ArticlePDF Available

Causal Inference in Law: An Epidemiological Perspective

Authors:
  • Leiden University Medical Center

Abstract and Figures

Causal inference lies at the heart of many legal questions. Yet in the context of complicated disease litigation, in particular, the causal inquiry is beset with difficulties due to gaps in scientific knowledge concerning the precise biological processes underlying such diseases. Civil courts across the globe, faced with increased litigation on such matters, struggle to adhere to their judicial fact-finding and decision-making role in the face of such scientific uncertainty. An important difficulty in drawing evidentially sound causal inferences is the binary format of the traditional legal test for factual causation, being the ‘but for’ test, which is based on the condicio-sine-qua-non principle. To the question ‘would the damage have occurred in the absence of the defendant's wrongful behaviour’ the ‘but for’ test requires a simple yes or no answer. This is increasingly deemed unsatisfactory in cases in which, given the state of science, true causation cannot possibly be determined with certainty.
Content may be subject to copyright.
EJRR1|2016175 CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiological
Perspective
BobSiegerink,WouterdenHollander,MauriceZeegersandRutgerMiddelburg*
I.Introduction
Causalinferenceliesattheheartofmanylegalques-
tions.Yetinthecontextofcomplicateddiseaseliti-
gation,inparticular,thecausalinquiryisbesetwith
difficultiesduetogapsinscientificknowledgecon-
cerningtheprecisebiologicalprocessesunderlying
suchdiseases.Civilcourtsacrosstheglobe,facedwith
increasedlitigationonsuchmatters,struggletoad-
heretotheirjudicialfact-findinganddecision-mak-
ingroleinthefaceofsuchscientificuncertainty .An
importantdifficultyindrawingevidentiallysound
causalinferencesisthebinaryformatofthetradi-
tionallegaltestforfactualcausation,beingthe‘but
for’test,whichisbasedonthecondicio-sine-qua-non
principle.1T othequestion‘wouldthedamagehave
occurredintheabsenceofthedefendant’swrongful
behaviour’the‘butfor’testrequiresasimpleyesor
noanswer.Thisisincreasinglydeemedunsatisfacto-
ryincasesinwhich,giventhestateofscience,true
causationcannotpossiblybedeterminedwithcer-
tainty.Giventhegeneralrulethattheburdenofproof
inprinciplelieswiththeclaimant,the‘butfor’test
passesontheuncertaintytotheclaimantentirely.
Suchisnotonlyfelttobeatoddswithfairness,but
isalsounsatisfactorilyfromanepidemiologicalper-
spective,giventhebinaryformatofthe‘butfor’test
ontheonehandandthefactthatmostdiseasesare
multi-causalandcannotbeascribedtoasinglefac-
toronlyontheotherhand.
Inthisarticle,wewillelaboratethisepidemiolog-
icalperspectiveandfromthatperspectivediscussthe
problemofcausalinferenceinlawingeneraland
scrutinizeonenewlegalconceptdealingwiththis
probleminparticular.Thisistheconceptoftheso-
calledproportionalliability,asacceptedbytheDutch
SupremeCourtintheNefalit-case.TheSupreme
Courtagreedwiththelowercourts,assumingliabil-
ityofemployerNefalit,inproportiontothereasoned
estimationofthechancethatthelungcancerKara-
mussufferedfromwascausedbyasbestosexposure
duringtheworkforhisemployerNefalit(55%).We
willarguethatalthoughsuchproportionalliability
adherestotheepidemiologicalconceptofmulti-
causality,andinthatrespect,isnotwithoutmerit,
epidemiologicalmeasurementsonapopulationlevel
shouldnotbetakentocalculatetheprobabilitythat
theemployers’wrongfulconducthasactuallycaused
thediseaseinanindividual.Weproposeadifferent
approachintwostages,makingproportionalliabili-
tymoretrulyproportionaltothedefendant’srelative
contributionintheknowncausalmechanismunder-
lyingthedamageinquestionand,bythat,morefair
forbothparties,eventhoughourapproachisnot
flawlesseither.
Wewillsetoutsomeimportantconceptsfromthe
fieldofepidemiologywithrespecttocausalinference
first.Athoroughunderstandingoftheseconcepts
willhelptofurtherstrengthenandinformlegalprin-
ciplesofcausation.Epidemiology ,whereprobabilis-
ticconceptsareappliedtoaddresscausalquestions
inindividuals,couldinparticularaidintheunder-
standingofmulti-causalityanditspossiblelinksto
proportionalliabilityasalegalconcept.Epidemiolo-
gystudiesthedistributionanddeterminantsofdis-
easefrequencyinhumanpopulations.Itcontrasts
withdailymedicalpracticewhichfocusesonindivid-
uals.Wewillelaboratethedifferenceinconceptsof
causalinferencebetweengroupsandindividuals,
withalinktothecondicio-sine-qua-nonprincipleand
theconceptofmulti-causality.W ewillthendiscuss
*BobSiegerink,Phd:CenterforStrokeResearch,Charité,Univeris-
titätsmedizinBerlin,Berlin,GermanyandDepartmentofClinical
Epidemiology,LeidenUniversityMedicalCenter,Leiden,the
Nehterlands;P .WouterHollander,LLMMA:InstituteforPrivate
Law,LeidenUniversity,Leiden,theNetherlands;MauriceP .
Zeegers,PhD:MaastrichtUniversity,SchoolofNutrition,Toxicol-
ogyandMetabolism&MaastrichtForensicInstitute,Maastricht,
theNetherlands;RutgerA.Middelburg,PhD:CenterforClinical
TransfusionResearch,SanquinResearch,Leiden,theNetherlands,
andDepartmentofClinicalEpidemiology,LeidenUniversity
MedicalCenter ,Leiden,theNetherlands.Theauthorswouldlike
toacknowledgeAGCastermansandRubendeGraaff(both
InstituteforPrivateLaw,LeidenUniversity)fortheirusefulcom-
ments.
1SeeforinstanceDeakin,S.,Johnston,A.,Markesinis,B.Markesi-
nisandDeakin’sT ortLaw(7thed.),Oxford:ClarendonPress
2013,pp.218-256.
EJRR1|2016 176CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
howcausationcanbequantifiedinasinglenumber
andhowthesenumberscomparetothelegalconcept
ofproportionalliabilityasacceptedintheNefalit-
case.Ultimately ,wewilltrytoreconciletheimpossi-
bilitytoknowtheexactcausalmechanismofadis-
easeinanindividualtothecondicio-sine-qua-non
principleandtheapplicationofproportionalliabili-
tytocometoafairreimbursementofdamagesin
complexdiseaselitigation.
II.CausalInferenceinMedicineand
Epidemiology
Inclinicalmedicine,doctorsareconfrontedwith
questionsofcausalityonadailybasis.Willthismed-
icaltreatmentcausethecureofapatient?Andwill
thebenefitsoutweightheside-effectscausedbythis
treatment?Forexample,whenapatientsuffersfrom
anischaemicstrokecausedbyabloodclotinthebrain
thatispreventingtheflowofoxygenatedblood,ade-
cisioncanbemadetostarttreatmenttargetedtore-
solvethebloodclotandrestorebloodflow .Thistreat-
mentiscalledthrombolysisandrestoresbloodflow
in43%oftreatedcases.2However,thrombolysisal-
socausesbleedings,whichinitselfcanalsobeacause
ofmorbidityandmortality.3Thrombolysiscanonly
beappliedinthefirst3-4,5hoursaftertheonsetof
symptoms,becauseonlyinthistimeperiodtheben-
efitsoftreatment,whichdeclinesovertime,out-
weighthenegativeconsequencesofthistreatment
onapopulationlevel.
Treatingapatientisnotrestrictedtoaddressing
theacutesymptomsofacertaincause,butalsoin-
cludestheremovalofpossiblecausestopreventa
possiblerecurrenceofthedisease.Forexample,the
physicianconfrontedwithapatientsufferingfrom
anischaemicstrokewillnotonlyapplythromboly-
sis,butwillalsotargetthesmokinghabitandthein-
creasedcholesterollevelsofthatparticularpatient
topreventanothercaseofischaemicstrokeinthe
longrun.Thedecisiontotargettheseriskfactorsis
basedonstudiesthatonapopulationlevelthesefac-
torsareacauseofthedisease.T argetingtheserisk
factorsinanindividualisthereforethoughttolow-
ertheriskofrecurrence.4,5Buthowcanthephysi-
cian,basedonepidemiologicalstudies,becertain
thatthesmokinghabitandhighcholesterollevels
werecausalinthemechanismleadingtotheis-
chaemicstrokeinthisparticularpatient?Theunset-
tlingansweristhatheisnotcertain,neithercanhe
everbe.
III.TheCounterfactualIdeal
Theoretically,wecanonlybecertainonthecausal
natureofariskfactorifweobservetheoutcomewhen
thepatientisexposedtothisriskfactorandcompare
thattothesituationwhenwegobackintime,and
seewhathappensifthepatientisunexposed,butall
otherfactorsarekeptconstant.6Becausethishypo-
theticalsituationiscontrarytofact,thisconceptis
sometimesreferredtoasthecounterfactualorpoten-
tialoutcomemodel.7,8Ifwecouldgobackintime,
andmanipulateonlyonecertainfactorwecouldde-
termineineachindividualpatientwhetheranindi-
vidualriskfactorwasindeedacauseoftheobserved
disease.
