-all explanation. Although synaesthesia has been described as a merging of the senses, not
all types are cross-sensory. Evidence shows that it can be activated by a concept alone (van
Leeuwen etal., 2015); the inducer does not have to be physically present (Meier, 2014). For
example, Dixon and colleagues (2000) found that synaesthetes responded to the concept of 7
triggered by the presentation of 5+2 in the absence of the actual number, and Ward, Tsakanikos,
and Bray (2006) found that the concept of musical notation was enough to elicit a synaesthetic
response. These findings have led to the development of alternative theories such as ideaesthesia
(Jürgens & Nikolić, 2012; Nikolić, 2009), meaning “sensing concepts” (Mroczko-Wąsowicz &
Nikolić, 2014, p. 4), connecting sensation and phenomenal experiences, or qualia, with their
conceptual triggers or semantic inducers. Qualia is the term used to describe the qualities of
subjective experience associated with certain sensory stimuli (see Jackson, 1982). In music,
this might include the difference in experience between a melody played on a piano and the
same melody played on a French horn (see also Curwen, 2018).
Synaesthetic experiences have been described by Wager (1999) as “extra qualia” (p. 264)
that manifest themselves differently from synaesthete to synaesthete. Attempts to explain
extra qualia associated with synaesthesia challenge philosophies of mind such as representa-
tionalism: “the view that the phenomenal character of an experience supervenes on its rep-
resentational content [or] the way an experience seems to its subject is . . . the way the
experience represents the world as being” (Wager, 1999, p. 263). Tye (1998) ventures that
phenomenal character must be identical to its representational content. The challenge to
representationalism posed by synaesthesia is that it appears at odds with reality. Experiencing
green in response to music does not mean the music is actually green, nor that the synaes-
thete is experiencing green-ness (Auvray & Deroy, 2015). There is much disagreement on
this topic (see Curwen, 2018).
Differences between higher and lower synaesthetes, and between associators and projectors,
further highlight the diversity of synaesthetic manifestations. The distinction between higher
and lower synaesthetes was first proposed by Ramachandran and Hubbard (2001), based on
evidence of cross-activation mechanisms operating at different times and in different locations
in the brain. Lower synaesthetes were thought to process information at an early stage in the
fusiform areas that manage form and colour perception, while higher synaesthetes were
thought to process information at a later stage in areas that manage the conceptual aspects of
colour. Associators describe their experience as being in the mind’s eye (Dixon etal., 2004;
Dixon & Smilek, 2005) or as knowing the colour (Ward etal., 2007), while projectors claim to
see colours projected outside the body into external space (Smilek etal., 2001). It appears rea-
sonable to consider associators as higher synaesthetes and projectors as lower synaesthetes,
but this has not been substantiated by research and in some studies the two dimensions of
Curwen 3
synaesthesia are shown to be orthogonal (Ward etal., 2007). The crucial distinction between
associators and projectors lies in the experience of the concurrent, while that between higher
and lower synaesthetes lies in the nature of the inducer. Lower synaesthetes can perceive col-
ours in their mind’s eye, and higher synaesthetes can be projectors. These examples, among
many others, illustrate that the potential scope of music-colour synaesthesia is very wide.
Coloured Hearing
Tone-colour synaesthesia is the type of music-colour synaesthesia examined most often: single
tones and chords, isolated from any musical context, elicit specific colours. It has been attrib-
uted to neurological mechanisms, specifically bottom-up processing (see Music-Colour
Synaesthesia below). However, the synaesthetic experience of music is not just about the ability
to assign a colour to individual tones or chords, nor is it just about sound (Mills etal., 2003).
Timbre, tempo, and emotion mediate the experience, and some synaesthetes have to hear an
entire musical piece to produce a synaesthetic response (Curwen, 2018). In this article I focus
on higher, concept-driven, forms of music-colour synaesthesia.
According to Peacock (1985) there are four broad categories of musical inducer: composi-
tional style, timbre, tonality, and pitch (tone). Concurrents are almost always experienced as
colour, but can also be experienced as shapes, spatial layouts and textures (Eagleman & Goodale,
2009). Synaesthetes often experience more than one form simultaneously and in various com-
binations. For example, GS, the sole participant in Mills etal.’s (2003) study, experienced large
blocks of darker colours when hearing heavy metal music, and unpleasant colour combina-
tions when hearing music she disliked. The particular colours were influenced by changes in
instrumentation or timbre, and higher and lower pitches were associated with lighter and
darker colours, respectively. She also experienced shapes, texture, and movement creating land-
scapes that she referred to as maps, that moved at speeds in accordance with the tempo of the
music and were often easier for GS to follow than standard musical notation.
There are some similarities between synaesthetic experiences and typical non-synaesthetic
cross-modal associations, such as those between pitch height and lightness (Eitan & Timmers,
2010; Ward, Huckstep, & Tsakanikos, 2006) and pitch height, size, and brightness (von
Hornbostel, 1925; Marks, 1974, 1987). Marks (1975) argues that the cross-modal mecha-
nisms underlying synaesthesia and general cognition are so similar that the former can be seen
as a kind of shorthand for the latter (p. 325).
Music-Colour Synaesthesia and General Cognition
Krueger (2011, 2014) argues that music helps individuals realise emotional and social experi-
ences in everyday life. According to the original extended mind thesis (EMT), cognitive processes
are not confined to the head, nor even the body, but extend into the external world (Clark &
Chalmers, 1998): a pen and paper aids calculation, a cane helps the blind navigate, and musi-
cal instruments facilitate music production (Chemero, 2018). The EMT has been expanded to
propose a dynamic coupling system between subject and environment (Sutton, 2010; Kirchhoff,
2012). Colombetti and Roberts (2015) explain that a “self-stimulating, coupled relationship is
instantiated” (p. 1259) between a saxophonist and their instrument demonstrating that the
relationship extends beyond “skull and skin” (p. 1244) to affective states: the sound produced
by the instrument affects the player’s emotional experience, influencing what they play next.
Reybrouck (2017) suggests that musical sense-making derives from the mediation of cognitive
events by sensorimotor interactions with the physical world, which may be multimodal. The
4 Musicae Scientiae 00(0)
addition of a visual modality to an auditory modality may make a listener aware of previously
hidden auditory information, modifying their perceptual experience. Interpreting synaesthesia
in similar terms challenges the prevailing view that music-colour synaesthesia is a form of
cross-sensory imagery with neurological origins.
Notwithstanding the rarity of synaesthetic experiences, and their characteristic automatic-
ity and consistency, music-colour synaesthesia may not be so different from typical music cog-
nition. Barsalou’s perceptual symbol systems theory (PSS) explains how a conceptual system
grounded in perception might work (1999, 2003). When people perceive objects, their basic
sensorimotor experiences are captured as sensory symbols so that patterns of activation estab-
lished during early sensory processing can be re-enacted subsequently. Conceptual systems
derive from category knowledge, each category relating to a different component of experience
(Barsalou, 2003). Individual concepts are the product of repeated re-enactments of the pattern
of activation established when the object was perceived for the first time. These re-enactments
are only partial, however; certain elements of the original pattern of activation evoked by the
perception of the object remain, but context determines the nature of each subsequent re-
enactment, adding further multimodal sensorimotor information to previous perceptions of
the object (Jacobson, 2013). As Zbikowski (2010) explains:
. . . a simulator for the category of conjoined musical events associated with the term “perfect authentic
cadence” could be established simply through multiple encounters with exemplars of the category . . .
such a simulator would not only include auditory information, but also extend to sensorimotor
information about the feeling of performing these events . . . introspective states associated with such
cadences, and physical responses to hearing them (Zbikowski, 2010, pp. 35–36).
In music-colour synaesthesia, the concurrent might be mediated by new information that
influences the conceptual content of the stimulus. This information might consist of timbre,
emotion, tonality or musical style (Mroczko-Wąsowicz & Danko, 2014). There are many differ-
ent types of synaesthesia, however, and in accordance with Simner (2012) who argues against
a one-for-all explanation, and Auvray and Deroy (2015) who suggest that each type be con-
sidered separately, my aim here is not to propose a single underlying mechanism. Some syn-
aesthesias may be of neurological origin, others genetic. Nevertheless, it is likely that higher,
concept-driven forms of music-colour synaesthesia are based on experience, albeit to varying
extents.
Music Cognition
Cognitivist Approaches
Cognitivist accounts of musical experience propose representations and computations based
on an input-output model (Lerdahl & Jackendoff, 1983; Nussbaum 2007): the sensory system
receives a stream of external information from which internal representations of the real world
are created (i.e., music processing). They do not consider the role of the body; Fodor (1983)
argued for the modularity of mind, while more recent neurological explanations focus on the
role of areas of the brain thought to be specialised for music (e.g., Peretz & Coltheart, 2003).
These explanations are criticised (e.g., Di Paola etal., 2017; Fuchs, 2017; Gallagher, 2017;
Varela etal., 1991) yet their core tenets are still endorsed. For example, Huron (2006) explains
musical experience in terms of an internal appraisal mechanism based on “some sort of
weighted sum” (p. 110) of different representations of listeners’ expectations, while Sloboda
Curwen 5
and Juslin (2010) explored the relationship between real emotions and their representation in
the form of emotional responses elicited from music. Yet musical experience is intersubjective
and influenced by what individual listeners feel and what they do (Leman, 2008; Reybrouck,
2006). People fulfil their social needs and experience well-being through musical engagement
not by processing internal representations but by exploring the external, musical, environment
(Krueger, 2009, 2011; Reybrouck 2010; Schiavio etal., 2017).
Ecological Approaches
Clarke (2005) applied ecological psychology, based on Gibson’s (1966, 1979) theory of
affordances, to music perception. Affordances, according to Gibson, are what the environment
“offers the animal, what it provides or furnishes, either for good or ill . . . I mean by it some-
thing that refers to both the environment and the animal . . . it implies the complementarity
of the animal and the environment” (1979, p. 127). Consequently, perception is seen not as
an internal process but as the result of the ongoing relationship between the animal’s, or
agent’s, whole perceptual system, rather than isolated receptors such as the ear or the eye,
and its environment.