Thiscounterfactualmodeliscomparabletothe
condicio-sine-qua-non-testinlaw.Theriskthatde-
scribesthisrelationshipbetweenexposureanddis-
easeforoneindividualisbinary,being1(forthedis-
easeiscausedbytheexposure)or0(forthedisease
isnotcausedbytheexposure).However,sincethe
counterfactualoutcomecannotbeobserved,wecan-
notdeterminethecausalmechanisminanindivid-
ual.Thecounterfactualidealcanbeapproached,
though,inthecomparisonofdifferentpopulations
undercertainconditions.Forexample,iftwogroups
aresimilarexceptforthepresenceoftheriskfactor
ofinterest,adifferenceindiseasefrequencycanbe
ascribedtothesoledifferencebetweenthesegroups,
2Joung,H.Rha,&Saver,L.J.,‘TheImpactofRecanalizationon
IschaemicStrokeOutcome:aMeta-Analysis’,Stroke38(2007),
pp.967–73.
3Lansberg,M.G.etal., AntithromboticandThrombolyticTherapy
forIschaemicStroke:AntithromboticTherapyandPreventionof
Thrombosis,9thed:AmericanCollegeofChestPhysiciansEvi-
dence-BasedClinicalPracticeGuidelines’,Chest141(2012),
e601S–36S.
4GoyaWannamethee,S.etal.,‘SmokingCessationandtheRiskof
StrokeinMiddle-AgedMen’,JAMA274(1995),pp.155–60.
5Milionis,H.J.etal.,‘StatinTherapyafterFirstStrokeReduces10-
yearStrokeRecurrenceandImprovesSurvival’,Neurology72
(2009),pp.1816-22.
6Formorebackgroundreadingonthetheoryofcausation,please
referto:Pearl,J.,Causality:Models,Reasoning,andInference,
CambridgeUniversityPress,2000;2ndedition,2009.
7Rothman,K.J.etal.,‘CausationandCausalInferenceinEpidemi-
ology’,Am.J.PublicHealth95(2005)Suppl.1,pp.S144-50.
8Rothman,K.J.,Greenland,S.,Lash,T .L.,ModernEpidemiology
(thirdrevisededition),LippincottWilliams&Wilkins2008.
EJRR1|2016177 CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
beingtheriskfactorofinterest.Thiscomparisondoes
notallowtoestablishthecausalmechanismwithin
anindividual.However,thesegroupcomparisonsdo
allowustoestimatethecausalrelationshipbetween
theexposureandtheoutcometobequantifiedin
termsofprobability.
IV .FromOneCausetotheconceptof
Multi-causality
Beforewedescribehowcausalrelationshipscanbe
quantified,wefirsthavetofocusonthedefinitionof
acausalmechanism.Often,thecauseinacausal
mechanismisthoughttobeasinglefactorinacause-
consequencesequence.However,aconsequencecan
havemultiplecauses:severalfactors,asacombina-
tion,causeaneffect.Thisconceptisknownasmul-
ti-causalityandisimportantinepidemiological
thinkingoncausality ,foritprovidesawaytothink
aboutcausalmechanismsinsteadofsinglecause-con-
sequencesequences.Toavoidconfusion,multi-
causalityshouldbedistinguishedfromthesituation
inwhichasinglefactor,suchassmoking,cancause
differentdiseases.
Inepidemiologicaltheory ,theconceptofmulti-
causalityhasgainedgroundsinceitwasformalized
byK.J.Rothmanin1976.9Theconceptdistinguishes
anddescribestheimplicationsofnecessary,suffi-
cientandcomponentcausesandisfurtherexplained
withtheuseoffigure1.
Lettherebethreepossiblecausalmechanismsthat
leadtoacertaindisease.Figure1depictsthesethree
causalmechanismsasthreesufficientcauses,allcom-
prisingmultiplecomponentcauses.Inthisexample
weassumethatthesethreesufficientmechanisms
aretheonlythreepossiblecausalmechanismsthat
leadtoanevent,whichcanbeadisease,injuryor
anythingsimilar.Thefrequencyofthediseasenor-
mallyisadirectfunctionofthefrequencyofacom-
binationofthedifferentcomponentcauses.Weal-
soassumethatallcomponentcausesareequally
presentinthepopulationandthatthepresenceof
eachcomponentcauseisindependentfromtheoth-
ers(i.e.noconfoundingcauses,seebelow).
Importanttonoteisthatsometimescomponent
causesarepresentinallsufficientcauses,making
themnecessarycomponentcauses(Ainourexam-
ple).Intheory ,removalofanecessarycomponent
causefromthepopulationwillleadtocompleteerad-
icationofthedisease.Itisnotnecessaryforallsuf-
ficientcausestohaveanequalnumberofcomponent
causes,norisitneededtonameallcomponentcaus-
esindetail.Acomponentcausecanevenbeunknown
(oftendepictedas‘U’,asisdoneinthemiddlesuffi-
cientcauseinfigure1).
Acomponentcausecanbepresentlongbeforethe
sufficientcauseiscompleted.Forexample,agenet-
icvariationinacertaingeneispresentfrombefore
birth,butothercomponentcausesareneededtocom-
pleteasufficientcause.Thecompletionofasuffi-
cientcauseequalsthebiologiconsetofthedisease,
whichisnotnecessarilythetimeofdiagnosis.These
conceptsareillustratedinanexamplewheregenet-
icvariationsarepartofthecausalmechanismlead-
ingtoischaemicstroke:geneticvariationsinthe
APOEgeneareknowntocausebloodcholesterollev-
elstorise.Thesegeneticvariationsarepresentfrom
beforebirth,butthissmallincreaseinbloodcholes-
terolaloneisinitselfinsufficientandadditionalcar-
9Rothman,K.J.,‘Causes’,Am.J.Epidemiol104(1976),pp,
587-92.
Figure1-Threesufficientcauses
EJRR1|2016 178CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
diovascularriskfactorsareneededinordertocause
anischaemicstroke.Togetherwithsuchfactors(e.g.
smoking),increasedbloodcholesterolmightresult
inanatheroscleroticplaque.Sometimes,these
plaquesruptureandathrombusisformed,which
subsequentlyblockstheflowofbloodtothebrain.
Also,themomentofdiagnosisoftheischaemicstroke
oreventhefirstsymptomscanbehourslaterthan
theactualblockageofthecerebralartery.
Sincecomponentcausesaccumulateovertime,the
incidenceofmanydiseasesrisessharplywithage.
Thetimebetweenthefirstpresenceofacomponent
causeandthecompletionofthesufficientcauseis
referredtoastheinductiontime.Inourexample,the
alphabeticalorderofthecomponentsreferstothe
orderinwhichtheyoccur.Itisimportanttonotethat
thelengthoftheinductiondoesnotnecessarilyre-
ducetheimportanceofaparticularcomponentcause.
Thecomponentcausethatcompletesthesufficient
causehasaninductiontimeofzeroandistherefore
easilyidentifiedasacause.Componentcauseswith
littletonoinductiontimeareinlayman’stermsfor
thatreasonsometimeserroneouslyreferredtoasthe
causeofthedisease.
Nonetheless,theorderofcomponentcausesisof
importance:apersonwhoisonlyexposedtocompo-
nentcausesAandBhasnosufficientcause.Subse-
quentexposuretothetwocomponentscausesCand
Dwillcompleteasufficientcause.Whenthisperson
isnotexposedtoCorD,hewillnotdevelopthedis-
easeatthatparticularpointintime.However,when
thissamepersonatalatermomentisexposedtocom-
ponentcauseF,asufficientcausehasformedandthe
personstilldevelopsthedisease,albeitsomewhatlat-
erintime.
Thesufficientcausemodeladherestothecounter-
factualideal.Whenweconsiderthesufficientcause
1depictedinfigure1,wecanseethatA,B,CandD
arethecomponentcausesforthisparticularsuffi-
cientcause.Ifwethinkofthecounterfactualsitua-
tionthatthisparticularindividualwasnotexposed
tocomponentcauseAandallotherthingsequal,this
diseasewouldnothaveoccurred.Thesamegoesfor
thecommoncausesB,CandD.Wecanevenbroad-
enourviewandseewhathappenswiththewhole
population:ifnecessarycomponentcauseAwereto
beeliminatedfromthepopulation,100%ofallsuf-
ficientcausescannotbeformedanymoreandthedis-
easewouldhavebeeneradicatedfromthepopula-
tion.
Wecanalsoseethat2/3ofthesufficientcauses
comprisecomponentcauseD.RemovingDfromour
populationwouldhowevernotnecessarilyreduce
thenumberofdiseasedinourpopulationbythis
samenumber.Afterall,personswithsufficientcause
1arenowonlyexposedtocomponentcauseA,Band
Candthereforestillatriskofdevelopingthedisease
forexamplewhenexposedtocomponentcauseFlat-
erintime.Ifintheextremecaseeachindividualex-
posedtocomponentcauseDisalso,atsomelater
time,exposedtocomponentcauseF,sufficientcause
threewouldbeformedinhalfofthepeopleforwhom
thesufficientcauseotherwiseincludedD(halfsince
halfofthosepeoplesufficientcause2isnotex-
posedtocomponentcauseB).Inthisexamplewe
canseethatonly1/3ofthediseasedcanbeattrib-
utedtocomponentcauseD(knownastheattribut-
ablefraction),eventhoughitispresentin2/3suffi-
cientcauses(knownastheaetiologicfraction).
Pleasenoticethatthisobservationcanbeatodds
withtheinterpretationofthecondicio-sine-qua-non-
testthatisappliedindifferentjudicialsystems,for
thisprincipledoesnotnecessarilyprovidetheright
mind-settohandlethepossibilitythatadifferent
causalmechanismleadingtothesameconsequence
couldarise.
Althoughneitherthecounterfactualnorthesuffi-
cientcauseofanindividualcanbeobserved,thiscon-
ceptualframeworkdoesprovideusefulinsightinthe
ideaofcausationandmulti-causality.
V .StudyDesigns
Thecounterfactualidealcanbeapproachedinsev-
eralstudydesigns,aslongasseveralassumptions
aremade.Althoughuncommon,sometimesthe
counterfactualisundisputedanddirectcausalinfer-
encescanbemade.Forexample,certainformsof
braininjurycaninducemassiveswellingofthebrain
whichleadstoincreasedintracranialpressureand
subsequentlythedeathofalmostallpatientswith
thiscondition.10Anyinterventionthatreducesthe
intracranialpressureandpreventsdeathinallpa-
tients,forexamplebydrillingaholeintheskullso
thattheswollenbraincanextentoutward,willbere-
10Zuurbier ,S.M.etal.,‘DecompressiveHemicraniectomyin
SevereCerebralVenousThrombosis:aProspectiveCaseSeries’,
Journalof.Neurology259(2012),pp.1099-105.
EJRR1|2016179 CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
gardedascausalinthepreventionofdeathofthese
patients.
Therewillhardlybeanydiscussionaboutthe
causalclaimmadeinsuchascenario,sowewillnot
focusonthistypeofstudies.Wewillfocusonsce-
narioswhicharemuchmoreunclear.Sincemost,if
notall,diseasescanberegardedasmulti-causal,the
compositionofsufficientcauseofindividualpatients
cannotbeknown,makingitimpossibletodetermine
causalmechanismsinindividuals.Wecanonlyquan-
tifytheeffectofcomponentcausesinprobabilistic
terms.11Oftenthisisdonebycomparingtheriskof
thosewhoareexposedtothefactorofinteresttothe
riskofthosewhoarenotexposed,forexampleby
theratiooftherespectiveprobabilitiesofdisease.
Thisratioisalsoknownastherelativerisk.
Thestudydesignthatapproachesthecounterfac-
tualidealascloseaspossibleisthecrossovertrial.
Inthisdesignpatientsareassignedtotwosubse-
quenttreatmentstrategies,ofwhichonecanbea
placebotreatment,andtheoutcomeofthepatient
(e.g.bloodpressure)ismeasureddirectlyaftereach
treatment(e.g.antihypertensivemedicationvs.
placebo).Thiswaythesamepatientisobservedboth
withandwithouttheexposure,asprescribedbythe
counterfactualideal.Itisimportantthatthepatient
hastoreturntohis‘originalstate’frombeforehis
firsttreatment,beforereceivinghissecondtreat-
ment.Otherwisesuchacomparisonwillnotresult
incorrectcausalinference.Thisproblemcanbe
counteredbytweakingtheexperimentaldesign,for
exampleintroducingawash-outperiodbetweenthe
twotreatmentperiods,butalsoseverelylimitsthe
applicabilityofthisdesign.12Anotherstudydesign
thatapproachesthecounterfactualidealisthecase-
crossoverdesign.Inthisdesigntheexposurestatus
ofapatientisdeterminedontwomoments:acutely
beforetheonsetofthediseaseandinacontrolperi-
odsometimebeforetheonsetofthedisease.Ifthe
exposureofinterestisindeedacauseofthedisease
itislikelytobemorepresentjustbeforetheacute
onsetofthediseasethaninthecontrolperiod.This
canonlybedonewhentheinformationneededto
determineexposurestatuscanbereliablyobtained
afterthepatientsareidentified.Anotherdisadvan-
tageofthisdesignisthatitcanonlyinvestigatetrig-
gersofdiseaseswithanacuteonset,whicharethe
componentcauseswithnoorlittleinductiontime.
Anexampleofthisstudydesignisastudythatin-
vestigatedpotentialtriggersofsubarachnoidbleed-
ing,whichshowedthatshortbutdistinctiveexpo-
suressuchascoffeeconsumptionandsexualinter-
coursecanindeedbethetriggerofthistypeofhaem-
orrhagicstroke.13,14
Althoughthesetwostudydesignsapproachthe
counterfactualideal,thesecanonlybeappliedtosit-
uationsinwhichanexposureisvariablewithinone
personandtheeffectiseitheracuteorreversible.
Manyresearchquestionsdonotadheretothesecon-
ditions(e.g.geneticexposuresarenotvariablewith-
inaperson,cancerhasnoacuteonsetanddeathis
notreversible)thusleavingoneorbothofthese
crossoverdesignsinappropriate.Otherstudydesigns
donotsufferfromtheserestrictions,butneedmore
assumptionstojustifycausalinferences.Random-
izedtrialscanbeusedtostudytheeffectofdifferent
treatmentstrategiesbyapplyingthetreatmentsto
differentgroupsofpersonsandobservewhether
thereisadifferenceinthefrequencyoftheoutcome
ofinterest.Thisstudydesignreliesheavilyontheas-
sumptionthatthetwogroupswouldhaveasimilar
riskoftheoutcomeifthesewereleftuntreated,asit-
uationinwhichthecounterfactualidealclearlyres-
onates.Thissituationiscreatedbytherandomiza-
tionprinciple:thelikelihoodofreceivingacertain
treatmentisindependentfromothercausesofthe
outcome.Randomizedtrialsareapowerfultoolin
thediscoveryofintendedeffectsofmodifiableexpo-
sures,beingtreatmentstargetedatreducingtherisk
oftheoutcome,asisthecaseinaclinicaltrialthat
comparestwotreatmentstopreventcardiovascular
disease.Also,datafromrandomizedtrialscanpro-
videmoreinsightinthesideeffectsofnewdrugs.
However,theuseofrandomizedtrialstoidentify
causesofadiseaseisinmanycasesethicallyunde-
sirable.Additionally ,manyexposurescannotbe
modified(e.g.geneticvariations)andthereforea
largeproportionofcausalquestionscannotbean-
sweredbyexperimentalstudies.Insuchcasesobser-
vationalstudiesmustbeappliedtoestimatethe
causalrelationshipbetweentheexposureandthe
11Rothman,K.J.,Greenland,S.,Lash,T.L.,ModernEpidemiology
(thirdrevisededition),LippincottWilliams&Wilkins2008.
12Senn,S.,Crossover-trialsinclinicalresearch,Wiley1993.
13Maclure,M.etal,‘Shouldweuseacase-crossoverdesign?’,
AnnualReviewofPublicHealth(2000),pp.193-221.
14Vlak,M.H.M.etal.,‘TriggerFactorsandTheirAttributableRisk
forRuptureofIntracranialAneurysms:aCase-crossoverStudy’,
Stroke42(2011),pp.1878–82.
EJRR1|2016 180CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
outcomeofinterest.Theobservationalstudydesigns
canbecategorisedintwogroups,beingthecohort
studiesandthecase-controlstudy,eachwiththeir
ownmerits.Likeexperimentalstudydesigns,obser-
vationalstudydesignsrelyoncertainassumptions
toallowestimationofthecausaleffect.Thesede-
signs,theirmeritsandpitfallsaswellastheassump-
tionsneededforcausalinferencearetoocomplexto
describehereindetailandarediscussedatgreat
lengthinseveraltextbooksandwelimitourselvesto
ageneraldescriptionoftheconceptofbias.15
VI.Bias
Onemajorassumptionincausalinferencefromepi-
demiologicalstudiesistheabsenceofbias,whichin-
troducesanincomparabilityintothestudy.W ewill
discussthreemajorformsofbiaswithregardtothe
causalrelationshipbetweensmokingandlungcan-
cer.Thefirstisinformationbiasinwhichdataare
collectedincorrectlyandbiastheresultinaparticu-
lardirection.Forexamplewhendataaboutsmoking
habitsarecollectedinadifferentfashion(forexam-
plemorerigorouslyorthroughdifferenttypesof
questionnaires)inlungcancerpatientsthanin
healthysubjects.Acomparisonofthosedatawould
notonlyreflecttheeffectofsmokingontheriskof
developinglungcancer,butundesirablyalsoreflects
thedifferencesindatacollection.Anotherformof
biasisselectionbiasinwhichstudyparticipationis
dependentontheexposureand/ortheoutcome.For
example,whenlungcancerpatientsarecomparedto
agroupofhealthyvolunteerswhoarenotreflective
ofthepopulationfromwhichthelungcancerpa-
tientsarose,butareinstead(indirectly)selectedfor
beingnon-smokers,resultsofthecomparisonof
thesegroupswouldnotreflecttheeffectofsmoking
ontheriskofdevelopinglungcancer.Itwillunde-
sirablybereflectiveofthedifferencesbetweenthe
twoseparatepopulationsfromwhichthepatients
andcontrolgroupweresampled.Athirdformofbias
isconfoundingbiasinwhichtheincreaseinriskof
theexposureofinterestismixedwiththeriskofan-
othercauseofthediseaseofinterest.Thishappens
whentheexposureofinterestsharesacommoncause
withtheoutcomeofinterest,asisdiscussedinfig-
ure2.
15Rothman,K.J.,Greenland,S.,Lash,T.L.,ModernEpidemiology
(thirdrevisededition),LippincottWilliams&Wilkins2008.