But what are musical affordances? Most scholars agree that music affords movement or
some form of entrainment (e.g., Clarke, 2005; Leman, 2008; Krueger, 2014; Reybrouck, 2005,
2012). DeNora describes musical affordances as “moods, messages, energy levels, and situa-
tion” (2000, p. 44). A musical event may be an interactive exploration of different “sonic
affordances”, and a provider of emotional and social affordances without which our ability to
relate to others would be significantly diminished (Krueger, 2011). Krueger (2014) subse-
quently put forward a model of the musically extended mind, explaining that music affords not
just movement but also entrainment, observed as moving in time to the beat and sharing the
experience with others. As an “emotion-extending resource” (2014, p. 9) musical affordances
offer access to extended experiences and expressivity beyond those available to us in non-musi-
cal situations.
In their theory of musical affordance, Menin and Schiavio (2012) propose an embodied,
motor-based account emphasising the intentional nature of the relationship between musical
subjects and objects. When a skilled guitarist demonstrates a motor form of intentionality by
using their fingers on the strings in such a way as to reproduce a musical sequence, “this sen-
sory-motor process not only represents the basis of musical understanding, but it can also shed
light on the notion of musical affordance, relying on a sub-cognitive, pre-linguistic, intrinsi-
cally motor form of intentionality” (p. 210). Applying Ramstead et al.’s (2016) cultural
affordances framework to music performance, Einarsson and Ziemke (2017) argue that it is
“the situation as a whole that has affordances” (p. 10), offering a still broader perspective.
Embodied Approaches
The rejection of the distinction between action and perception is at the heart of Gibson’s eco-
logical theory, and key to theories of embodiment (Chemero, 2009; Leitan & Chaffey, 2014;
Wilson & Golonka, 2013). Their proponents acknowledge the constitutive (i.e., essential) role
of the body in driving cognitive processes and dismiss the key role of mental representations in
the cognitive economy of the living system (Thompson, 2007; Varela et al., 1991). Should
information be there for the taking in the environment, why would nature build an internal
mechanism to do the same job (Rowlands, 2003)? Nevertheless, those who propose embodied
approaches to music cognition have struggled to discard all aspects of representation. For
6 Musicae Scientiae 00(0)
example, representational structures are retained in Leman’s (2008) theory of embodied music
cognition, which otherwise describes the relationship between agent and environment, to cap-
ture the richness of musical experience (see Schiavio & Menin, 2013). Recent research frames
more “radically embodied” (van der Schyff etal., 2018, p.13) and enactive approaches to musi-
cal engagement in the context of musical emotion, communication, and meaning in commu-
nity music making, and musical creativity (Schiavio etal., 2017, 2019; van der Schyff etal.,
2018). In contrast to approaches presenting music cognition as a series of internal (i.e., com-
putational, neural) processes and representations, these approaches propose the direct, circu-
lar interaction between the agent’s body and its social, cultural, and physical environment
(Reybrouck, 2014; van der Schyff etal., 2018).
Sensorimotor Theory
Matyja (2010) highlights the importance of O’Regan and Noë’s (2001) sensorimotor contingency
theory (SCT) in an enactive approach to music cognition. SCT is an account of perceptual con-
sciousness that attempts to explain qualia without reference to representation. It presents a new
approach to perception emphasising the influence of motor actions on changes in sensory stim-
ulation (Bishop & Martin, 2014). Focusing on visual experience, “the central idea of our new
approach is that vision is a mode of exploration of the world that is mediated by knowledge of what we
call sensorimotor contingencies [emphasis in original]” (O’Regan and Noë, 2001, p. 940).
SCT explains how an agent explores the environment, and how their attention is attracted
by (unpredictable) attributes of the environment described as bodiliness, grabbiness and insubor-
dinateness. The extent to which an agent makes use of sensorimotor contingencies determines
the quality of their experience:
Bodiliness refers to the objectively quantifiable way in which bodily changes modify sensory input; for
example, turning your head alters visual input, but has no effect on thoughts. Insubordinateness is the
fact that bodily changes, though they have a systematic effect, do not completely determine sensory
changes (sensory input can change without bodily changes occurring). Grabbiness concerns the fact
that, due to basic properties of sensory systems, sudden transitory changes in sensory input strongly
grab our attention and cause perceptual processing to be focused on the sudden event (Degenaar &
O’Regan, 2015, p. 2).
Sensorimotor Theory and Music
How can we relate this to music? If an act of listening to music is an interaction with the sonic
environment (Krueger, 2009), relevant sensorimotor contingencies may be obtained in the
following ways: bodiliness: turning towards the sound we hear; grabbiness: being alerted at a
key or instrumentation change; insubordinateness (relating to aspects of the sonic world
beyond our control): music stopping unexpectedly, equipment failure, instrument failure.
If SCT is about actively exploring the environment, doing and interacting, how can it be
applied to music listening when we appear not to be doing anything? Yet doing denotes not only
bodily movement, but also thinking, imagining, and standing still (Beaton, 2013). Listening to
music offers affordances in the form of our memory of previous experiences of musical engage-
ment (Myin, 2016).
Stewart etal. (2003) report empirical evidence for a sensorimotor role in reading and play-
ing music in a functional imaging study with non-musicians. Twelve learners undertook 15
weeks of musical training and carried out an explicit music reading task requiring them to
press keys on an electronic keyboard. Their results were compared with those of a control
Curwen 7
group. Activation in the superior parietal lobe (SPL) was observed in the learners but not the
control group. The researchers conclude that reading music involves a sensorimotor transla-
tion of the notation to appropriate keypresses.
Some have argued that formal musical training is needed to achieve deep musical under-
standing (e.g., Kivy, 2002), whilst others have shown that an implicit understanding of the
structure of Western tonal music can be acquired through exposure alone (Krumhansl, 2010).
Importantly, formal musical training is not needed to obtain relevant sensorimotor knowledge.
For example, Peñalba-Acitores illustrates how bodiliness and grabbiness might emerge during
typical musical engagement (Peñalba, 2011, p. 222):
. . . our perception roams around different aspects of the material, exploring melodies, instruments,
chords, structure, and style; and we are aware of that exploration through bodiliness . . . we will know
that we are experiencing a crescendo because of increasing tension in the muscles; and we will
experience rhythm because of the way that it allows us to synchronize our movements (virtual or
actual) with the beat; This constitutes bodiliness.
Grabbiness, by contrast, captures the idea that the environment guides the subject in perception . . . In
an orchestral piece, a listener might be more likely to be “grabbed” by timbre . . . Or we may be “grabbed”
by the unexpected change from minor to major in a tierce de Picardie.1
Peñalba-Acitores also suggests that listeners unfamiliar with Indian music find it difficult to
listen to at first because they attempt to apply the sensorimotor skills they have learned from
listening to Western tonal music.
Music-Colour Synaesthesia
Neurological Theories
There are two primary neurological explanations for the cause of synaesthesia, the disinhibited
feedback theory (Grossenbacher & Lovelace, 2001) and the hyperconnectivity theory (Ramachandran
& Hubbard, 2001). The disinhibited feedback theory suggests that a breakdown of the barriers
that normally keep modules and their processing completely separate permits a free flow of
information from primary sensory areas to associated areas such as the parietal lobe or limbic
system. In this way, if feedback signals are not inhibited, later stages of processing can influence
earlier stages of processing (Neufeld etal., 2012). According to the hyperconnectivity theory,
both intermodal and intramodal synaesthesias are caused by a bottom-up process arising from
unusual direct connections between different modules of the brain such as visual and auditory
areas. In infancy, there are many more connections between brain areas than in adulthood.
These extra connections are normally pruned as the brain matures, yet in synaesthesia it is
thought that this process is not completed fully, leaving some unusual connections behind (see
Ramachandran & Hubbard, 2001, pp. 9–10). Both theories emphasise the role of genetic factors
for the cause of synaesthesia and provide little role learning in its development. Yet synaesthesia
may not just arise from inadequate neural pruning and weakened inhibitory re-entrant feed-
back. The reasons for such disinhibition or connectivity may be various.
Role of Concept
As previously mentioned, some synaesthesias can arise from a conceptual stimulus (Dixon
etal., 2000; Mroczko-Wąsowicz & Werning, 2012; Mroczko-Wąsowicz & Nikolić, 2014; Ward,
8 Musicae Scientiae 00(0)
Tsakanikos, & Bray, 2006) implying that synaesthetes may not be predisposed to synaesthesia
but, rather, have learned to assign meanings to certain stimuli for the purpose of strengthening
their knowledge and understanding of abstract concepts (van Leeuwen etal., 2015). Individual
synaesthetes frequently disagree as to the specific colours and imagery associated with musical
inducers, suggesting that the learned meanings assigned to stimuli are neither random nor
universally applied.
Role of Body, Action and Environment
The similarities that exist between synaesthetic pairings and the cross-modal associations
commonly made by the general population between colour, music, emotion, pitch-height and
pitch size indicate that synaesthetes and non-synaesthetes employ comparable mental pro-
cesses (Gallace & Spence, 2006; Isbilen & Krumhansl, 2016; Marks, 1987, 2004; Mondloch
& Maurer, 2004; Palmer etal., 2016; Palmer etal., 2013; Tsiounta etal., 2013; Walker etal.,
2010; Ward, Huckstep, & Tsakanikos, 2006). Both groups are exposed to similar learned
cultural and environmental associations. For example, large objects make bigger and louder
sounds on impact than smaller ones, and higher pitches are associated with smaller animals
(Spence, 2011). Parise and Spence (2009) hypothesise that, according to Bayesian theory,
pairings such as those between pitch and size are based on the individual’s prior knowledge
that these cross-modal associations “go together” (p. 2) in the natural environment. Music-
colour synaesthesia may simply be a typical musical experience with “extra qualia,” as
described by Wager (1999, p. 264), for some people. Nevertheless, as we have seen, the phe-
nomenological experience of seeing the colour green when hearing the pitch class A presents
a challenge to representationalism (Alter, 2006; Auvray & Deroy, 2015; Brogaard, 2016;
Curwen, 2018; Rosenberg, 2004; Wager, 1999). Embodied and enactive music cognition
research rejects explanations of musical experience as a series of internal cognitive processes
(Reybrouck, 2005, 2012) and argues rather that “musical experience . . . is not something
that is done to us” [but instead is] “something we do” (Krueger, 2011, p. 2). A more holistic
and embodied approach to understanding musical experience (Schiavio & van der Schyff,
2016) can be applied to the development of a sensorimotor explanation for music-colour
synaesthesia.
Synaesthesia and Sensorimotor Contingency Theory
Deroy and Spence (2013) suggest that the cross-modal correspondences underlying synaesthe-
sia may be grounded in sensorimotor associations:
. . .most people match angular shapes with the word “takete” while matching rounded shapes with
the word “maluma” . . . it is the sharp vocal transitions made by the mouth when uttering the plosive
sounds in “takete” that people map onto the sharp/angular shape . . . this cross-modal correspondence
would then become “embodied” and grounded in sensorimotor associations (p. 1249).