Figure2
EJRR1|2016181 CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
Thisfigurecontainsfourgraphsthatdescribethe
causalrelationshipbetweensmokingandlungcan-
cer,butalsoincludeathirdfactor.Thesegraphsare
examplesoffourdifferentclassesoffactorsthatare
statisticallyassociatedtotheriskoflungcancer,
whichcouldimpedecausalinference.Itisimportant
todifferentiatebetweentheseclassesbecausethena-
tureofsuchavariabledetermineswhetheritshould
betakenintoaccounttoensurevalidestimationof
thecausaleffectbetweensmokingandlungcancer
development.
A|Acommoncauseoftheexposureandoutcome
isconsideredaconfounder.Thisexampleshowsthat
menaremorelikelytosmoke,butalsothatmenin-
trinsicallyhaveahigherriskoflungcancer.The
smoking-lungcancerassociationissaidtobecon-
foundedand‘malesex’needstobetakenintoaccount
inordertoensurevalidcausalinference.Confound-
ingcanbeasourceoffallacious‘posthocergopropter
hoc’conclusions.
B|Anothercauseoflungcancer,e.g.ageneticpre-
disposition,whichisindependentofsmokingisnot
consideredaconfounder.Therefore,theadditional
riskofsomeindividualswillnotconfoundthesmok-
ing-lungcancerassociation.
C|Causesoftheexposurewhicharenotacauseof
theoutcomeotherthanviatheexposureofinterest
arenotconfounders.Inthisexample,anaddiction
pronepersonalityisacausalfactorinthedevelop-
mentofasmokinghabit.However,itisnotacause
oflungcancerbyitself.Thesecausesarepartofthe
causalmechanismoflungcancer,butdonotcon-
foundthesmoking-lungcancerassociation.
D|Adirectconsequenceoftheexposurewhichul-
timatelyleadstotheoutcomeofinterestisnotcon-
sideredtobeaconfounder.Inthisexample,smok-
ingincreasestheriskoflungcancerbecauseitcaus-
esdamagetolungtissue.Thisintermediatecauseis
saidtolie‘inthecausalpathway’.Therefore,thereis
noconfoundingpresent.
Thepresenceofconfoundingcanleadtoafalla-
cious‘posthocergopropterhoc’conclusion:even
whenanexposureofinterestisnotacauseofthedis-
ease,itisstillpossiblethatexposedindividualsare
morelikelytodevelopthedisease.Thisincreasein
risk,whichisinfactaspuriousrelationship,canthen
beexplainedbyothercausesofdiseasethatarefound
moreoftenamongstexposedindividualsleadingto
confoundingbias.Whenconfoundingisnottakenin-
toaccountthediseasedevelopsmoreofteninthose
withacertainexposure,itseemsasiftheexposure
isinfactthecause.Ifsourcesofconfoundingare
identifiedbeforethestartofthestudy ,confounding
canbeaddressedandaccountedforinthestudyde-
signorstatisticalanalyses.16However,whencon-
foundingisnotsufficientlyaddressed,itspresence
mayleadtoerroneouscausalstatements.
Allstudydesignsaresubjecttobias,butdifferent
studydesignssufferfromdifferentformsofbiasand
toadifferentextent.Therearesomeclassifications
thatcategorisestudiesaccordingtotheir‘levelofev-
idence’.17Thispracticecanbeuseful,aslongasthis
practicedoesnotprecludecriticalthinking.Forex-
ample,manyresearchersbelievethattherandomized
clinicaltrialistheonlystudydesigninwhichcausal
relationshipscanbestudied.Thisishoweveranout-
datedpointofview,sinceobservationalstudiescan
beascredibleasrandomizedtrialsundercertaincon-
ditions.18Therandomizedcontrolledtrialstudyde-
signremainshowevertheunbeatablegoldenstan-
dardifonewantstostudythebeneficialeffectsofa
newdrug.Therandomizationprocedurebreaksthe
linkbetweentheprescriptionofthenewdrugand
theprobabilityoftheoutcome.Observationalstud-
iesdonotbreakthislink,whichcouldseverelybias
theresults(i.e.confoundingbyindication).Howev-
er,thesebiasesarelessseverewhenonewantsto
studydrugsideeffectsoridentifycausesofadisease.
Thismakesobservationalstudiessuitabletoinvesti-
gatecausalmechanisms,incasebiasescanbeac-
countedfor.
VII.CausalInference:MorethanOne
Study
Socanwedrawdefiniteconclusionsontheproba-
bilisticrelationshipofacauseanditsconsequence
basedonasinglestudy?Itisadvisabletousemulti-
plestudiesforseveralreasons.First,itispossiblethat
16Formorebackgroundinformationonthestatisticalapproaches
thatcanbeappliedtoinvestigatecausalrelationships,please
refertoBerzuini,C.,Dawid,S.,Bernadinell,L.,(editors),Causali-
ty:StatisticalPerspectivesandApplications ’ ,(Wiley,2012)
17SeeforexamplethewebsiteoftheCentreforevidencebased
medicinewiththetitle‘Levelsofevidence’,<http://www .cebm
.net/index.aspx?o=1025>(21July2014).
18Vandenbroucke,J.P.,‘Whenareobservationalstudiesascredible
asrandomisedtrials?’,Lancet363(2004),pp.1728–31.
EJRR1|2016 182CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
justbychancetheeffectestimatefromasinglestudy
isverydifferentfromthetrueeffect.Bycombining
theresultofmultiplestudiesintoaso-called‘meta-
analysis’thestatisticalpowerincreasesandtheef-
fectestimateismoreprecise.Second,allstudiesare
subjecttobiasandsomestudiesaremoreproneto
particularformsofbias.Therefore,alotcanbe
learnedfromcomparingtheresultsofstudieswith
differentstudydesigns.Butevenintheunlikelysce-
nariothatbiasisthoughttobecompletelyabsentand
thattheeffectofthepresumedcauseismeasured
withsufficientstatisticalpower,moreinformationis
neededtodrawfirminferencesonthecausalrela-
tionshipbetweentheexposureandoutcomeofinter-
est.Thisknowledgemustfocusontheplausibilityof
theproposedcausalclaim.Areotherplausiblefac-
torspresentthatcouldexplainourresults?Isthepro-
posedmechanisminlinewithourcurrentknowl-
edge?
Therefore,partofcausalinferenceinmedicinelies
outsidethereachofasinglestudyorevenoutside
therealmofepidemiology.Thisconceptisinline
withthecrosswordanalogyofsciencephilosopher
SusanHaack.19,20Severalfactorsareofimportance
whenfillingoutacrossword:theclue,thealready
enteredanswers,thepossibilityofalternativean-
swers,andthelevelofcompletionofthecrossword.
Anewanswercannotbeatoddswithalreadyexist-
ingentrieswithoutrethinkingpreviousanswers.
Causalinferencecanberegardedinasimilarfash-
ion:onesingleresultisnotlikelytojustifycausal
claims.Butseveralresults,fromvariousresearch
groups,backedbypreviousknowledge,notlikelyto
beexplainedbyalternativescenariossuchasbiasor
chancecouldjustifycautiouscausalclaimsaboutthe
quantificationofthecauseandeffectestimateofin-
terest.
Somehavetriedtocodifyallaspectsthatneedto
beconsideredbeforearelationcanberegardedas
causal.Forexample,SirAustinBradfordHillnoted
nineaspectsofcausalitythatmightbeconsidered
whentalkingaboutcausalityinepidemiology .21Hill
notedinhisoriginaladdresstotheRoyalSocietythat
thesefactorsarenottobeconsideredascriteria.On-
lyone,‘temporality’,isatruecriterion,thatisthat
thecausemustbepresentoractbeforeitseffect.The
othereightaspectsarenotcriteriaandcanberegard-
edasaspectsthatmightbediscussedwhenonewants
tocometoacausaljudgement.However,despitethe
warningsbyHillandothers,someresearchershave
misusedthesenineconditionsasachecklistfor
causalclaims.Suchpracticeprohibitsacriticalap-
praisalofallevidenceandshouldbeabandoned.Un-
fortunately,thisnotthecase.22,23
VIII.CausalClaimsinLaw
Itiseasytoseethatitisnotstraightforwardtotrans-
ferepidemiologicalknowledgeobtainedfrompopu-
lationstoindividuallegalclaims.Wewilldiscuss
thesedifficultiesbydiscussingtheDutchNefalit-
case.24Inthiscase,Karamusattributedhisdisease
tohislong-termexposuretoasbestos,sufferedinthe
factorywhereheworked,forwhichheheldhisfor-
meremployerNefalitliable.Nefalithadfailedtotake
thenecessaryprecautionarymeasuresandwasthere-
fore,intheviewofKaramus,tocompensatealldam-
agesrelatedtohisdisease.Nefalitresponded,how-
ever,thatthelungcancercouldalsohavebeencaused
byKaramus’longtimesmokinghabit,byotherfac-
torsoracombinationofthese.Itisindeedknown
fromepidemiologicalevidenceaswellaslaboratory
studiesthatbothexposuresareknowntoincrease
theriskofthisparticulartypeoflungcancer,often
incombinationwithotherscauses.Thereforeitis
notpossible,giventhestateofscienceandtheidea
ofmulti-causality,todeterminethesinglecauseof
Karamus’diseaseandhisdamages.Lowercourts,
withtheconsentoftheDutchSupremeCourt,ac-
knowledgedthatapplyingthecondicio-sine-qua-non-
testwouldmeanpassingonthisuncertaintytoKara-
musentirely,ashisclaimwouldhavetobedismissed
onthegroundthatcausationcouldnotbeestab-
19Haack,S.,ManifestoofaPassionateModerate,Chicago:Univer-
sityofChicagoPress1998.
20Vandenbroucke,J.P., AlternativeMedicine:A“MirrorImage”for
ScientificReasoninginConventionalMedicine’,AnnalsofInter-
nalMedicine135(2001),pp.507-511.
21Hillreferstotheseninepointsas‘aspectsof…(an)association’
thatshouldbeconsideredbeforedecidingontheinterpretationof
causation.Thesepointsare:strength,consistency,specificity,
temporality,biologicalgradient,plausibility,coherence,experi-
mentandanalogy.SeealsoHill,A.B.,‘TheEnvironmentand
Disease:AssociationorCausation?’,ProceedingsoftheRoyal
SocietyofMedicine(1965),pp.295-300.
22Morabia,A.,‘OntheOriginofHill’ sCausalCriteria’,Epidemiolo-
gy2(1991),pp.367-369.
23Phillips,C.V .etal.,‘TheMissedLessonsofSirAustinBradford
Hill’,EpidemiologyPerspectivesandInnovations1(2004),p.3.
24HogeRaad31March2006,ECLI:NL:HR:2006:AU6092,reach-
ablethrough<http://uitspraken.rechtspraak.nl/#ljn/AU6092>(in
Dutch;9December2014).
EJRR1|2016183 CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
lished.Thereforethesecourtsappliedtheconceptof
so-calledproportionalliability,rulingthatNefalit
wasliableforonlyaproportionofKaramus’dam-
ages,basedonexperttestimonyandepidemiologi-
calpublicationsaboutthechancesthathislungcan-
cerwasindeedcausedbytheasbestosexposure
(55%).25
Itwasamatteroffairness,theSupremeCourtin-
dicated,nottopassonthisuncertaintytothe
claimantentirely ,bydismissingKaramus’claimal-
together,giventhatinthiscasethechancethatthe
lungcancerwasindeedcausedbyasbestos,wasnei-
therverysmallnorverylarge.Insuchcases,courts
areallowedtomakeareasonedestimate,ifnecessary
onthebasisofexperttestimony .Itisimportantto
notethattheSupremeCourtjustifiedtheapplication
ofthisso-called‘proportionalliability’inpartbystat-
ingthattherewasuncertaintywhetheritwastheas-
bestosexposure,theclaimant’ssmokinghabits,ge-
neticsorotheradditionalexternalfactorsthatcaused
thelungcancer,aloneorincombination.
Wewilldiscusslaterwhetherthe55%-rulingis
justifiedinlightofthismotivationgivenbytheDutch
SupremeCourt.First,itisimportanttounderstand
howthe55%cameabout.Thisnumberwasobtained
bycalculatingtheattributablefraction,asdiscussed
insectionIV ,whichisdefinedasthefractionofcas-
esinwhichtheexposureofinterestisacomponent
causeofthesufficientcauseleadingtothedisease.
Asecondrelatedmeasureistheprobabilityofcausa-
tion,whichisadirectfunctionofanotherfraction:
theaetiologicalfraction.Thisfractiondescribesthe
probabilitythatthefactorofinterestisacomponent
causeinasufficientcause,inacaserandomlydrawn
fromapatientpopulation.Intheory ,theseconcepts
canbeveryhelpfulinliabilitycases,becausethey
provideawaytolinkapopulationmeasuretoasin-
glecase.However,wehavealreadyarguedthatthe
aetiologicalfractioncannotbeobserveddirectlyor
calculatedwithoutstrongadditionalassumptions,
whichcannotbeempiricallyverified.
However,theattributablefraction,thefractionof
thediseasesamongtheexposedthatcanbeascribed
totheexposureofinterest,onthecontrarycanbe
calculatedinacohortstudyas(seeEquation1),where
therelativeriskistheriskoftheoutcomeamongst
theexposeddividedbytheriskintheunexposed.
Oncecalculatedtheattributablefractionshoulddi-
rectlybeinterpretedastheaetiologicalfraction:the
aetiologicfractionisalwayssimilarorhigher,but
neverlowerthantheattributablefraction.26
Somepointshavetobeemphasizedtoensurecor-
rectinterpretationofthesenumbers.Boththeaetio-
logicandattributablefractionarecalculatedforcom-
ponentcauses,whichimpliesthatthesumofallfrac-
tionsdonotnecessarilyequal,butislikelytobehigh-
erthan100%,duetothemulti-causalnatureofcom-
plexdiseases.Infact,thesumofthesefractionscould
bebothhigherorlower,andbasicallydependslarge-
lyonthenumberofcausesthathavebeenidentified
foraspecificdisease.Therefore,thesefractions
shouldneverbeinterpretedastheprobabilitythata
certainfactorofinterestisthesinglecauseofthedis-
easeinaparticularcase,sincethereisnosuchthing
asasinglecause.Somehaveproposedthiswrongde-
finitioninordertousetheeffectsizeasameasure
ofcausality .Inlinewiththiswrongnotionarelative
riskgreaterthan2,whichequalsanattributablefrac-
tionof>50%(AF=(2-1)/2),hassometimeseven
beenabusedascutoffpointfor‘causality-provenvs.
25HogeRaad31maart2006,ECLI:NL:HR:2006:AU6092.See
also,morerecently,HogeRaad14december2012,
ECLI:NL:HR:2012:BX8349.Onthesecases,seeCastermans,A.G.
&Hollander ,P.W.den,‘Omgaanmetonzekerheid.Proportionele
aansprakelijkheid,artikel6:101BWendeleervandekanss-
chade’,NTBR2013,pp.185-195(inDutch).
26Thesituationunderwhichtheattributablefractioncanbeinter -
pretedastheaetiologicalfractionaredescribedinKennethJ.
Rothman,SanderGreenland,T imothyL.Lash.ModernEpidemi-
ology,thirdrevisededition,(LippincottWilliams&Wilkins,
2008)
EJRR1|2016 184CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
causalitynotproven’.27Thismisuseoftheattribut-
ablefractionprecludesanyformofcriticalthinking
aboutthecausalmechanismunderlyingeventsand
shouldbeabandoned.
Anotherpossiblemisinterpretationofboththeae-
tiologicandattributablefractionliesinthedirect
translationoftheattributablefractiontothepropor-
tionoftheclaimsthatshouldbereimbursed,with
theideathatonaverageboththeplaintiffaswellas
thedefendantsaretreatedsatisfactorily.However ,by
couplingtheattributablefractiontotheproportion
thatshouldbereimbursed,thecourtforgetsacrucial
characteristicoftheattributablerisk,whichagainis
thatthesumoftheattributablefractioncanexceed
100%.Incontrast,thesharesinproportionalliabili-
tyinoneparticularcaseshouldnot.Consideragain
ourexampleinfigure1,inwhich100%ofcases(3/3)
wascausedbyA’and66%ofallcases(2/3)was
‘causedbyB’.Ifaclaimantwiththisparticulardis-
easewouldtheoreticallyholdboth A’and‘B’liable
inseparatelawsuits,thisapproachwouldyieldato-
talof166%oftheclaimedsum,whichdoesnotad-
heretothefairnessprinciple.Themisconceptionthat
theaetiologicorattributablefractioncandirectlybe
appliedasanallocationinstrumentforproportional
liabilityasalegalconceptthusliesinerroneouslyap-
plyingapopulationmeasuretoanindividualproba-
bilityestimation.Thiscanalsobeappreciatedwhen
wecomparetheformulafortheaetiologicalfraction
(seeEquation2)totheconceptthatusesproportion-
alliabilitytoadheretothefairnessprinciple(see
Equation3).
Sowhattothinkthenoftheuseofproportional
liabilityinthecaseofNefalitandKaramus?During
thehearings,anexpertmotivatedthattherewasa
125%increaseinriskduetoasbestosexposure,which
correspondstoarelativeriskof2.25andanattribut-
ablefractionof55%(theAF=(2.25-1)/2.25=55.56%,
thelowercourtmentions55%initsruling).The
DutchSupremeCourtmotivatedtheuseofpropor-
tionalliability ,includingthisfigure,andtherebyim-
plicitlytheuseoftheattributablefractioninitsrul-
ingwiththeobservationthattherewasuncertainty
whetherasbestoswasindeedthecause.However,the
courtwentfurtherbycouplingthisnumberasthe
fractionofthedamagesthatemployerNefalitshould
reimburseasamatteroffairness.Atfirstglance,the
motivationoftheSupremeCourtsoundsfair,butwe
havealreadyshowedinourexampleabovethatlink-
ingtheattributablefractiontothefractionthat
shouldbereimbursedbythedefendantdoesnotal-
waysadheretothematteroffairness.Therefore,the
rulingbytheSupremeCourtcouldleadtounfairre-
imbursementsand,perhapsunknowinglyandun-
wantedly,setsaprecedentwithpossiblyunwanted
consequences.
WewillcontinuewiththeNefalit-casetoillustrate
this.Letsaythatbesidessmokingandasbestosexpo-
suretheclaimantwasalsosubjectedtoanotherrisk
factor‘X’duetonegligenceofanotheremployer.