However, it is important to acknowledge the challenges that synaesthesia poses to the basic
assumptions of sensorimotor theory, which Mroczko-Wąsowicz (2015) highlights in the fol-
lowing three objections:
1. Synaesthetic concurrents are generated internally, and do not arise from light reflecting
from a surface, changing the angle of the head, or eye saccades.
Curwen 9
2. Synaesthetic colour does not adapt away as in colour inversion in normal vision. It is
generally consistent and unchanging.
3. Synaesthetes can tell the difference between synaesthetic colours and veridical colours,
suggesting that synaesthetic colours lack perceptual presence (i.e., of being real and
existing in the world).
However, higher, concept-driven forms of music-colour synaesthesia can be reconciled to sen-
sorimotor theory and the above objections resolved, as discussed below.
Synaesthetic Colours are Generated Internally
Synaesthesia has little to do with vision per se: “synesthetic visual responses to music aren’t
affected by shutting or moving the eyes” (Ward, 2013, p. 51) and concurrents do not arise from
normal vision. The colours experienced by associators are often described as being in the mind’s
eye, or of knowing a colour. Yet this does not mean that a synaesthetic experience is not the
result of an individual’s interaction with their direct environment. Affordances derived from
interactive patterns in previous experiences of musical engagement can be understood as
“something we do now, in the light of what we have done before” (Myin, 2016, p. 100).
Similarly, Barsalou’s PSS theory proposes that a pattern of activation established during early
basic sensorimotor processing can be re-enacted subsequently (1999, 2003). For example, in
other synaesthesia research, Mroczko-Wąsowicz and Werning’s (2012) presented two semi-
professional swimmers who associated synaesthetic colours with four swimming strokes
(breaststroke, crawl, butterfly and back stroke). In a Stroop-like task (Stroop, 1935) both named
colours faster when shown photographs of swimmers in stroke-congruent colours. Simply
thinking about or imagining the swimming stroke was enough to re-enact the original activa-
tion pattern and elicit a colour response; the strokes did not have to be executed physically.
Beaton (2013) argues that colour does not exist independently in the external world, nor
just in our minds, but as the result of our interaction with the world (see also Varela et al.,
1991) emphasising that learned associations are an important part of individuals’ personal
experience with colour, and what it means to them. For example, Gilbert etal. (2016) found
that participants deliberately matched similar colours to similarly valenced emotion terms.
Participants’ choices differed significantly as a function of emotion and were moderated by sex
and age. When participants in another study were asked to judge the effects of colour on emo-
tion (Wilms & Oberfield, 2018), the combination of hue, saturation, and brightness was impor-
tant, and Palmer and Schloss (2016) found that preferences for a particular colour were
influenced by interaction with an object of the same colour. Barsalou (2003) also emphasises
the role of personal experience when re-enactments of original sensorimotor patterns are tai-
lored to the context of the individual’s current situation. Personal experience may explain disa-
greements between synaesthetes as to the colours associated with the same inducer.
Visual perceptual experiences can be obtained from stimuli other than those produced by
light reflecting from a surface, as demonstrated by the visually impaired with tactile-vision sub-
stitution systems (TVSS), as described by Bach-y-Rita and Kercel (2003), or other forms of sen-
sory substitution such as The vOICe (e.g., Pasqualotto & Esenkaya, 2016). For example, the
profoundly deaf Scottish virtuoso percussionist, Dame Evelyn Glennie, writes of how “my
whole body is similar to an ear, every surface has learnt to become a conduit, bringing meaning
and sense to my brain” (2016, para.11).
It can therefore be argued that what underpins music-colour synaesthesia is the develop-
ment of a conceptual system, in the form of sensorimotor features associated with a musical
10 Musicae Scientiae 00(0)
inducer the first time it is heard, and enriched through repeated exposure. For example, the
individual may experience, either as an instrumentalist or a listener, an intense emotional
response to the music, associated with a certain group of colours that in turn become associ-
ated with it. Different individuals presented with the same inducer experience it in different
contexts, however, which would explain why different synaesthetes see different colours. A
synaesthetic colour experience might be the result of subsequent re-enactments of the concep-
tual system while remembering, producing or listening to the music. For example, Ward,
Tsakanikos and Bray (2006) showed that synaesthetic colour was determined by musical con-
text rather than mode of presentation or form of stimulus. In the notation of Western music, a
dot presented on the middle line of a five-line stave has different meanings depending on the
clef (e.g., B in treble, D in bass). Synaesthesia is elicited at the conceptual level, so the same
colour will be assigned to a D whether it is shown on the middle line of a bass stave, below the
bottom line of a treble stave or as a letter, whether upper- or lower-case.
The variation in colour preferences from synaesthete to synaesthete for the same stimuli
reflects the differences in the meaning of the concept surrounding the stimuli for each indi-
vidual. According to Gardenfors (2004), concepts “are intrinsically dynamic entities, arising
and adapting continuously as the agent engages with its environment . . . concepts are never
free-floating entities but are always concepts for a particular agent, who comes with her own
perspectival biases” (p. 170). Barrett (2011) makes an interesting link between Gibson’s
affordances and Jacob von Uexküll’s Umwelt (1992). The notion of Umwelt is described by
Barrett as “the world as it is experienced by a particular organism” (p. 80) implying, as in
Gibson’s theory, that the same environment will not offer the same affordances to each animal.
An agent is only sensitive to those stimuli relevant to it from within its own environmental
niche. For example, humans do not need to see ultraviolet light or hear very high-pitched
sounds, neither do we need a heightened sense of smell to detect and avoid other predators in
the same environment. None of these things forms part of our Umwelt.
Reybrouck (2001, 2005) considers music listening relevant to Umwelt research, arguing that
“dealing with music can be considered as a process of knowledge acquisition” (2001, p. 623)
dependent on the individual listener’s previous interactions with their sonic environment and
the meanings that listener might attribute to the sounds. Reybrouck claims that “what is really
important is not the acoustical description of the sound, but the sounds as they are experienced
by the listener” (2001, p. 618). Non-synaesthetes are happy to accept reality as it is presented to
them: without unobtainable synaesthetic experiences (Eagleman, 2012). Similarly synaes-
thetes, whose phenomenal experience of music includes colours, accept their wider Umwelt.
Synaesthetic Colours Do Not Adapt Away
Kohler’s (1964) study describes the experience of wearers of coloured goggles who report an
adaption over time until the goggles no longer interfere with their normal vision. Yet, as Ward
(2012) points out, it is often overlooked that the adaptation does not mean that the colours
have returned to normal. The colours are still inverted, but the wearer has had to adjust to them
to be able to navigate their environment with relative ease. In the case of synaesthesia, seeing a
synaesthetic colour does not impair the synaesthete’s ability to see veridical colour. An asso-
ciator’s colours held in the mind’s eye do not arise from light reflecting off a surface (Ward,
2012) so there is no need for them to disappear to accommodate veridical colours. Synaesthetes
can see both veridical, and synaesthetic colours, just as well. For example, in Ward, Tsakanikos
and Bray’s (2006) study synaesthetes were shown musical notes in congruent and incongru-
ent colours and asked to name their synaesthetic colour, ignoring the veridical colour. Although
Curwen 11
a Stroop effect was observed, naming synaesthetic colours did not interfere with the synaes-
thetes’ normal vision. At no time did they see the written notation as anything other than its
veridical colour, black. Notably, Mroczko-Wąsowicz (2015) suggests that there is no real need
for synaesthetic colours to adapt away, as they do not carry the same colour information about
the objects within the synaesthete’s environment as veridical colours (see p. 10). Synaesthetic
colours associated with a musical event may instead provide information about a concept, emo-
tion, meaning, property or a previous action.
Synaesthetic Colours Lack Perceptual Presence
If a synaesthete is aware that the colours they see are not veridical, how can their experience be
viewed as an interaction with the real world, and how can the potential lack of perceptual pres-
ence (of being or existing in the world) be responded to? According to Noë (2001), perceptual
presence can be explained by the practical mastery of sensorimotor contingencies. For exam-
ple, we know what the reverse side of a tomato looks like even though we cannot see it. Our
sensory responses, elicited by the tomato, are such that we know how the tomato will behave in
a variety of situations.
But how can we account for phenomena such as synaesthesia, in which “raw sensory expe-
rience (‘qualia’) remains but perceptual presence is lacking” (Seth, 2014, p. 98)? Seth’s
Predictive Perception account of Sensorimotor Contingencies (PPSMC) accounts for normal
perception and synaesthesia through the interpretation of counterfactuals and predictive process-
ing. Generative models predict an outcome based on how sensory inputs would change in vari-
ous action situations, even if those actions did not actually happen. The richness of these
counterfactually encoded sensorimotor contingencies determines the degree of perceptual
presence. Counterfactuals might be understood as statements of what would occur if some-
thing other than the present state of affairs happened (e.g., the glass would break if I were to
drop it on the floor). A predictive model based on counterfactuals takes into account not just the
likely cause of a sensory input, but the likely cause of a sensory input based on a repertoire of
possible actions (Seth, 2014). Used in everyday science (Beaton, 2013), counterfactuals inform
us how an interaction might occur between an agent and its environment in various scenarios.
The interaction may, or may not, be carried out, but it could possibly happen in reality. Seth’s
theory claims that the lack of perceptual presence in synaesthesia is due to poor counterfactu-
als owing to a smaller, or non-existent, repertoire of likely real-world sensory inputs.
This interesting account has received a number of responses (Froese, 2014; Hohwy, 2014;
Madary, 2014; Metzinger, 2014; O’Regan & Degenaar, 2014; Rouw & Ridderinkhof, 2014; van
Leeuwen, 2014). Madary (2014) compares counterfactual richness in visual and other sen-
sory modalities where, in the latter cases, only some counterfactual information may be
required for perceptual presence. For example, there are far more counterfactual possibilities
available to us in vision than from sound. We can visually observe an object from many differ-
ent angles by moving our eyes alone, but fewer options are available to us from an auditory
perspective. This might suggest that auditory input need be far less counterfactually rich than
visual input to achieve perceptual presence. Madary proposes a modification to Seth’s proposal.