Again,itisuncertainwhetherindeeditwas‘X’that
wasthecauseofhisdisease.Letusstatethat‘X’in-
creasestheriskoflungcancerby178%andtherefore
hasanattributablefractionof64%(i.e.arelativerisk
=2.78andAF=(2.78-1)/2.78).Followingthesame
lineofreasoningasthecourtdidwhenitcametoas-
bestosexposure(i.e.thereisuncertaintyaboutthe
causalclaimandthereforeonlyapartoftheclaim
shouldbereimbursed),intheory64%oftheclaim
27Greenland,S.,‘RelationofProbabilityofCausationtoRelative
RiskandDoublingDose:aMethodologicErrorThatHasBecome
aSocialProblem’,AmericanJournalofPublicHealth89(1999),
pp.1166–9.
EJRR1|2016185 CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
shouldbereimbursedbythesecondemployer.This
makesthereceivedamounttotheoreticallysuper-
sedetheoriginalclaim.
Whenacourtwantstodirectlycoupletheaetio-
logicalfactiontoa‘fair’distributionofthedamages
thecourthastoknowthetrueunderlyingcausal
mechanismofeachindividualliabilityclaim.Ina
sense,thecourthastobecertainaboutallthecom-
ponentcausesthatmakeupthesufficientcausein
thisparticularindividual.However,theexactsuffi-
cientcausecannotbeobservedinanindividualcase,
anuncertaintythattheSupremeCourtusedtomo-
tivateitsruling.So,whenacourtiswillingtoassume
proportionalliability ,itshouldbewellmotivated.
Evenmore,whenacourtisuncertainwhetherthe
defendantisindeedresponsibleforoneofthecom-
ponentcausesinthisparticularcase,itisevenmore
difficulttounderstandhowitcanbejustifiedtolink
theproportionalliabilitytotheaetiologicalfraction,
itsderivativesandapproximations.
Basedonthesepoints,itisalreadyhighlyques-
tionablewhetherproportionalliabilityshouldbedi-
rectlylinkedtoepidemiologicalpopulationmeasures
suchastheunobservableaetiologicalfractionorthe
attributablefractionasitsderivative.Butthemost
importantobjectionofthisdirectcouplingisthefact
thatthesumofthesenumbersarenotrestrictedto,
andisevenverylikelytosupersede,100%.Wedosee
themeritofproportionalliability ,especiallygiven
themulti-causalnatureofmostdiseases,andwe
wouldthereforeliketoproposeadifferentapproach
thatlinksthesetwoconceptswithouttheaforemen-
tionedproblems.Forthis,wewillusethecomponent
causeconceptincombinationwiththecondicio-sine-
qua-non-principleinatwo-stagesapproach.
IX.ProportionalLiabilityinTwoStages
Theapproachwewouldliketoproposeisatwo-
stages-approach,linkingtheconceptsofproportion-
alliabilityandmulti-causality .Thisapproachmakes
useofthecondicio-sine-qua-non-testandthuspro-
videsequalweightstoallpossiblecauses.Thisisin
linewiththenotionofboththesufficientcausemod-
elandthecounterfactualmodel.
Duringthefirststageofthisapproach,thecourt
hastodecidewhetherthedefendant’swrongfulbe-
haviourindeedplayedaroleinthecausalmecha-
nism.Thecourtshouldmotivateitsdecisiononevi-
denceandexpertwitnesses.Oncedecidedwhether
thedefendantindeedplayedaroleinthecausalmech-
anism(i.e.isresponsibleforoneormorecomponent
causesofthesufficientcause),thedefendantcanad-
vocateproportionalliabilityinthesecondstage.The
defendantdoessobyprovidingalistofpossibleoth-
ercomponentcausestothecourt,ofwhichithasto
determinewhetherthesealsoplayedaroleinthis
particularcase.Thisway ,thecourtcandeterminethe
fractionofcomponentcausespartofthepresumed
sufficientcause,thataretheresponsibilityofthede-
fendant.Thisfractioncouldbeusedtodetermine
proportionalliability(cf.equation2).Forexample,
whentherearesixpossiblecauses,ofwhichfour
mightplayaroleinthecaseathandandoneofthese
fourcanbeattributedtothedefendant,thedefen-
dantwouldhavetocompensate25%oftheclaim.
Thistwo-stages-approachisnotflawless,forit
couldoverestimatethenumberofcomponentcaus-
esthatplayaroleinthesufficientcauseandthere-
byunderestimatetheliabilityofthedefendant.Al-
so,newcomponentcausescouldbeidentifiedafter
thecourthasdecided.Ifthiswouldleadtoanewli-
abilityclaimwithanewdefendant,ourexample
couldbesummarisedasfollows.Withthediscovery
ofanewcausethatisrelevanttoourcase,thereare
nowsevencomponentcausesofwhichfiveareap-
plicabletothecaseathand.Ifoneofthosecompo-
nentcausescanbeattributedtotheseconddefen-
dant,thenhewouldhavetopay20%oftheoriginal
claim.Thisway ,thetotalsumofallclaims,40%in
ourexample,willneversupersede100%oftheorig-
inalclaim,butapproachesthisnumberasymptoti-
cally.Receivingthis20%oftheseconddefendant
shouldbeconditionalonthereimbursementofthe
excess5%thatwaspaidbythefirstdefendant.
Anotherproblematicaspectofthistwo-stage-
methodisthatallpossiblecomponentcausesarecon-
sideredequallyimportantandaregiventhesame
weightinthisapproach.Althoughthisisinlinewith
thecomponentcausemodel,itdoesresultinsome
practicalproblems.Forexample,therecanbenumer-
ouscomponentcauseswhichmightbelistedthatin-
deedarecomponentcausesinthemoststrictdefin-
ition,butlackrelevancewhenitcomestoproportion-
alliability(e.g.onehastohavelungsinordertode-
veloplungcancer).Also,evidencemightsuggestthat
somecomponentcausescannotbediscarded,butare
certainlylessrelevanttothecaseinquestionthen
others.Inthatcase,aweightedapproachcouldbe
EJRR1|2016 186CausalInferenceinLaw:AnEpidemiologicalPerspective
considered.Allinall,itisuptothecourt,withthe
aidofexpertsandscientists,torulewhichpossible
componentcausesarerelevanttothequestionofli-
ability.
X.Conclusion
Causalityresearchinepidemiologyislargelyembed-
dedintheconceptofthecounterfactualmodel,which
resemblesthelegalcondicio-sine-qua-non-test.Byde-
finition,thecounterfactualcannotbeobservedand
thesufficientcauseinasinglepersoncannotbe
known.Therefore,itisnotpossibletoknowtheex-
actcausalmechanismleadingtothediseaseinanin-
dividualperson.However,epidemiologicalstudies
canbeusedtostudytheeffectofapresumedcause
ontheriskofdiseaseatthepopulationlevel.Results
frommultipleandreliablestudies,consideringmul-
ti-causality,combinedwithpriorbiologicalknowl-
edgecanresultincautiouscausalclaims.Although
theaetiologicfractioncanneverbeknown,theat-
tributablefractioncanbecalculatedandgivesinsight
intherelationbetweencauseandeffectonagroup
level.
Thispopulationmeasurecannotdirectlybeap-
pliedtoindividualcaseswithoutrelyingon
untestableassumptions(seeBox1).
Linkingtheconceptofproportionalliabilitytothe
attributablefractionisthuswrong.Inaddition,the
sumoftheattributableaetiologicalfractionsislike-
lytoexceed100%,whichcouldleadtounfairreim-
bursements.Wehavethereforeproposedatwo-stage-
approachforacourttoapplytheconceptofpropor-
tionalliability ,byfirstdecidingonliabilityandthen
ontheproportion.Thislinksproportionalliabilityto
theconceptofmulti-causality ,whilealsoandfirstly
adheringtothecondicio-sine-qua-non-test.Inthis
process,thecourtshouldconsultscientistandex-
perts,butultimately,thedecisionremainsanorma-
tivejudgmentforthecourtitselftomake.
Box1-Takehomemessages
-Causalclaimsshouldalwaysbeconsideredinthelightofmulti-causality:thereisneverthe
cause,butasetofcomponentcausesthatmakeupasufficientcause.
-Causalityinepidemiologyreliesonmorethanjustonestudy:differentstudies,theeffectof
possiblebiasesandadditionalevidence,evenoutsidetherealmofepidemiology,shouldall
betakenintoaccountbeforecautiousclaimscanbemade.
-Theaetiologicalfractionandtheprobabilityofcausationasitsderivativearebothepidemio-
logicalmeasureswhichcannotbecalculated.Theycanonlybeapproached,undercertainas-
sumptions,bycalculatingtheattributablefraction.
-Linkingtheconceptofproportionalliabilitytotheattributablefractioniswrong,especially
becausethesumofallattributablefractionsislikelytoexceed100%.
... For example, would the driver in a head-to-head car collision have died at that moment if he had worn a seatbelt? In assessing counterfactuals, we need to specify sufficiently-well defined versions of the potential outcome and its counterfactual contrast, given the circumstances, by taking all available knowledge/ evidence into account [26][27][28][29][30] and assuming a ceteris paribus condition, i.e. all other things or conditions being equal [31]. Because a counterfactual condition cannot be observed directly, and counterfactual outcomes cannot be determined in an individual, we need a substitute from which we can infer it. ...
... The probability of causation (PC) expresses the amount of causation attributable to a component cause, which is equal to the reduction of the risk of the condition in a population that is not exposed to the cause. It should never be interpreted as the probability that a putative cause is the single cause of the effect in an individual [30]. There are dissenting opinions about the bounds of the PC in specific causation. ...
... A primary obstacle in drawing causal inferences is the binary format of the legal question for causation. It is based on the 'but-for' test and demands a simple yes or no answer [30]. ...
Article
Full-text available
The primary aim of forensic medical analysis is to provide legal factfinders with evidence regarding the causal relationship between an alleged action and a harmful outcome. Despite existing guides and manuals, the approach to formulating opinions on medicolegal causal inference used by forensic medical practitioners, and how the strength of the opinion is quantified, is mostly lacking in an evidence-based or systematically reproducible framework. In the present review, we discuss the literature describing existing methods of causal inference in forensic medicine, especially in relation to the formulation of expert opinions in legal proceedings, and their strengths and limitations. Causal inference in forensic medicine is unique and different from the process of establishing a diagnosis in clinical medicine. Because of a lack of tangibility inherent in causal analysis, even the term “cause” can have inconsistent meaning when used by different practitioners examining the same evidence. Currently, there exists no universally applied systematic methodology for formulating and assessing causality in forensic medical expert opinions. Existing approaches to causation in forensic medicine generally fall into two categories: intuitive and probabilistic. The propriety of each approach depends on the individual facts of an investigated injury, disease, or death. We opine that in most forensic medical settings, probabilistic causation is the most suitable for use and readily applicable. Forensic medical practitioners need, however, be aware of the appropriate approach to causation for different types of cases with varying degrees of complexity.
... The concepts in this paper are applicable to estimation tasks in general, but we focus on the specific task of estimating a causal effect, which is of the upmost importance for policy making [38], the development of medical treatments [49], the evaluation of evidence within legal frameworks [45,59], and others. A canonical characterization of the problem of causal inference from observational data is depicted in the Directed Acyclic Graphs (DAGs) shown in Figs. 2, and we provide an overview of causal inference in this section. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Parameter estimation in the empirical fields is usually undertaken using parametric models, and such models are convenient because they readily facilitate statistical inference. Unfortunately, they are unlikely to have a sufficiently flexible functional form to be able to adequately model real-world phenomena, and their usage may therefore result in biased estimates and invalid inference. Unfortunately, whilst non-parametric machine learning models may provide the needed flexibility to adapt to the complexity of real-world phenomena, they do not readily facilitate statistical inference, and may still exhibit residual bias. We explore the potential for semiparametric theory (in particular, the Influence Function) to be used to improve neural networks and machine learning algorithms in terms of (a) improving initial estimates without needing more data (b) increasing the robustness of our models, and (c) yielding confidence intervals for statistical inference. We propose a new neural network method MultiNet, which seeks the flexibility and diversity of an ensemble using a single architecture. Results on causal inference tasks indicate that MultiNet yields better performance than other approaches, and that all considered methods are amenable to improvement from semiparametric techniques under certain conditions. In other words, with these techniques we show that we can improve existing neural networks for `free', without needing more data, and without needing to retrain them. Finally, we provide the expression for deriving influence functions for estimands from a general graph, and the code to do so automatically.
... The estimation of the causal effects of interventions or treatments on outcomes is of the upmost importance across a range of decision making processes, such as policy making [1], advertisement [2], the development of medical treatments [3], and the evaluation of evidence within legal frameworks [4], [5]. Despite the common preference for Randomized Controlled Trial (RCT) data over observational data, this preference is not always justified. ...
... To the best of our knowledge, we are not aware of a well-established theory in psychology or social science which does not incorporate at least some level of consideration for cause and effect, and, if there is one, we would question its utility in so far as it can help us understand the world. Models which sufficiently align with the structure of reality may facilitate causal inference, even with observational (as opposed to experimental) data (Glymour, 2001;Grosz et al., 2020;Pearl, 2009;Pearl et al., 2016) and have wide ranging applications including advertisement (Bottou et al., 2013), policy making (Kreif & DiazOrdaz, 2019), the evaluation of evidence within legal frameworks (Pearl, 2009;Siegerink et al., 2016), and the development of medical treatments (Petersen et al., 2017;van der Laan & Rose, 2011). There are a number of challenges associated with adopting a causal approach. ...
Article
Full-text available
The replicability crisis has drawn attention to numerous weaknesses in psychology and social science research practice. In this work we focus on three issues that cannot be addressed with replication alone, and which deserve more attention: Functional misspecification, structural misspecification, and unreliable interpretation of results. We demonstrate a number of possible consequences via simulation, and provide recommendations for researchers to improve their research practice. Psychologists and social scientists should engage with these areas of analytical and statistical improvement, as they have the potential to seriously hinder scientific progress. Every research question and hypothesis may present its own unique challenges, and it is only through an awareness and understanding of varied statistical methods for predictive and causal modeling, that researchers will have the tools with which to appropriately address them. (PsycInfo Database Record (c) 2021 APA, all rights reserved).
... Causal understanding has been described as 'part of the bedrock of intelligence' [145], and is one of the fundamental goals of science [11,70,183,[241][242][243]. It is important for a broad range of applications, including policy making [136], medical imaging [30], advertisement [22], the development of medical treatments [189], the evaluation of evidence within legal frameworks [183,218], social science [82,96,246], biology [235], and many others. It is also a burgeoning topic in machine learning and artificial intelligence [17,66,76,144,210,247,255], where it has been argued that a consideration for causality is crucial for reasoning about the world. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Causal reasoning is a crucial part of science and human intelligence. In order to discover causal relationships from data, we need structure discovery methods. We provide a review of background theory and a survey of methods for structure discovery. We primarily focus on modern, continuous optimization methods, and provide reference to further resources such as benchmark datasets and software packages. Finally, we discuss the assumptive leap required to take us from structure to causality.
... The estimation of the causal effects of interventions or treatments on outcomes is of the upmost importance across a range of decision making processes, such as policy making (Kreif & DiazOrdaz, 2019), advertisement (Bottou et al., 2013), the development of medical treatments (Petersen et al., 2017), and the evaluation of evidence within legal frameworks (Pearl, 2009;Siegerink et al., 2016). Despite the common preference for Randomized Controlled Trial (RCT) data over observational data, this preference is not always justified. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Undertaking causal inference with observational data is extremely useful across a wide range of domains including the development of medical treatments, advertisements and marketing, and policy making. There are two main challenges associated with undertaking causal inference using observational data: treatment assignment heterogeneity (i.e., differences between the treated and untreated groups), and an absence of counterfactual data (i.e. not knowing what would have happened if an individual who did get treatment, were instead to have not been treated). We address these two challenges by combining structured inference and targeted learning. To our knowledge, Targeted Variational AutoEncoder (TVAE) is the first method to incorporate targeted learning into deep latent variable models. Results demonstrate competitive and state of the art performance.
... To the best of our knowledge, we are not aware of a well-established theory in psychology or social science which does not incorporate at least some level of consideration for cause and effect, and, if there is one, we would question its utility in so far as it can help us understand the world. Models which sufficiently align with the structure of reality may facilitate causal inference, even with observational (as opposed to experimental) data (Glymour, 2001;Pearl, 2009;Pearl et al., 2016;Grosz et al., 2020) and have wide ranging applications including advertisement (Bottou et al., 2013), policy making (Kreif & DiazOrdaz, 2019), the evaluation of evidence within legal frameworks (Pearl, 2009;Siegerink et al., 2016), and the development of medical treatments (Petersen et al., 2017;van der Laan & Rose, 2011). There are a number of challenges associated with adopting a causal approach. ...
Preprint
The replicability crisis has drawn attention to numerous weaknesses in psychology and social science research practice. In this work we focus on three issues that deserve more attention: The use of models with limited functional form, the use of misspecified causal models, and unreliable interpretation of results. We demonstrate a number of possible consequences via simulation, and provide recommendations for researchers to improve their research practice. We believe it is extremely important to encourage psychologists and social scientists to engage with the debate surrounding areas of possible analytical and statistical improvements, particularly given that these shortfalls have the potential to seriously hinder scientific progress. Every research question and hypothesis may present its own unique challenges, and it is only through an awareness and understanding of varied statistical methods for predictive and causal modeling, that researchers will have the tools with which to appropriately address them.
... I therefore have a rich experience in getting optimal results from big data and have repeatedly shown important new relationships, [12,27] which were later confirmed. [13,15,32,33] For the current project I intend to use data, collected through my existing network both within the Netherlands and internationally, to analyze with our innovative new methodologies. These data are already present at my group and include data from the TOPPS trial, [34,35] R-fact study, [30,36] and MEGA study. ...
Research Proposal
Full-text available
The major problem in clinical medicine today is the lack of tailoring of treatments to individual patients’ needs. Treatments can be safe and effective in one patient and not in another (i.e. effect modification). Effect modification causes two major problems in clinical practice and clinical research. 1. Commonly used treatments are useless for most patients who receive those treatments 2. Large negative effects of treatments can easily go undetected for decades Solving these two closely related problems would help provide the evidence required to give every patient the individually tailored, safest, and most effective treatment possible (i.e. precision medicine). One of the reasons why the required evidence base is still lacking, is the complete absence of statistical methods specifically optimized to use routinely collected clinical data to derive quantitative estimates of effect modification. Therefore, even the largest clinical datasets can provide only very limited insight into which risk factors determine whether a patient will benefit from a treatment, or not. I therefore aim to: Develop, verify, and apply innovative new epidemiological methodologies to quantify effect modification and thereby help provide a valid evidence base for truly individualised and safe precision medicine I will complete this project in two parallel research lines. Two PhD students will each develop their own set of methodologies. 1. PhD student 1 will focus on individualising the quantitative estimation of treatment effectiveness by quantifying effect modification at the individual level. 2. PhD student 2 will focus on increasing the sensitivity of the detection of causal contributions to adverse events by quantifying effect modification in the most sensitive way possible. Both PhD students will verify the validity and precision of their methods both in normal simulation studies and in plasmode simulations. All verified new methods will be applied to real data, currently available in my group.