Instead of the degree of presence depending upon the degree of richness of counterfactual
information, “some counterfactual information” regarding sensorimotor contingencies is
required for perceptual presence (p. 132). However, Madary questions whether even this modi-
fication might explain the apparent lack of presence in synaesthetic concurrents, asking
whether there are any sensorimotor contingencies in synaesthetic concurrents at all? Madary
suspects not, but one might argue otherwise.
12 Musicae Scientiae 00(0)
Froese’s (2014) main challenge to Seth’s explanation is that counterfactual predictive pro-
cessing only appears to address perceptual presence and not the appearance of reality, and that
it is “the absence of the latter, and not of the former, that is an essential property of synesthetic
experience” (p. 126). By not distinguishing sufficiently between the two, Froese argues that
Seth does not account for types of synaesthesia that in fact might present some kind of percep-
tual presence. While it may be more difficult to attribute sensorimotor contingencies to some
forms of synaesthesia than others, music-colour synaesthesia is often accompanied by shapes,
textures and moving landscapes (Eagleman & Goodale, 2009) similar to the tunnels reported in
spatial sequence synaesthesia (Gould etal., 2014). Although “this contextual space appears as
distinct from the real world” (Froese, 2014, p. 127) counterfactuals by themselves cannot
explain the lack of reality of concurrents, as the experience of counterfactuals may remain
surprisingly rich. An enactive account of perception does not attempt to explain veridical expe-
rience in terms of internal representation, but by how that experience “is shaped by the real
world” (p. 127). Indeed, such phenomenal experience, as reported in music-colour synaesthe-
sia, might offer a perceptual presence in a similar form to those Beaton (2013) attributes to
visual memory. Counterfactuals may operate even in imaginary contexts, and it is only the lack
of reality that distinguishes synaesthetic colour from veridical. Beaton (2013) claims that both
visual memory and visual imagination are themselves types of interaction with the world and
gives examples of how we are “poised to act” (p. 306) even when encountering hallucinations
of a unicorn, or an illusion of a tomato. Although the unicorn does not and cannot exist in the
world, we can gain an understanding, by using counterfactuals, of how we would act if these
objects were actually present (Shoemaker, 1994). For example, O’Regan and Degenaar com-
pare a synaesthetic experience to the ability “to vividly imagine things that are absent” suggest-
ing that the relevant cortical activity remains “dangling” (2014, p. 131): in the sense that the
cortical activity is not related to current sensorimotor events happening in the environment
(Hurley & Noë, 2003). Indeed, Schubotz (2007) provides evidence supporting an explanation
as to how a simulation of events, including auditory events, may be realised in our sensory-
motor system, even those that we are unable to reproduce ourselves.
According to O’Regan & Degenaar (2014) “sensorimotor theory itself already has the
resources to explain synaesthesia” (2014, p. 131). Bodiliness, grabbiness and insubordinate-
ness are able to go beyond the idea of explaining perceptual presence in terms of counterfactual
richness, and are equipped to explain all sensory experience. The argument here is that senso-
rimotor contingencies can be attributed to cases of music-colour synaesthesia. We can imagine
our interaction with tunnels and shapes in a moving spatial landscape or the expected feel of
certain textures. Resonating with Barsalou’s PSS theory, a fragment of the original sensorimo-
tor state might be placed in memory (Jacobson, 2013) explaining why a synaesthetic concur-
rent may appear disembodied from the original sensorimotor qualities of its inducer. It may
appear that a synaesthetic concurrent “seems to have little to do with the SMCs underwriting
the perception of the inducer” (Seth, 2014, p. 105), but once the sensorimotor contingencies
of experiencing red have been mastered, then red can be re-enacted in an atypical way.
Music-Colour Synaesthesia as a Variant of General Human Cognition
Although never directly referring to an enactive or sensorimotor approach, Sollberger
(2013) stresses that the extent to which an individual is able to interact with their environ-
ment has an important functional role when characterising a perceptual experience as
veridical. Furthermore, if the perceiver is able to distinguish and interact with external
objects in the world, then how the experience is embodied, whether as a taste or a coloured
Curwen 13
sound, is irrelevant (Sollberger, 2009, pp. 151–152). Acknowledging that different types of
synaesthesia might require different explanations for their cause, Sollberger argues that not
all forms of synaesthesia should be viewed as a non-veridical experience, and that some
synaesthesias should be viewed as a “normal variant of human perception” (2013, p. 171).
Sollberger refers to music-colour synaesthesia as a form that presents to the perceiver some-
thing about their real-world environment. Specifically, synaesthetes with this type of syn-
aesthesia are able to meet the following two conditions:
They literally attribute the sensory properties of the synesthetic experiences to the distal stimulus itself.
They do not take their synesthetic experiences to be nonveridical, e.g., illusory or hallucinatory (2013,
p. 173).
Sollberger (2013, p. 174) cites experiences from music-colour synaesthetes collected by
Cytowic (2002):
A person who sings with little phrasing or variation in volume has a straight line voice. A baritone has
a round shape that I feel. This is so obvious, it’s all very logical. I thought everyone felt this way. When
people tell me they don’t, it’s as if they were saying they don’t know how to walk or run or breathe
(Cytowic, 2002, p. 28).
The shapes are not distinct from hearing them—they are part of what hearing is. The vibraphone, the
musical instrument, makes a round shape. Each is like a little gold ball falling. That’s what the sound
is; it couldn’t possibly be anything else (Cytowic, 2002, p. 69).
The colours and shapes experienced in music-colour synaesthesia are a fundamental part of
the phenomenal character of musical experience, or the “what it is like” (Nagel, 1974, p. 437)
to hear music, for synaesthetes (Chalmers, 1996; Shoemaker, 1994). Synaesthetes are often
surprised to learn that not everyone experiences music as they do and cannot imagine experi-
encing music in any other way. Perhaps the question we should be asking is not, “what is it like
to have synaesthesia” but, “what is it like not to have synaesthesia?”
Historically, synaesthesia has been examined as a sensory/perceptual condition distinct
from typical cognition. Yet, many different types and sub-categories of synaesthesia exist, and
purely neurological explanations remain inconclusive. The similar mental processes employed
by synaesthetes and non-synaesthetes (Simner, 2012) suggest that certain synaesthesias can
be described in terms of typical cognition. Recent research in general music cognition has
moved away from a cognitivist approach, and explains musical experience via embodied and
enactive theories (Schiavio etal., 2017; Schiavio etal., 2019). It is possible that certain forms
of synaesthesia may arise from purely neurological or genetic factors. However, the direction of
research in general music cognition and in synaesthesia point to a sensorimotor approach as a
promising next step in explaining the phenomena of synaesthesia associated with music.
Conclusion
I have argued that music-colour synaesthesia should be examined not as a separate and distinct
condition, but as a continuation of typical perception and cognition. Research in general music
cognition has embraced embodied and enactive accounts that include an active role for the
body and its situated power of action. Central to these accounts is how engagement with music
might be regarded as an act of doing, in accordance with Gibson’s theory of affordances and
14 Musicae Scientiae 00(0)
sensorimotor theory, and how certain attributes of a musical environment attract a subject’s
attention in the form of their bodiliness, grabbiness and insubordinateness (Peñalba, 2011;
Krueger, 2009). Yet actively exploring and interacting with a musical environment should not
be restricted to physical acts of engagement we more commonly associate with doing, but can
extend to imagining and thinking (Beaton, 2013; Myin, 2016). Deep musical understanding
can be acquired without formal musical training through attentive everyday listening
(Krumhansl, 2010). I have described how a synaesthete can obtain a mastery of sensorimotor
contingencies and become poised to act (Beaton, 2013), and how the quality of the synaesthetic
experience is governed by a level of “dangling cortical activity” (Hurley & Noë, 2003, p. 158).
The similarities in the progression of research in synaesthesia and general music cognition
show how music-colour synaesthesia might be reconciled with a sensorimotor account and
viewed as a “normal variant of human perception” (Sollberger, 2013, p. 171). The phenome-
non of shapes, colours and textures experienced on hearing music represents something about
the real-world environment for the synaesthete, and is integral to their perception, experience,
knowledge, and musical understanding.
These claims present an opportunity for future empirical research. Starting from the hypoth-
esis that synaesthesia associated with music is mediated by concept and context but grounded
in sensorimotor action, the commonalities between the mechanisms underlying music-colour
synaesthesia and general music cognition, might be tested. A group of non-synaesthete musi-
cians could undertake sufficient training until they were able to produce a series of triads on a
keyboard to which they could reliably assign a specific colour. A Stroop-like task would verify
that congruent colour-triad trials were produced with faster times and with fewer errors than
incongruent colour-triad trials. In a second study, the newly trained group might be compared
to a group with pre-existing music-colour synaesthesia. Ward, Tsakanikos, and Bray (2006)
suggest that the involvement of the superior parietal lobe (SPL) in sensorimotor transforma-
tions is likely to be important in synaesthesia. The application of transcranial magnetic stimu-
lation (TMS) disrupts neural processing in the SPL. Both groups would undertake the Stroop
task whilst receiving TMS over the right intraparietal cortex. It is expected that in the non-
congruent trials, interference would no longer be observed in either group as the TMS would
un-bind the colour-triad associations.
I hope this article will encourage a shift in thinking about music-colour synaesthesia as well
as promote investigations of the role of our sensorimotor system and actual as well as imagined
interactions with the environment in various forms of synaesthesia.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Dr. Renee Timmers and Dr. Andrea Schiavio for their expert advice and guidance,
and the members of the Music Mind Machine reading group at the University of Sheffield for their valuable
feedback. I would also like to extend my thanks to the editor and the two anonymous reviewers for their
detailed comments on an earlier draft of this paper.
Funding
The author(s) received no financial support for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this
article.
ORCID iD
Caroline Curwen https://orcid.org/0000-0003-2557-7909
Curwen 15
Note
1. A tierce de Picardie (meaning a Picardy third) is the term given to the use of a major chord in the final
tonic chord of a piece of music in a minor key.
References
Alter, T. (2006). Does synesthesia undermine representationalism? Psyche, 12(1983), 1–11.
Auvray, M., & Deroy, O. (2015). How do synaesthetes experience the world? In M. Matthen (Ed.), The
Oxford handbook of philosophy of perception (pp. 640–658). Oxford University Press. https://doi.
org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199600472.013.027
Bach-y-rita, P., & Kercel, S. W. (2003). Sensory substitution and the human-machine interface. Trends in
Cognitive Science, 7(12), 541–546. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2003.10.013
Barrett, L. (2011). Beyond the brain: How body and environment shape animal and human minds. Princeton
University Press.
Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(4), 577–609.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X99002149
Barsalou, L. W. (2003). Situated simulation in the human conceptual system. Language and Cognitive
Processes, 18(5–6), 513–562. https://doi.org/10.1080/01690960344000026
Beaton, M. (2013). Phenomenology and embodied action. Constructivist Foundations, 8(3), 298–313.
Bishop, J. M., & Martin, A. O. (2014). Contemporary sensorimotor theory: A brief introduction. In
J. M. Bishop & A. M. Martin (Eds.), Contemporary sensorimotor theory. Studies in applied philosophy,
epistemology and rational ethics (Vol. 15, Issue May, pp. 1–22). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-
3-319-05107-9
Brogaard, B. (2016). Synesthesia as a challenge for representationalism. In W. Buckwalter & J. Sytsma
(Eds.), Blackwell companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 306–317). Wiley - Blackwell.
Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chemero, A. (2003). An outline of a theory of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 15(2), 181–195. https://
doi.org/10.1207/S15326969ECO1502
Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press.
Chemero, A. (2018). Synergy and synaesthesia. In D. Martin (Ed.), Mirror touch synaesthesia: Thresholds of
empathy with art (pp. 177–190). Oxford University Press.
Clarke, E. F. (2005). Ways of listening: An ecological approach to the perception of musical meaning. Oxford
University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195151947.001.0001
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.
Colombetti, G., & Roberts, T. (2015). Extending the extended mind: The case for extended affectivity.
Philosophical Studies, 172(5), 1243–1263. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0347-3
Curwen, C. (2018). Music-colour synaesthesia: Concept, context and qualia. Consciousness and Cognition,
61, 94–106. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2018.04.005
Cytowic, R. E. (2002). Synesthesia: A union of the senses (2nd ed.). Springer Verlag.
Degenaar, J., & O’Regan, J. (2015). Sensorimotor theory of consciousness. Scholarpedia, 10(5), 1–15.
https://doi.org/10.4249/scholarpedia.4952
DeNora, T. (2000). Music in everyday life. Cambridge University Press.
Deroy, O., & Spence, C. (2013). Are we all born synaesthetic? Examining the neonatal synaesthesia
hypothesis. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 37(7), 1240–1253. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.
neubiorev.2013.04.001
Di Paolo, E. A., Buhrmann, T., & Barandiaran, X. E. (2017). Sensorimotor life: An enactive proposal.
In Sensorimotor life: An enactive proposal. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198786849.00
1.0001
Dixon, M. J., & Smilek, D. (2005). The importance of individual differences in grapheme-color synesthesia.
Neuron, 45(6), 821–823. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2005.03.007
Dixon, M. J., Smilek, D., Cudahy, C., & Merikle, P. M. (2000). Five plus two equals yellow. Nature,
406(6794), 365. https://doi.org/10.1038/35019148
16 Musicae Scientiae 00(0)
Dixon, M. J., Smilek, D., & Merikle, P. M. (2004). Not all synaesthetes are created equal: Projector versus
associator synaesthetes. Cognitive, Affective & Behavioral Neuroscience, 4(3), 335–343. https://doi.
org/10.3758/CABN.4.3.335
Eagleman, D. M. (2012). The Umwelt. In J. Brockman (Ed.), This will make you smarter: New scientific con-
cepts to improve your thinking (pp. 143–145). Harper Perennial.
Eagleman, D. M., & Goodale, M. A. (2009). Why color synesthesia involves more than color. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences, 13(7), 288–292. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2009.03.009
Einarsson, A., & Ziemke, T. (2017). Exploring the multi-layered affordances of composing and performing
interactive music with responsive technologies. Frontiers in Psychology, 8(SEP), 1–12. https://doi.
org/10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01701
Eitan, Z., & Timmers, R. (2010). Beethoven’s last piano sonata and those who follow crocodiles: Cross-
domain mappings of auditory pitch in a musical context. Cognition, 114(3), 405–422. https://doi.
org/10.1016/j.cognition.2009.10.013
Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. Cambridge, Massachusetts : MIT
Press, 1983.
Froese, T. (2014). Steps toward an enactive account of synesthesia. Cognitive Neuroscience, 5(2), 126–
127. https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2014.905521
Fuchs, T. (2017). Collective body memories. In C. Durt, T. Fuchs, & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment, enaction,
and culture: Investigating the constitution of the shared world (pp. 333–352). MIT Press.
Gallace, A., & Spence, C. (2006). Multisensory synesthetic interactions in the speeded classification of
visual size. Perception & Psychophysics, 68(7), 1191–1203. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03193720
Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press. https://doi.
org/10.1093/oso/9780198794325.001.0001
Gardenfors, P. (2004). Conceptual spaces: The geometry of thought. Bradford Books.
Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as perceptual systems. Houghton Mifflin.
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin.
Gilbert, A. N., Fridlund, A. J., & Lucchina, L. A. (2016). The color of emotion: A metric for implicit
color associations. Food Quality and Preference, 52, 203–210. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.food-
qual.2016.04.007
Glennie, E. (2016). Listening to the Tempest: A tale to cure deafness. Evelyn Glennie: Teach the world to lis-
ten. https://www.evelyn.co.uk/essays/
Gould, C., Froese, T., Barrett, A. B., Ward, J., & Seth, A. K. (2014). An extended case study on the phe-
nomenology of sequence-space synesthesia. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 1–16. https://doi.
org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00433
Grossenbacher, G., & Lovelace, C. (2001). Mechanisms of synesthesia: Cognitive and physiological con-
straints. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5(1), 36–41.
Hohwy, J. (2014). Elusive phenomenology, counterfactual awareness, and presence without mastery.
Cognitive Neuroscience, 5(2), 127–128. https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2014.906399
Hurley, S., & Noë, A. (2003). Neural plasticity and consciousness 1. Biology and Philosophy, 18(1), 131–168.
Huron, D. (2006). Sweet anticipation. Music and the psychology of expectation. MIT Press.
Isbilen, E. S., & Krumhansl, C. L. (2016). The color of music: Emotion-mediated associations to Bach’s
well-tempered clavier. Psychomusicology: Music, Mind, and Brain, 26(2), 149–161.
Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly, 32(127), 127–136. https://doi.
org/10.2307/2960077
Jacobson, A. J. (2013). Thought. In Keeping the world in mind: Mental representations and the sciences of the
mind. Palgrave Macmillan UK.
Jürgens, U. M., & Nikolić, D. (2012). Ideaesthesia: Conceptual processes assign similar colours to similar
shapes. Translational Neuroscience, 3(1), 22–27. https://doi.org/10.2478/s13380-012-0010-4
Kirchhoff, M. D. (2012). Extended cognition and fixed properties: Steps to a third-wave version of extended
cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11(2), 287–308. https://doi.org/10.1007/
s11097-011-9237-8
Kivy, P. (2002). Introduction to a philosophy of music. Oxford : Clarendon Press, 2002.
Curwen 17
Kohler, I. (1964). Formation and transformation of the perceptual world. Psychological Issues, 3(4,
Monograph number 12), 1–17.
Krueger, J. W. (2014). Affordances and the musically extended mind. Frontiers in Psychology, 4(JAN),
1–13. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.01003
Krueger, J. W. (2009). Enacting musical experience. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16(2–3), 98–123.
Krueger, J. W. (2011). Doing things with music. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 10(1), 1–22.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-010-9152-4
Krumhansl, C. L. (2010). Cognitive foundations of musical pitch. Oxford University Press. https://doi.
org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195148367.001.0001
Leman, M. (2008). Embodied music cognition and mediation technology. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.1525/
mp.2009.26.3.289
Leitan, N. D., & Chaffey, L. (2014). Embodied cognition and its applications: A brief review. Sensoria: A
Journal of Mind, Brain and Culture, 10(1), 1–10. https://doi.org/10.7790/sa.v10i1.384
Lerdahl, F., & Jackendoff, R. (1983). A generative theory of tonal music. MIT Press.
Loaiza, J. M. (2016). Musicking, embodiment and participatory enaction of music: Outline and key points.
Connection Science, 28(4), 410–422. https://doi.org/10.1080/09540091.2016.1236366
Madary, M. (2014). Perceptual presence without counterfactual richness. Cognitive Neuroscience, 5(2),
131–133. https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2014.907257
Maes, P. J., Leman, M., Palmer, C., & Wanderley, M. M. (2014). Action-based effects on music perception.
Frontiers in Psychology, 4(JAN), 1–14. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.01008
Marks, L. E. (1974). On associations of light and sound: The mediation of brightness, pitch, and loudness.
The American Journal of Psychology, 87(1–2), 173–188. https://doi.org/10.2307/1422011
Marks, L. E. (1975). On colored-hearing synesthesia: Cross-modal translations of sensory dimensions.
Psychological Bulletin, 82(3), 303–331. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.82.3.303
Marks, L. E. (1987). On cross-modal similarity: Auditory-visual interactions in speeded discrimination.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 13(3), 384–394. https://doi.
org/10.1037/0096-1523.13.3.384
Marks, L. E. (2004). Cross-modal interactions in speeded classification. In G. A. Calvert, C. Spence, & B. E.
Stein (Eds.), The handbook of multisensory processes (pp. 85–105). MIT Press.
Matyja, J. (2010). Embodied music cognition. Master’s thesis, The University of Edinburgh. https://doi.org/
http://hdl.handle.net/1842/5325
Meier, B. (2014). Semantic representation of synaesthesia. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum, 10, 125–134.
https://doi.org/10.12775/ths-2013-0006
Menin, D., & Schiavio, A. (2012). Rethinking musical affordances. Avant, 3(2), 202–215.
Metzinger, T. (2014). How does the brain encode epistemic reliability? Perceptual presence, phenomenal
transparency, and counterfactual richness. Cognitive Neuroscience, 5(2), 122–124. https://doi.org/1
0.1080/17588928.2014.905519
Mills, C. B., Boteler, E. H., & Larcombe, G. K. (2003). “Seeing things in my head”: A synesthete’s images for
music and notes. Perception, 32(11), 1359–1376. https://doi.org/10.1068/p5100
Mondloch, C. J., & Maurer, D. (2004). Do small white balls squeak? Pitch-object correspondences in young
children. Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience, 4(2), 133–136. https://doi.org/10.3758/
CABN.4.2.133
Mroczko-Wąsowicz, A. (2015). What can sensorimotor enactivism learn from studies on phenomenal
adaptation in atypical perceptual conditions? Open MIND, 16, 1–17. https://doi.org/10.15502/
9783958570603
Mroczko-Wąsowicz, A., & Nikolić, D. (2014). Semantic mechanisms may be responsible for develop-
ing synesthesia. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8(509), 1–13. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.
2014.00509
Mroczko-Wąsowicz, A., & Werning, M. (2012). Synesthesia, sensory-motor contingency, and semantic
emulation: How swimming style-color synesthesia challenges the traditional view of synesthesia.
Frontiers in Psychology, 3(AUG), 1–12. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00279
Myin, E. (2016). Perception as something we do. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 23(5–6), 80–104.
18 Musicae Scientiae 00(0)
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Source: The Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450. http://
www.jstor.org/stable/2183914
Neufeld, J., Sinke, C., Zedler, M., Dillo, W., Emrich, H. M., Bleich, S., & Szycik, G. R. (2012). Disinhibited
feedback as a cause of synesthesia: Evidence from a functional connectivity study on auditory-vis-
ual synesthetes. Neuropsychologia, 50(7), 1471–1477. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsycholo-
gia.2012.02.032
Nikolić, D. (2009). Is synaesthesia actually ideaesthesia? An inquiry into the nature of the phenomenon.
Proceedings of the Third International Congress on Synaesthesia, Science & Art, Granada, Spain, April
26–29.
Noë, A. (2001). Experience and the active mind. Synthese, 129(1), 41–60.
Nussbaum, C. O. (2007). The musical representation: Meaning, ontology, and emotion. MIT Press. https://doi.
org/10.1080/10848770.2014.965517
O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939–1031.
O’Regan, J. K., & Degenaar, J. (2014). Predictive processing, perceptual presence, and sensorimotor the-
ory. In Cognitive Neuroscience, 5(2), 130–131. https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2014.907256
Palmer, S. E., Langlois, T. A., & Schloss, K. B. (2016). Music-to-color associations of single-line
piano melodies in non-synesthetes. Multisensory Research, 29(1–3), 157–193. https://doi.
org/10.1163/22134808-00002486
Palmer, S. E., Schloss, K. B., Xu, Z., & Prado-León, L. R. (2013). Music-color associations are mediated
by emotion. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 110(22),
8836–8841. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1212562110
Palmer, S. E., & Schloss, K. B. (2010). An ecological valence theory of human color preference. Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 107(19), 8877–8882. https://doi.
org/10.1073/pnas.0906172107
Parise, C. V., & Spence, C. (2009). “When birds of a feather flock together”: Synesthetic correspondences
modulate audiovisual integration in non-synesthetes. PLoS ONE. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.
pone.0005664
Pasqualotto, A., & Esenkaya, T. (2016). Sensory substitution: The spatial updating of auditory scenes
“mimics” the spatial updating of visual scenes. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 10(APRIL),
1–10. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnbeh.2016.00079
Peacock, K. (1985). Synesthetic perception: Alexander Scriabin’s color hearing. Music Perception, 2(4),
483–506. https://doi.org/10.2307/40285315
Peñalba, A. A. (2011). Towards a theory of proprioception as a bodily basis for consciousness in
music. In D. Clarke & E. F. Clarke (Eds.), Music and consciousness: Philosophical, psychological, and
cultural perspectives (pp. 215–231). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:
oso/9780199553792.003.0066
Peretz, I., & Coltheart, M. (2003). Modularity of music processing. In Nature Neuroscience, 6(7), 688–691.
https://doi.org/10.1038/nn1083
Ramachandran, V. S., & Hubbard, E. M. (2001). Psychophysical investigations into the neural basis of
synaesthesia. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 268(1470), 979–983. https://doi.
org/10.1098/rspb.2000.1576
Ramstead, M. J. D., Veissière, S. P. L., & Kirmayer, L. J. (2016). Cultural affordances: Scaffolding local
worlds through shared intentionality and regimes of attention. Frontiers in Psychology, 7(1090),
1–21. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01090
Reybrouck, M. (2001). Biological roots of musical epistemology: Functional cycles, Umwelt, and enactive
listening. Semiotica, 2001(134), 599–633. https://doi.org/10.1515/semi.2001.045
Reybrouck, M. (2005). Body, mind and music: Musical semantics between experiential cognition and
cognitive economy. Trans: Transcultural Music Review, 9. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-004-
6679-4
Curwen 19
Reybrouck, M. (2006). Music cognition and the bodily approach: Musical instruments as tools for
musical semantics. Contemporary Music Review, 25(1–2), 59–68. https://doi.org/10.1080/074
94460600647451
Reybrouck, M. (2010). Music cognition and real-time listening: Denotation, cue abstraction, route
description and cognitive maps. Musicae Scientiae Special Issue, 14, 187–202.
Reybrouck, M. (2012). Musical sense-making and the concept of affordance: An ecosemiotic and experi-
ential approach. Biosemiotics, 5(3), 391–409. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-012-9144-6
Reybrouck, M. (2014). Music as environment: An ecological and biosemiotic approach. Behavioral
Sciences, 5(1), 1–26. https://doi.org/10.3390/bs5010001
Reybrouck, M. (2017). Perceptual immediacy in music listening. Multimodality and the “in time/outside
of time” dichotomy. Versus, XLVI(1), 89–104. https://doi.org/10.14649/87044
Rosenberg, G. H. (2004). On the possibility of panexperientialism. In D. J. Chalmers (Ed.) A place for
consciousness: Probing the deep structure of the natural world (pp. 91–103). Oxford University Press.
https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195168143.003.0005
Rouw, R., & Ridderinkhof, K. R. (2014). The most intriguing question in synesthesia research. Cognitive
Neuroscience, 5(2), 128–130. https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2014.906400
Rowlands, M. (2003). Externalism: Putting mind and world back together again. McGill-Queen’s University
Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzi193
Schiavio, A., & Menin, D. (2013). Embodied music cognition and mediation technology: A critical review.
Psychology of Music, 41(6), 804–814. https://doi.org/10.1177/0305735613497169
Schiavio, A., & van der Schyff, D. (2016). Beyond musical qualia. Reflecting on the concept of experience.
Psychomusicology: Music, Mind, and Brain, 26(4), 366–378. https://doi.org/10.1037/pmu0000165
Schiavio, A., van der Schyff, D., Cespedes-Guevara, J., & Reybrouck, M. (2017). Enacting musical emo-
tions. Sense-making, dynamic systems, and the embodied mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Sciences, 16(5), 785–809. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-016-9477-8
Schiavio, A., van der Schyff, D., Gande, A., & Kruse-Weber, S. (2019). Negotiating individuality and col-
lectivity in community music. A qualitative case study. Psychology of Music, 47(5), 706–721.
Schubotz, R. I. (2007). Prediction of external events with our motor system: Towards a new framework.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11(5), 211–218. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2007.02.006
Seth, A. K. (2014). A predictive processing theory of sensorimotor contingencies: Explaining the puzzle of
perceptual presence and its absence in synesthesia. Cognitive Neuroscience, 5(2), 97–118. https://doi.
org/10.1080/17588928.2013.877880
Shoemaker, S. (1994). Phenomenal character. Noûs, 28(1), 21–38.
Simner, J. (2012). Defining synaesthesia. British Journal of Psychology, 103, 1–15. https://doi.
org/10.1348/000712610X528305
Simner, J. (2007). Beyond perception: Synaesthesia as a psycholinguistic phenomenon. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 11(1), 23–29. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2006.10.010
Sloboda, J. A., & Juslin, P. N. (2010). Psychological perspectives on music and emotion. In The Oxford
handbook of music and emotion: Theory, research, applications.
Smilek, D., Dixon, M. J., Cudahy, C., & Merikle, P. M. (2001). Synaesthetic photisms influence visual
perception. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 13(7), 930–936. https://doi.org/10.1162/08989
2901753165845
Sollberger, M. (2009). Synaesthesia and the relevance of phenomenal structures in perception. Abstracta,
5(2), 139–153.
Sollberger, M. (2013). Rethinking synesthesia. Philosophical Psychology, 26(2), 171–187. https://doi.org
/10.1080/09515089.2011.627539
Spence, C. (2011). Crossmodal correspondences: A tutorial review. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics,
73(4), 971–995. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13414-010-0073-7
Stewart, L., Henson, R., Kampe, K., Walsh, V., Turner, R., & Frith, U. (2003). Brain changes after
learning to read and play music. NeuroImage, 20(1), 71–83. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1053-
8119(03)00248-9
20 Musicae Scientiae 00(0)
Stroop, J. R. (1935). Studies of interference in serial verbal reactions. Journal of Experimental Psychology,
18(6), 643–662. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0054651
Sutton, J. (2010). Exograms and interdisciplinarity: History the extended mind, and the civilizing process.
In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 189–225). MIT Press.
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge.
Tsiounta, M., Staniland, M., & Patera, M. (2013). Why is classical music yellow: A colour and sound asso-
ciation study. AIC 2013 - 12th Congress of the International Colour Association.
Tye, M. (1998). Inverted earth, swampman, and representationalism. Philosophical Perspectives, 12,
459–477.
van der Schyff, D., Schiavio, A., Walton, A., Velardo, V., & Chemero, A. (2018). Musical creativity and the
embodied mind. Music & Science, 1, 1–18. https://doi.org/10.1177/2059204318792319
van Leeuwen, T. M., Singer, W., & Nikolić, D. (2015). The merit of synesthesia for consciousness research.
Frontiers in Psychology, 6(1850), 1–7. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01850
van Leeuwen, T. M. (2014). Constructing priors in synesthesia. Cognitive Neuroscience, 5(2), 124–126.
https://doi.org/10.1080/17588928.2014.905520
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experi-
ence. In Philosophical books. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0149.1965.tb01386.x
Vernon, P. E. (1930). Synaesthesia in music. Psyche, 10, 22–39.
von Hornbostel, E. (1925). Die einheit der sinne. Melos, Zeitschrift Für Musik, 4, 290–297. https://doi.
org/10.1037/11497-008
von Uexküll, J. (1992). A stroll through the worlds of animals and men: A picture book of invisible worlds.
Semiotica. https://doi.org/10.1515/semi.1992.89.4.319
Wager, A. (1999). The extra qualia problem: Synaesthesia and representationism. Philosophical
Psychology, 12(3), 263–281. https://doi.org/10.1080/095150899105756
Walker, P., Bremner, J. G., Mason, U., Spring, J., Mattock, K., Slater, A., & Johnson, S. P. (2010).
Preverbal infants’ sensitivity to synaesthetic cross-modality correspondences. Psychological Science,
21(1), 21–25.