Article
Causal reasoning is a crucial part of science and human intelligence. In order to discover causal relationships from data, we need structure discovery methods. We provide a review of background theory and a survey of methods for structure discovery. We primarily focus on modern, continuous optimization methods, and provide reference to further resources such as benchmark datasets and software packages. Finally, we discuss the assumptive leap required to take us from structure to causality.
Article
Full-text available
This article provides recommendations on the use of antithrombotic therapy in patients with stroke or transient ischemic attack (TIA). We generated treatment recommendations (Grade 1) and suggestions (Grade 2) based on high (A), moderate (B), and low (C) quality evidence. In patients with acute ischemic stroke, we recommend IV recombinant tissue plasminogen activator (r-tPA) if treatment can be initiated within 3 h (Grade 1A) or 4.5 h (Grade 2C) of symptom onset; we suggest intraarterial r-tPA in patients ineligible for IV tPA if treatment can be initiated within 6 h (Grade 2C); we suggest against the use of mechanical thrombectomy (Grade 2C) although carefully selected patients may choose this intervention; and we recommend early aspirin therapy at a dose of 160 to 325 mg (Grade 1A). In patients with acute stroke and restricted mobility, we suggest the use of prophylactic-dose heparin or intermittent pneumatic compression devices (Grade 2B) and suggest against the use of elastic compression stockings (Grade 2B). In patients with a history of noncardioembolic ischemic stroke or TIA, we recommend long-term treatment with aspirin (75-100 mg once daily), clopidogrel (75 mg once daily), aspirin/extended release dipyridamole (25 mg/200 mg bid), or cilostazol (100 mg bid) over no antiplatelet therapy (Grade 1A), oral anticoagulants (Grade 1B), the combination of clopidogrel plus aspirin (Grade 1B), or triflusal (Grade 2B). Of the recommended antiplatelet regimens, we suggest clopidogrel or aspirin/extended-release dipyridamole over aspirin (Grade 2B) or cilostazol (Grade 2C). In patients with a history of stroke or TIA and atrial fibrillation we recommend oral anticoagulation over no antithrombotic therapy, aspirin, and combination therapy with aspirin and clopidogrel (Grade 1B). These recommendations can help clinicians make evidence-based treatment decisions with their patients who have had strokes.
Article
Full-text available
Small retrospective case series suggest that decompressive hemicraniectomy can be life saving in patients with cerebral venous thrombosis (CVT) and impending brain herniation. Prospective studies of consecutive cases are lacking. Thus, a single centre, prospective study was performed. In 2006 we adapted our protocol for CVT treatment to perform acute decompressive hemicraniectomy in patients with impending herniation, in whom the prognosis with conservative treatment was considered infaust. We included all consecutive patients with CVT between 2006 and 2010 who underwent hemicraniectomy. Outcome was assessed at 12 months with the modified Rankin Scale (mRS). Ten patients (8 women) with a median age of 41 years (range 26-52 years) were included. Before surgery 5 patients had GCS < 9, 9 patients had normal pupils, 1 patient had a unilaterally fixed and dilated pupil. All patients except one had space-occupying intracranial hemorrhagic infarcts. The median preoperative midline shift was 9 mm (range 3-14 mm). Unilateral hemicraniectomy was performed in 9 patients and bilateral hemicraniectomy in one. Two patients died from progressive cerebral edema and expansion of the hemorrhagic infarcts. Five patients recovered without disability at 12 months (mRS 0-1). Two patients had some residual handicap (one minor, mRS 2; one moderate, mRS 3). One patient was severely handicapped (mRS 5). Our prospective data show that decompressive hemicraniectomy in the most severe cases of cerebral venous thrombosis was probably life saving in 8/10 patients, with a good clinical outcome in six. In 2 patients death was caused by enlarging hemorrhagic infarcts.
Article
Book
Causality: Statistical Perspectives and Applications presents a wide-ranging collection of seminal contributions by renowned experts in the field, providing a thorough treatment of all aspects of statistical causality. It covers the various formalisms in current use, methods for applying them to specific problems, and the special requirements of a range of examples from medicine, biology and economics to political science. Provides a clear account and comparison of formal languages, concepts and models for statistical causality. Addresses examples from medicine, biology, economics and political science to aid the reader's understanding. Is authored by leading experts in their field. Is written in an accessible style. Postgraduates, professional statisticians and researchers in academia and industry will benefit from this book.
Article
Objective. —To examine the effects of giving up smoking, years since quitting smoking and the quantity of cigarettes smoked, and primary pipe or cigar smoking on the risk of stroke.Design, Subjects, and Setting. —A prospective study of cardiovascular disease and its risk factors in 7735 men aged 40 through 59 years drawn at random from the age-sex registers of one general practice in each of 24 British towns from 1978 through 1980 (the British Regional Heart Study).Main Outcome Measure. —Incidence of fatal and nonfatal major stroke events (strokes) during an average follow-up period of 12.75 years.Results. —During the 12.75 years of follow-up, there were 167 major stroke events (43 fatal and 124 nonfatal) in the 7264 men with no recall of previous ischemic heart disease or stroke. After full adjustment for other risk factors, current smokers had a nearly fourfold relative risk (RR) of stroke compared with never smokers (RR, 3.7; 95% confidence interval [CI], 2.0 to 6.9). Ex—cigarette smokers showed lower risk than current smokers but showed excess risk compared with never smokers (RR, 1.7; 95% CI, 0.9 to 3.3; P=.11); those who switched to pipe or cigar smoking showed a significantly increased risk (RR, 3.3; 95% CI, 1.6 to 7.1) similar to that of current light smokers. Primary pipe or cigar smokers also showed increased risk (RR, 2.2; 95% CI, 0.6 to 8.0), but the number of subjects involved was small. The benefit of giving up smoking completely was seen within 5 years of quitting, with no further consistent decline in risk thereafter, but this was dependent on the amount of tobacco smoked. Light smokers (<20 cigarettes/d) reverted to the risk level of those who had never smoked. Heavy smokers retained a more than twofold risk compared with never smokers (RR, 2.2; 95% CI, 1.1 to 4.3). The age-adjusted RR of stroke in those who quit smoking during the first 5 years of follow-up (recent quitters) was reduced compared with continuing smokers (RR, 1.8; 95% CI, 0.7 to 4.6 vs RR, 4.3; 95% CI, 2.1 to 8.8). The benefit of quitting smoking was observed in both normotensive and hypertensive men, but the absolute benefit was greater in hypertensive subjects.Conclusion. —Smoking cessation is associated with a considerable and rapid benefit in decreasing the risk of stroke, particularly in light smokers (<20 cigarettes/d); a complete loss of risk is not seen in heavy smokers. Switching to pipe or cigar smoking confers little benefit, emphasizing the need for complete cessation of smoking. The absolute benefit of quitting smoking on risk of stroke is most marked in hypertensive subjects.(JAMA. 1995;274:155-160)
Article
The rules to assess causation formulated by the eighteenth century Scottish philosopher David Hume are compared to Sir Austin Bradford Hill's causal criteria. The strength of the analogy between Hume's rules and Hill's causal criteria suggests that, irrespective of whether Hume's work was known to Hill or Hill's predecessors, Hume's thinking expresses a point of view still widely shared by contemporary epidemiologists. The lack of systematic experimental proof to causal inferences in epidemiology may explain the analogy of Hume's and Hill's, as opposed to Popper's, logic.
Article
Little is known about activities that trigger rupture of an intracranial aneurysm. Knowledge on what triggers aneurysmal rupture increases insight into the pathophysiology and facilitates development of prevention strategies. We therefore aimed to identify and quantify trigger factors for aneurysmal rupture and to gain insight into the pathophysiology. During a 3-year period, 250 patients with aneurysmal subarachnoid hemorrhage completed a structured questionnaire regarding exposure to 30 potential trigger factors in the period soon before subarachnoid hemorrhage (hazard period) and for usual frequency and intensity of exposure. We assessed relative risks (RR) of rupture after exposure to triggers with the case-crossover design comparing exposure in the hazard period with the usual frequency of exposure. Additionally, we calculated population-attributable risks. Eight triggers increased the risk for subarachnoid hemorrhage: coffee consumption (RR, 1.7; 95% CI, 1.2-2.4), cola consumption (RR, 3.4; 95% CI,1.5-7.9), anger (RR, 6.3; 95% CI, 4.6-25), startling (RR, 23.3; 95% CI, 4.2-128), straining for defecation (RR, 7.3; 95% CI, 2.9-19), sexual intercourse (RR, 11.2; 95% CI, 5.3-24), nose blowing (RR, 2.4; 95% CI, 1.3-4.5), and vigorous physical exercise (RR, 2.4; 95% CI, 1.2-4.2). The highest population-attributable risks were found for coffee consumption (10.6%) and vigorous physical exercise (7.9%). We identified and quantified 8 trigger factors for aneurysmal rupture. All triggers induce a sudden and short increase in blood pressure, which seems a possible common cause for aneurysmal rupture. Some triggers are modifiable, and further studies should assess whether reduction of exposure to these factors or measures preventing sudden increase in blood pressure decrease the risk of rupture in patients known to have an intracranial aneurysm.
Article
No abstract available.