Ward, D. (2012). Why don’t synaesthetic colours adapt away? International Electronic Journal of Elementary
Education, 159(1), 123–138. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9693-y
Ward, J. (2013). Synesthesia. Annual Review of Psychology, 64(1), 49–75. https://doi.org/10.1146/
annurev-psych-113011-143840
Ward, J., Huckstep, B., & Tsakanikos, E. (2006). Sound-colour synaesthesia: To what extent does it use
cross-modal mechanisms common to us all? Cortex, 42(2), 264–280. https://doi.org/10.1016/
S0010-9452(08)70352-6
Ward, J., Li, R., Salih, S., & Sagiv, N. (2007). Varieties of grapheme-colour synaesthesia: A new theory
of phenomenological and behavioural differences. Consciousness and Cognition, 16(4), 913–931.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2006.09.012
Ward, J., Tsakanikos, E., & Bray, A. (2006). Synaesthesia for reading and playing musical notes. Neurocase,
12(1), 27–34. https://doi.org/10.1080/13554790500473672
Wilms, L., & Oberfeld, D. (2018). Color and emotion: Effects of hue, saturation, and brightness. Psychological
Research, 82(5), 896–914. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00426-017-0880-8
Wilson, A. D., & Golonka, S. (2013). Embodied cognition is not what you think it is. Frontiers in Psychology.
https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00058
Zbikowski, L. M. (2010). Music and analogy. In Foundations of musical grammar (pp. 32–38). Oxford
University Press.
... Synaesthesia has traditionally been described in neurology as the merging of the senses, emphasising cross-sensory co-activation upon uni-sensory perception, emphasising direct connectivity between sound and colour in the case of music (Cytowic, 2002, p. 325). Acknowledging the central role of action for perception and cognition, we recently challenged this perspective putting the potential role of sensorimotor experiences in music-colour synaesthesia to the fore (Curwen, 2020(Curwen, , 2022a. Music is known to present rich cross-modal sensorimotor associations including with action, and various sensory dimensions (Eitan & Timmers, 2010;Reybrouck, 2017). ...
... Influences of instrumental expertise on cross-modal correspondences have also been shown when comparing flautists and pianists and their mapping of pitch in horizontal space (Timmers & Li, 2016). It is proposed here that such embodied motor knowledge is likely to extend to forms of music-colour synaesthesia which may share a similar grounding in action to typical music cognition (Curwen, 2020) leading to the following predictions that are examined in this paper. ...
... The aim of this study was to investigate music-colour synaesthesia from a novel perspective of grounding in action. Complementing previous views, special emphasis was placed on bodily action and its experience, starting from the hypothesis that music-colour synaesthesia may share similar action-based properties with more typical music cognition (Curwen, 2020). We compared the contribution of the mediating factor of emotional responses to music to synaesthesia with the mediating factor of sensorimotor associations, and the effect of performing music on their principal, an unknown or an electronic, dead-pan instrument. ...
Article
Full-text available
Synaesthesia has been conceptualised as a joining of sensory experiences. Taking a holistic, embodied perspective, we investigate in this paper the role of action and emotion, testing hypotheses related to (1) changes to action-related qualities of a musical stimulus affect the resulting synaesthetic experience; (2) a comparable relationship exists between music, sensorimotor and emotional responses in synaesthetes and the general population; and (3) sensorimotor responses are more strongly associated with synaesthesia than emotion. 29 synaesthetes and 33 non-synaesthetes listened to 12 musical excerpts performed on a musical instrument they had first-hand experience playing, an instrument never played before, and a deadpan performance generated by notation software, i.e., a performance without expression. They evaluated the intensity of their experience of the music using a list of dimensions that relate to sensorimotor, emotional or synaesthetic sensations. Results demonstrated that the intensity of listeners’ responses was most strongly influenced by whether or not music is performed by a human, more so than familiarity with a particular instrument. Furthermore, our findings reveal a shared relationship between emotional and sensorimotor responses among both synaesthetes and non-synaesthetes. Yet it was sensorimotor intensity that was shown to be fundamentally associated with the intensity of the synaesthetic response. Overall, the research argues for, and gives first evidence of a key role of action in shaping the experiences of music-colour synaesthesia.
... With VMI, individuals can represent the world in their minds and are able to recall past experiences or picture themselves in the future. In contrast, synaesthetic experiences have traditionally been conceptualized as not containing any reference to the external world, landscapes, persons or episodic memories, although this view has recently been disputed (Curwen, 2020). Furthermore, synaesthetic experiences do not occur deliberately but rather automatically and involuntarily. ...
... People often remember a piece of music that accompanied important or salient events of their lives and automatically see the images of these events in their mind's eye when presented with that particular piece of music. In synaesthesia, however, memory does not seem to play a role for how synaesthetic experiences are triggered and manifested (but see again Curwen, 2020), although early accounts of synaesthesia often tried to find such associations (see Craver-Lemley & Reeves, 2013). Still, it is important to note that synaesthetes are sometimes found to have better memory than non-synaesthetes, particularly in some kinds of visual memory. ...
Chapter
Synaesthesia is a condition in which a sensory stimulus does not only activate a specific sense—such as when sound waves activate our hearing—but also concurrently, automatically, and involuntarily stimulates another modality (e.g., vision). Music-induced visual mental imagery (VMI) shares some of its features with synaesthesia, the most obvious being that stimulation in one sensory modality co-activates another. In this chapter, we compare both phenomena and, more specifically, carve out differences and commonalities between sound-colour synaesthesia and music-induced VMI. For example, some conceptual and experiential features overlap such as the location of imagined visuals (in the mind’s eye) and the fact that even if synaesthetes cannot control the onset of their synaesthetic experience, some are able to zoom in and out of imagined visuals as are individuals experiencing VMI. A historical comparison reveals that a definition of mental imagery from the 1960s would also fit a definition of synaesthesia as we understand it today. Our main argument is that mental imagery could be considered a weak form of synaesthesia, and we provide several examples and empirical evidence to support this claim. To close the chapter, we compare both phenomena with regards to emotion, memory, and creativity, and extrapolate from current evidence how synaesthetes and non-synaesthetes may behave in experiments concerned with music-induced VMI.
... Through this feeling, we can sense the music and unique emotions in the social setting. When considering music to be an abstract art, with synaesthesia, hearing and visual are similar in their fundamental and psychological characteristics (Curwen, 2022); therefore, they frequently work in concert to produce superior outcomes. Other than the most direct hearing, current psychology states that combining several sensory systems creates the cognition of music (Ilari, 2021). ...
Article
Full-text available
This survey explores the symbiotic relationship between Machine Learning (ML) and music, focusing on the transformative role of Artificial Intelligence (AI) in the musical sphere. Beginning with a historical contextualization of the intertwined trajectories of music and technology, the paper discusses the progressive use of ML in music analysis and creation. Emphasis is placed on present applications and future potential. A detailed examination of music information retrieval, automatic music transcription, music recommendation, and algorithmic composition presents state-of-the-art algorithms and their respective functionalities. The paper underscores recent advancements, including ML-assisted music production and emotion-driven music generation. The survey concludes with a prospective contemplation of future directions of ML within music, highlighting the ongoing growth, novel applications, and anticipation of deeper integration of ML across musical domains. This comprehensive study asserts the profound potential of ML to revolutionize the musical landscape and encourages further exploration and advancement in this emerging interdisciplinary field.
... Although the phenomenon is typically considered to be separate from general cognition, the shared mental processes of synaesthetes and non-synaesthetes (Simner, 2012) suggest that there may be certain similarities and differences that are a matter of degree. It is argued here that music-colour synaesthesia may share a similar grounding in action to general music cognition (Curwen, 2020). ...
... However, on the more perceptual, cognitive level, Clarke (2018) and many more researchers (Curwen, 2020;Bishop et al., 2018) argue that "there really is no such thing as passive listening". Music is a sound we listen to rather than just hear. ...
Experiment Findings
This project uses music to explore the way in which the environment affects cross-modal correspondences (CMC). This phenomenon relates to the way senses might be synchronised. Gibson’s ecological theory of perception and the subsidiary theory of 4E cognition provide the theoretical starting points for the research. The thesis builds on data collected in relation to the public research concert MusicLab 8: Synaesthesia. The thesis consists of a two-stage experiment, one representing the live performance and another a home listening context. Data collection was done using open-ended surveys, interviews and audio-visual recordings. The data is studied using qualitative methods such as content analysis and coding. The significance of the work contributes to the multisensory experience in music and HCI research. The exploration of a 4E cognition framework opens up interesting possibilities to reconsider the generative role of musical engagement. With this in mind, it may provide practitioners with a more solid, holistic foundation when planning and designing musical events where cross-modalities are more important (i.e. audiences’ participation, staging, sound array positioning, visualisation).
Chapter
Full-text available
Psychology of Music is a flourishing area of research in the Western Balkans. However, much of its findings and insights have remained relatively unknown outside the region. Psychological Perspectives on Musical Experiences and Skills features recent research from the Western Balkans, foregrounding its specific topics, methods, and influences, and bringing it into productive conversation with complementary research from Western Europe and further afield. The essays in this collection investigate the psychology of listening and performance and their relevance to music practice. Employing a range of research methodologies, they address divergent themes, from a cross-cultural understanding of aesthetic experiences and innovations to attract new audiences, to developmental perspectives on musical growth and the challenges of mastering performance skills. Authors reflect independently and collaboratively on how these psychological processes are shaped by the different traditions and geopolitical conditions inside and outside the Western Balkans. The result is a volume that emphasizes how musical experiences and practices happen not in isolation but in socio-cultural environments that contribute to their definition. This work will appeal to musicians, music educators, students, researchers, and psychologists with an interest in the psychology of music and exemplify ways forward in decolonizing academia.
Article
Duygusal aracılık hipotezi, insanların müzik-renk arasında eşleşmeler yaptıklarında müziğin duygusal çağrışımlarına uygun renklerin seçildiğini savunur. Bu araştırmada klasik batı müziği piyano eserleri ile ilgili müzik-renk ve müzik-duygu çağrışımlarının belirlenerek duygusal aracılık hipotezinin test edilmesi amaçlanmıştır. Çalışma Ordu Üniversitesi Eğitim Fakültesi’nin farklı anabilim dallarında öğrenim gören 151 öğrenci üzerinde yürütülmüştür. Çalışmada son-test tek gruplu deneme öncesi desen kullanılmıştır. Deneysel işlemde katılımcılara Mozart (Majör tonunda/hızlı tempoda), Beethoven (Minör tonunda/hızlı tempoda) ve Chopin’in (Minör tonunda/yavaş tempoda) piyano eserleri dinletilmiştir. Katılımcılar dinledikleri her bir eseri yakın üç renkle ve en yakın üç duyguyla eşleştirmişledir. Katılımcıların renkleri seçmesi için 37 renkten oluşan bir kartela kullanılmıştır. Duygular için mutlu/üzgün, huzurlu/gergin, güçlü/zayıf olmak üzere 6 duygu durumu sunulmuştur. Verilerin analizinde betimsel istatistik yöntemlerinden yararlanılmıştır. Elde edilen verilerin duygusal aracılık hipotezini desteklediği söylenebilir. Katılımcıların seçtikleri renkler ve duygu durumları dinlenen müziklerin ton ve hızlarına göre farklı dağılımlar göstermektedir. Ayrıca sonuçlar müzik-renk ve müzik-duygu çağrışımları dağılımının alanyazındaki çalışmalar ile örtüştüğünü göstermektedir.
Book
Full-text available
Drawing on perspectives from music psychology, cognitive neuroscience, philosophy, musicology, clinical psychology, and music education, Music and Mental Imagery provides a critical overview of cutting-edge research on the various types of mental imagery associated with music. The four main parts cover an introduction to the different types of mental imagery associated with music such as auditory/musical, visual, kinaesthetic, and multimodal mental imagery; a critical assessment of established and novel ways to measure mental imagery in various musical contexts; coverage of different states of consciousness, all of which are relevant for, and often associated with, mental imagery in music, and a critical overview of applications of mental imagery in health, educational, and performance settings. By both critically reviewing up-to-date scientific research and offering new empirical results, this book provides a unique overview of the different types and origins of mental imagery in musical contexts, various ways to measure them, and intriguing insights into related mental phenomena such as mind-wandering and synaesthesia. This will be of particular interest for scholars and researchers of music psychology and music education. It will also be useful for practitioners working with music in applied health and educational contexts.
Article
The importance of forming primary school children’s musical perception is justified by the introduction of the new version of the educational standard and educational programs as well as by teaching Arts on the basis of an integrative methodological approach. The purpose of the article is to scientifically ground the system of didactic influences on musical perceptual processes of younger school children focusing on the following research tasks: a) to define sensory ability as a unit of functioning of musical perception; b) to characterize the levels of pupils’ musical sensory skills formed in the mass experience of primary education; c) to disclose the specifics of variable experimental effects which differ in the degree of intensity of intermodal connections of sensory channels; d) to compare the quality dynamics of musical sensory skills formation in different versions of the pedagogical experiment. Musical sensory ability is defined as the performance of a system of auditory interiorized perceptual familiarizing and cognitive actions based on the mastered standards of music sounds and skills of applying these standards in the examination of musical phenomena. It has been found that in the mass experience of primary education pupils master musical sensory skills at elementary, intermediate and sufficient quality levels where the intermediate one prevails. The system of exercises and game tasks has been developed on the basis of intermodality with coordination of musical and phonemic auditory, musical auditory and color visual, musical auditory and spatial visual sensory processes. The system is aimed at expanding and systematizing pupils' reference ideas about music sounds as well as forming rational ways of their examining musical phenomena. The effectiveness of the introduced didactic influences has been proved: in comparison with the control group the participants of experimental groups, especially the first one, have demonstrated both the highest efficiency of distinguishing and systematizing music sounds and a variety of skills to reproduce them in singing, spatial modelling and instrumental game. The following changes have taken place in the structure of experimental groups: the respondents with an elementary level of musical perception development have not been identified, but a level gradation with intermediate, sufficient, high and consistently high levels of mastery of musical sensory processes. Key words: musical sensory ability, standards of musical sounds, methods of examination of musical sounds, game tasks, exercises, younger students.
Article
Full-text available
In this paper, we report on a qualitative study based on the "Meet4Music" (M4M) project recently developed at the University of Music and Performing Arts Graz, Austria. M4M is a low-threshold community-based program where participatory sessions dedicated to different artistic activities are freely offered to people from different social and cultural backgrounds. Our study explores how M4M promotes self-expression, creativity, social understanding, and artistic development through a number of interviews that we collected with the "facilitators"-those who help guide the heterogeneous ensemble of participants without being committed to a fixed and pre-defined teaching content. Our data focus on three aspects of M4M: "mutual collaborations," "non-verbal communication," and "sense of togetherness." Taking the "enactive" approach to cognition as a theoretical background, we argue that M4M helps to promote a sense of community that goes beyond the distinction between "individuality" and "collectivity." M4M encourages participants to meaningfully engage in collective forms of artistic activities, and develop new perspectives on their cultural identities that can play a key role for their flourishing as musical beings. In conclusion, we briefly consider possibilities for future research and practice.
Chapter
A unique interdisciplinary collection of papers and commentaries by leading researchers and rising scholars, representing the latest research on consciousness, mind, and brain. This collection offers the most comprehensive collection on consciousness, brain, and mind available. It gathers 39 original papers by leaders in the field followed by commentaries written by emerging scholars and replies by the original paper's authors. Taken together, the papers, commentaries, and replies provide a cross-section of cutting-edge research in philosophy and cognitive science. Open MIND is an experiment in both interdisciplinary and intergenerational scholarship. Open MIND grows out of the MIND Group, an independent, international body of young philosophers and scientists with a strong interest in the mind, consciousness, and cognition. The original and supporting materials are available online at open-mind.net. Authors includeMichael L. Anderson, Andreas Bartels, Tim Bayne, Christian Beyer, Ned Block, Paul M. Churchland, Andy Clark, Carl S. Craver, Holk Cruse, Daniel C. Dennett, Jérôme Dokic, Chris Eliasmith, Kathinka Evers, Vittorio Gallese, Philip Gerrans, Rick Grush, John-Dylan Haynes, Heiko Hecht, J. Allan Hobson, Jakob Hohwy, Pierre Jacob, J. Scott Jordan, Victor Lamme, Bigna Lenggenhager, Caleb Liang, Richard Menary, Albert Newen, Alva Noë, Gerard O'Brien, Elisabeth Pacherie, Jesse Prinz, Joëlle Proust, Antti Revonsuo, Adina Roskies, Jonathan Schooler, Anil K. Seth, Wolf Singer, Evan Thompson, Ursula Voss, Kenneth Williford
Book
The power of music to influence mood, create scenes, routines and occasions is widely recognised and this is reflected in a strand of social theory from Plato to Adorno that portrays music as an influence on character, social structure and action. There have, however, been few attempts to specify this power empirically and to provide theoretically grounded accounts of music's structuring properties in everyday experience. Music in Everyday Life uses a series of ethnographic studies - an aerobics class, karaoke evenings, music therapy sessions and the use of background music in the retail sector - as well as in-depth interviews to show how music is a constitutive feature of human agency. Drawing together concepts from psychology, sociology and socio-linguistics it develops a theory of music's active role in the construction of personal and social life and highlights the aesthetic dimension of social order and organisation in late modern societies.
Book
This book elaborates a series of contributions to a non-representational theory of action and perception. It is based on current theoretical developments in the enactive approach to life and mind. These enactive ideas are applied and extended to provide a theoretically rich, naturalistic account of sensorimotor meaning and agency. This account supplies non-representational extensions to the sensorimotor approach to perceptual experience based on the notion of the living body as a self-organizing dynamic system in coupling with the environment. The enactive perspective entails the use of world-involving explanations, in which processes external to an agent co-constitute mental phenomena in ways that cannot be reduced to the supply of information for internal processing. These contributions to sensorimotor theories are a dynamical-systems description of different types of sensorimotor regularities or sensorimotor contingencies, a dynamical interpretation of Piaget's theory of equilibration to ground the concept of sensorimotor mastery, and a theory of agency as organized networks of sensorimotor schemes, with its implications for sensorimotor subjectivity. New tools are provided for examining the organization, development, and operation of networks of sensorimotor schemes that compose regional activities and genres of action with their own situated norms. This permits the exploration of new explanations for the phenomenology of agency experience that are favorably contrasted with traditional computational approaches and lead to new empirical predictions. From these proposals, capabilities once beyond the reach of enactive explanations, such as the possibility of virtual actions and the adoption of socially mediated abstract perceptual attitudes, can be addressed.
Book
A biologically oriented introduction to synesthesia by the leading authority on the subject. For decades, scientists who heard about synesthesia hearing colors, tasting words, seeing colored pain just shrugged their shoulders or rolled their eyes. Now, as irrefutable evidence mounts that some healthy brains really do this, we are forced to ask how this squares with some cherished conceptions of neuroscience. These include binding, modularity, functionalism, blindsight, and consciousness. The good news is that when old theoretical structures fall, new light may flood in. Far from a mere curiosity, synesthesia illuminates a wide swath of mental life. In this classic text, Richard Cytowic quickly disposes of earlier criticisms that the phenomenon cannot be "real," demonstrating that it is indeed brain-based. Following a historical introduction, he lays out the phenomenology of synesthesia in detail and gives criteria for clinical diagnosis and an objective "test of genuineness." He reviews theories and experimental procedures to localize the plausible level of the neuraxis at which synesthesia operates. In a discussion of brain development and neural plasticity, he addresses the possible ubiquity of neonatal synesthesia, the construction of metaphor, and whether everyone is unconsciously synesthetic. In the closing chapters, Cytowic considers synesthetes' personalities, the apparent frequency of the trait among artists, and the subjective and illusory nature of what we take to be objective reality, particularly in the visual realm. The second edition has been extensively revised, reflecting the recent flood of interest in synesthesia and new knowledge of human brain function and development. More than two-thirds of the material is new. Bradford Books imprint
Article
This review provides a commentary on coloured-hearing arising on hearing music: music-colour synaesthesia. Although traditionally explained by the hyperconnectivity theory (Ramachandran & Hubbard, 2001a) and the disinhibited feedback theory (Grossenbacher & Lovelace, 2001) as a purely perceptual phenomenon, the review of eight coloured-hearing neuroimaging studies shows that it may not be assumed that these explanations are directly translatable to music-colour synaesthesia. The concept of 'ideaesthesia' (Nikolić, 2009) and the role of conceptual and semantic inducers challenge the likelihood of a single mechanism underlying the cause of synaesthesia and argue for a move away from a purely sensory to sensory explanation. Finally, music-colour synaesthesia forms a challenge for established philosophical theories and the position of synaesthesia is considered within the larger context of musical qualia.